Philosophy (from Greek: φιλοσοφία, philosophia, ‘love of wisdom’)[1][2] is the systematized study of general and fundamental questions, such as those about existence, reason, knowledge, values, mind, and language.[3][4][5][6][7] Some sources claim the term was coined by Pythagoras (c. 570 – c. 495 BCE),[8][9] although this theory is disputed by some.[10][11][12] Philosophical methods include questioning, critical discussion, rational argument, and systematic presentation.[13][14][i]
Historically, philosophy encompassed all bodies of knowledge and a practitioner was known as a philosopher.[15] «Natural philosophy», which began as a discipline in ancient India and Ancient Greece, encompasses astronomy, medicine, and physics.[16][17] For example, Isaac Newton’s 1687 Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy later became classified as a book of physics. In the 19th century, the growth of modern research universities led academic philosophy and other disciplines to professionalize and specialize.[18][19] Since then, various areas of investigation that were traditionally part of philosophy have become separate academic disciplines, and namely the social sciences such as psychology, sociology, linguistics, and economics.
Today, major subfields of academic philosophy include metaphysics, which is concerned with the fundamental nature of existence and reality; epistemology, which studies the nature of knowledge and belief; ethics, which is concerned with moral value; and logic, which studies the rules of inference that allow one to derive conclusions from true premises.[20][21] Other notable subfields include philosophy of religion, philosophy of science, political philosophy, aesthetics, philosophy of language, and philosophy of mind.
Definitions
There is wide agreement that philosophy (from the ancient Greek φίλος, phílos: «love»; and σοφία, sophía: «wisdom»)[22] is characterized by various general features: it is a form of rational inquiry, it aims to be systematic, and it tends to critically reflect on its own methods and presuppositions.[23][24][25] But approaches that go beyond such vague characterizations to give a more interesting or profound definition are usually controversial.[24][25] Often, they are only accepted by theorists belonging to a certain philosophical movement and are revisionistic in that many presumed parts of philosophy would not deserve the title «philosophy» if they were true.[26][27] Before the modern age, the term was used in a very wide sense, which included the individual sciences, like physics or mathematics, as its sub-disciplines, but the contemporary usage is more narrow.[25][28][29]
Some approaches argue that there is a set of essential features shared by all parts of philosophy while others see only weaker family resemblances or contend that it is merely an empty blanket term.[30][27][31] Some definitions characterize philosophy in relation to its method, like pure reasoning. Others focus more on its topic, for example, as the study of the biggest patterns of the world as a whole or as the attempt to answer the big questions.[27][32][33] Both approaches have the problem that they are usually either too wide, by including non-philosophical disciplines, or too narrow, by excluding some philosophical sub-disciplines.[27] Many definitions of philosophy emphasize its intimate relation to science.[25] In this sense, philosophy is sometimes understood as a proper science in its own right. Some naturalist approaches, for example, see philosophy as an empirical yet very abstract science that is concerned with very wide-ranging empirical patterns instead of particular observations.[27][34] Some phenomenologists, on the other hand, characterize philosophy as the science of essences.[26][35][36] Science-based definitions usually face the problem of explaining why philosophy in its long history has not made the type of progress as seen in other sciences.[27][37][38] This problem is avoided by seeing philosophy as an immature or provisional science whose subdisciplines cease to be philosophy once they have fully developed.[25][30][35] In this sense, philosophy is the midwife of the sciences.[25]
Other definitions focus more on the contrast between science and philosophy. A common theme among many such definitions is that philosophy is concerned with meaning, understanding, or the clarification of language.[32][27] According to one view, philosophy is conceptual analysis, which involves finding the necessary and sufficient conditions for the application of concepts.[33][27][39] Another defines philosophy as a linguistic therapy that aims at dispelling misunderstandings to which humans are susceptible due to the confusing structure of natural language.[26][25][40] One more approach holds that the main task of philosophy is to articulate the pre-ontological understanding of the world, which acts as a condition of possibility of experience.[27][41][42]
Many other definitions of philosophy do not clearly fall into any of the aforementioned categories. An early approach already found in ancient Greek and Roman philosophy is that philosophy is the spiritual practice of developing one’s reasoning ability.[43][44] This practice is an expression of the philosopher’s love of wisdom and has the aim of improving one’s well-being by leading a reflective life.[45] A closely related approach identifies the development and articulation of worldviews as the principal task of philosophy, i.e. to express how things on the grand scale hang together and which practical stance we should take towards them.[27][23][46] Another definition characterizes philosophy as thinking about thinking in order to emphasize its reflective nature.[27][33]
Historical overview
In one general sense, philosophy is associated with wisdom, intellectual culture, and a search for knowledge. In this sense, all cultures and literate societies ask philosophical questions, such as «how are we to live» and «what is the nature of reality». A broad and impartial conception of philosophy, then, finds a reasoned inquiry into such matters as reality, morality, and life in all world civilizations.[47]
Western philosophy
Statue of Aristotle (384–322 BCE), a major figure of ancient Greek philosophy, in Aristotle’s Park, Stagira
Western philosophy is the philosophical tradition of the Western world, dating back to pre-Socratic thinkers who were active in 6th-century Greece (BCE), such as Thales (c. 624 – c. 545 BCE) and Pythagoras (c. 570 – c. 495 BCE) who practiced a «love of wisdom» (Latin: philosophia)[48] and were also termed «students of nature» (physiologoi).
Western philosophy can be divided into three eras:
- Ancient (Greco-Roman).
- Medieval philosophy (referring to Christian European thought).
- Modern philosophy (beginning in the 17th century).
Ancient era
While our knowledge of the ancient era begins with Thales in the 6th century BCE, little is known about the philosophers who came before Socrates (commonly known as the pre-Socratics). The ancient era was dominated by Greek philosophical schools. Most notable among the schools influenced by Socrates’ teachings were Plato, who founded the Platonic Academy, and his student Aristotle, who founded the Peripatetic school.[49] Other ancient philosophical traditions influenced by Socrates included Cynicism, Cyrenaicism, Stoicism, and Academic Skepticism. Two other traditions were influenced by Socrates’ contemporary, Democritus: Pyrrhonism and Epicureanism. Important topics covered by the Greeks included metaphysics (with competing theories such as atomism and monism), cosmology, the nature of the well-lived life (eudaimonia), the possibility of knowledge, and the nature of reason (logos). With the rise of the Roman empire, Greek philosophy was increasingly discussed in Latin by Romans such as Cicero and Seneca (see Roman philosophy).[50]
Medieval era
Medieval philosophy (5th–16th centuries) took place during the period following the fall of the Western Roman Empire and was dominated by the rise of Christianity; it hence reflects Judeo-Christian theological concerns while also retaining a continuity with Greco-Roman thought. Problems such as the existence and nature of God, the nature of faith and reason, metaphysics, and the problem of evil were discussed in this period. Some key medieval thinkers include Augustine, Thomas Aquinas, Boethius, Anselm and Roger Bacon. Philosophy for these thinkers was viewed as an aid to theology (ancilla theologiae), and hence they sought to align their philosophy with their interpretation of sacred scripture. This period saw the development of scholasticism, a text critical method developed in medieval universities based on close reading and disputation on key texts. The Renaissance period saw increasing focus on classic Greco-Roman thought and on a robust humanism.[51]
Modern era
Early modern philosophy in the Western world begins with thinkers such as Thomas Hobbes and René Descartes (1596–1650).[52] Following the rise of natural science, modern philosophy was concerned with developing a secular and rational foundation for knowledge and moved away from traditional structures of authority such as religion, scholastic thought and the Church. Major modern philosophers include Spinoza, Leibniz, Locke, Berkeley, Hume, and Kant.
19th-century philosophy (sometimes called late modern philosophy) was influenced by the wider 18th-century movement termed «the Enlightenment», and includes figures such as Hegel, a key figure in German idealism; Kierkegaard, who developed the foundations for existentialism; Thomas Carlyle, representative of the great man theory; Nietzsche, a famed anti-Christian; John Stuart Mill, who promoted utilitarianism; Karl Marx, who developed the foundations for communism; and the American William James. The 20th century saw the split between analytic philosophy and continental philosophy, as well as philosophical trends such as phenomenology, existentialism, logical positivism, pragmatism and the linguistic turn (see Contemporary philosophy).[53]
Middle Eastern philosophy
Pre-Islamic philosophy
The regions of the Fertile Crescent, Iran and Arabia are home to the earliest known philosophical wisdom literature.[citation needed]
According to the assyriologist Marc Van de Mieroop, Babylonian philosophy was a highly developed system of thought with a unique approach to knowledge and a focus on writing, lexicography, divination, and law.[54] It was also a bilingual intellectual culture, based on Sumerian and Akkadian.[55]
A page of The Maxims of Ptahhotep, traditionally attributed to the Vizier Ptahhotep (c. 2375–2350 BCE)
Early Wisdom literature from the Fertile Crescent was a genre that sought to instruct people on ethical action, practical living, and virtue through stories and proverbs. In Ancient Egypt, these texts were known as sebayt (‘teachings’), and they are central to our understandings of Ancient Egyptian philosophy. The most well known of these texts is The Maxims of Ptahhotep.[56] Theology and cosmology were central concerns in Egyptian thought. Perhaps the earliest form of a monotheistic theology also emerged in Egypt, with the rise of the Amarna theology (or Atenism) of Akhenaten (14th century BCE), which held that the solar creation deity Aten was the only god. This has been described as a «monotheistic revolution» by egyptologist Jan Assmann, though it also drew on previous developments in Egyptian thought, particularly the «New Solar Theology» based around Amun-Ra.[57][58] These theological developments also influenced the post-Amarna Ramesside theology, which retained a focus on a single creative solar deity (though without outright rejection of other gods, which are now seen as manifestations of the main solar deity). This period also saw the development of the concept of the ba (soul) and its relation to god.[58]
Jewish philosophy and Christian philosophy are religious-philosophical traditions that developed both in the Middle East and in Europe, which both share certain early Judaic texts (mainly the Tanakh) and monotheistic beliefs. Jewish thinkers such as the Geonim of the Talmudic Academies in Babylonia and Maimonides engaged with Greek and Islamic philosophy. Later Jewish philosophy came under strong Western intellectual influences and includes the works of Moses Mendelssohn who ushered in the Haskalah (the Jewish Enlightenment), Jewish existentialism, and Reform Judaism.[59][60]
The various traditions of Gnosticism, which were influenced by both Greek and Abrahamic currents, originated around the first century and emphasized spiritual knowledge (gnosis).[61]
Pre-Islamic Iranian philosophy begins with the work of Zoroaster, one of the first promoters of monotheism and of the dualism between good and evil.[62] This dualistic cosmogony influenced later Iranian developments such as Manichaeism, Mazdakism, and Zurvanism.[63][64]
Islamic philosophy
Islamic philosophy is the philosophical work originating in the Islamic tradition and is mostly done in Arabic. It draws from the religion of Islam as well as from Greco-Roman philosophy. After the Muslim conquests, the translation movement (mid-eighth to the late tenth century) resulted in the works of Greek philosophy becoming available in Arabic.[65]
Early Islamic philosophy developed the Greek philosophical traditions in new innovative directions. This intellectual work inaugurated what is known as the Islamic Golden Age. The two main currents of early Islamic thought are Kalam, which focuses on Islamic theology, and Falsafa, which was based on Aristotelianism and Neoplatonism. The work of Aristotle was very influential among philosophers such as Al-Kindi (9th century), Avicenna (980 – June 1037), and Averroes (12th century). Others such as Al-Ghazali were highly critical of the methods of the Islamic Aristotelians and saw their metaphysical ideas as heretical. Islamic thinkers like Ibn al-Haytham and Al-Biruni also developed a scientific method, experimental medicine, a theory of optics, and a legal philosophy. Ibn Khaldun was an influential thinker in philosophy of history.
Islamic thought also deeply influenced European intellectual developments, especially through the commentaries of Averroes on Aristotle. The Mongol invasions and the destruction of Baghdad in 1258 are often seen as marking the end of the Golden Age.[66] Several schools of Islamic philosophy continued to flourish after the Golden Age, however, and include currents such as Illuminationist philosophy, Sufi philosophy, and Transcendent theosophy.
The 19th- and 20th-century Arab world saw the Nahda movement (literally meaning ‘The Awakening’; also known as the ‘Arab Renaissance’), which had a considerable influence on contemporary Islamic philosophy.
Eastern philosophy
Indian philosophy
Indian philosophy (Sanskrit: darśana, lit. ‘point of view’, ‘perspective’)[69] refers to the diverse philosophical traditions that emerged since the ancient times on the Indian subcontinent. Indian philosophy chiefly considers epistemology, theories of consciousness and theories of mind, and the physical properties of reality. [70] [71] [72] Indian philosophical traditions share various key concepts and ideas, which are defined in different ways and accepted or rejected by the different traditions. These include concepts such as dhárma, karma, pramāṇa, duḥkha, saṃsāra and mokṣa.[73][74]
Some of the earliest surviving Indian philosophical texts are the Upanishads of the later Vedic period (1000–500 BCE), which are considered to preserve the ideas of Brahmanism. Indian philosophical traditions are commonly grouped according to their relationship to the Vedas and the ideas contained in them. Jainism and Buddhism originated at the end of the Vedic period, while the various traditions grouped under Hinduism mostly emerged after the Vedic period as independent traditions. Hindus generally classify Indian philosophical traditions as either orthodox (āstika) or heterodox (nāstika) depending on whether they accept the authority of the Vedas and the theories of brahman and ātman found therein.[75][76]
The schools which align themselves with the thought of the Upanishads, the so-called «orthodox» or «Hindu» traditions, are often classified into six darśanas or philosophies:Sānkhya, Yoga, Nyāya, Vaisheshika, Mimāmsā and Vedānta.[77]
The doctrines of the Vedas and Upanishads were interpreted differently by these six schools of Hindu philosophy, with varying degrees of overlap. They represent a «collection of philosophical views that share a textual connection», according to Chadha (2015).[78] They also reflect a tolerance for a diversity of philosophical interpretations within Hinduism while sharing the same foundation.[ii]
Hindu philosophers of the six orthodox schools developed systems of epistemology (pramana) and investigated topics such as metaphysics, ethics, psychology (guṇa), hermeneutics, and soteriology within the framework of the Vedic knowledge, while presenting a diverse collection of interpretations.[79][80][81][82] The commonly named six orthodox schools were the competing philosophical traditions of what has been called the «Hindu synthesis» of classical Hinduism.[83][84]
[85]
There are also other schools of thought which are often seen as «Hindu», though not necessarily orthodox (since they may accept different scriptures as normative, such as the Shaiva Agamas and Tantras), these include different schools of Shavism such as Pashupata, Shaiva Siddhanta, non-dual tantric Shavism (i.e. Trika, Kaula, etc.).[86]
The parable of the blind men and the elephant illustrates the important Jain doctrine of anēkāntavāda.
The «Hindu» and «Orthodox» traditions are often contrasted with the «unorthodox» traditions (nāstika, literally «those who reject»), though this is a label that is not used by the «unorthodox» schools themselves. These traditions reject the Vedas as authoritative and often reject major concepts and ideas that are widely accepted by the orthodox schools (such as Ātman, Brahman, and Īśvara).[87] These unorthodox schools include Jainism (accepts ātman but rejects Īśvara, Vedas and Brahman), Buddhism (rejects all orthodox concepts except rebirth and karma), Cārvāka (materialists who reject even rebirth and karma) and Ājīvika (known for their doctrine of fate).[87][88][89]<[90][91][iii][92][93]
Jain philosophy is one of the only two surviving «unorthodox» traditions (along with Buddhism). It generally accepts the concept of a permanent soul (jiva) as one of the five astikayas (eternal, infinite categories that make up the substance of existence). The other four being dhárma, adharma, ākāśa (‘space’), and pudgala (‘matter’). Jain thought holds that all existence is cyclic, eternal and uncreated.[94][95]
Some of the most important elements of Jain philosophy are the Jain theory of karma, the doctrine of nonviolence (ahiṃsā) and the theory of «many-sidedness» or Anēkāntavāda. The Tattvartha Sutra is the earliest known, most comprehensive and authoritative compilation of Jain philosophy.[96][97]
Major European Quantum Physicists, including Erwin Schrödinger, Werner Heisenberg, Albert Einstein, & Niels Bohr credit the Vedas with giving them the ideas for their experiments. [98]
Buddhist philosophy
Monks debating at Sera monastery, Tibet, 2013. According to Jan Westerhoff, «public debates constituted the most important and most visible forms of philosophical exchange» in ancient Indian intellectual life.[99]
Buddhist philosophy begins with the thought of Gautama Buddha (fl. between 6th and 4th century BCE) and is preserved in the early Buddhist texts. It originated in the Indian region of Magadha and later spread to the rest of the Indian subcontinent, East Asia, Tibet, Central Asia, and Southeast Asia. In these regions, Buddhist thought developed into different philosophical traditions which used various languages (like Tibetan, Chinese and Pali). As such, Buddhist philosophy is a trans-cultural and international phenomenon.
The dominant Buddhist philosophical traditions in East Asian nations are mainly based on Indian Mahayana Buddhism. The philosophy of the Theravada school is dominant in Southeast Asian countries like Sri Lanka, Burma and Thailand.
Because ignorance to the true nature of things is considered one of the roots of suffering (dukkha), Buddhist philosophy is concerned with epistemology, metaphysics, ethics and psychology. Buddhist philosophical texts must also be understood within the context of meditative practices which are supposed to bring about certain cognitive shifts.[100] Key innovative concepts include the Four Noble Truths as an analysis of dukkha, anicca (impermanence), and anatta (non-self).[iv][101]
After the death of the Buddha, various groups began to systematize his main teachings, eventually developing comprehensive philosophical systems termed Abhidharma.[102] Following the Abhidharma schools, Indian Mahayana philosophers such as Nagarjuna and Vasubandhu developed the theories of śūnyatā (’emptiness of all phenomena’) and vijñapti-matra (‘appearance only’), a form of phenomenology or transcendental idealism. The Dignāga school of pramāṇa (‘means of knowledge’) promoted a sophisticated form of Buddhist epistemology.
There were numerous schools, sub-schools, and traditions of Buddhist philosophy in ancient and medieval India. According to Oxford professor of Buddhist philosophy Jan Westerhoff, the major Indian schools from 300 BCE to 1000 CE were:[103] the Mahāsāṃghika tradition (now extinct), the Sthavira schools (such as Sarvāstivāda, Vibhajyavāda and Pudgalavāda) and the Mahayana schools. Many of these traditions were also studied in other regions, like Central Asia and China, having been brought there by Buddhist missionaries.
After the disappearance of Buddhism from India, some of these philosophical traditions continued to develop in the Tibetan Buddhist, East Asian Buddhist and Theravada Buddhist traditions.[104][105]
East Asian philosophy
East Asian philosophical thought began in Ancient China, and Chinese philosophy begins during the Western Zhou Dynasty and the following periods after its fall when the «Hundred Schools of Thought» flourished (6th century to 221 BCE).[106][107] This period was characterized by significant intellectual and cultural developments and saw the rise of the major philosophical schools of China such as Confucianism (also known as Ruism), Legalism, and Taoism as well as numerous other less influential schools like Mohism and Naturalism. These philosophical traditions developed metaphysical, political and ethical theories such Tao, Yin and yang, Ren and Li.
These schools of thought further developed during the Han (206 BCE – 220 CE) and Tang (618–907 CE) eras, forming new philosophical movements like Xuanxue (also called Neo-Taoism), and Neo-Confucianism. Neo-Confucianism was a syncretic philosophy, which incorporated the ideas of different Chinese philosophical traditions, including Buddhism and Taoism. Neo-Confucianism came to dominate the education system during the Song dynasty (960–1297), and its ideas served as the philosophical basis of the imperial exams for the scholar official class. Some of the most important Neo-Confucian thinkers are the Tang scholars Han Yu and Li Ao as well as the Song thinkers Zhou Dunyi (1017–1073) and Zhu Xi (1130–1200). Zhu Xi compiled the Confucian canon, which consists of the Four Books (the Great Learning, the Doctrine of the Mean, the Analects of Confucius, and the Mencius). The Ming scholar Wang Yangming (1472–1529) is a later but important philosopher of this tradition as well.
Buddhism began arriving in China during the Han Dynasty, through a gradual Silk road transmission,[108] and through native influences developed distinct Chinese forms (such as Chan/Zen) which spread throughout the East Asian cultural sphere.
Chinese culture was highly influential on the traditions of other East Asian states, and its philosophy directly influenced Korean philosophy, Vietnamese philosophy and Japanese philosophy.[109] During later Chinese dynasties like the Ming Dynasty (1368–1644), as well as in the Korean Joseon dynasty (1392–1897), a resurgent Neo-Confucianism led by thinkers such as Wang Yangming (1472–1529) became the dominant school of thought and was promoted by the imperial state. In Japan, the Tokugawa shogunate (1603–1867) was also strongly influenced by Confucian philosophy.[110] Confucianism continues to influence the ideas and worldview of the nations of the Chinese cultural sphere today.
In the Modern era, Chinese thinkers incorporated ideas from Western philosophy. Chinese Marxist philosophy developed under the influence of Mao Zedong, while a Chinese pragmatism developed under Hu Shih. The old traditional philosophies also began to reassert themselves in the 20th century. For example, New Confucianism, led by figures such as Xiong Shili, has become quite influential. Likewise, Humanistic Buddhism is a recent modernist Buddhist movement.
Modern Japanese thought meanwhile developed under strong Western influences such as the study of Western Sciences (Rangaku) and the modernist Meirokusha intellectual society, which drew from European enlightenment thought and promoted liberal reforms as well as Western philosophies like Liberalism and Utilitarianism. Another trend in modern Japanese philosophy was the «National Studies» (Kokugaku) tradition. This intellectual trend sought to study and promote ancient Japanese thought and culture. Kokugaku thinkers such as Motoori Norinaga sought to return to a pure Japanese tradition which they called Shinto that they saw as untainted by foreign elements.
During the 20th century, the Kyoto School, an influential and unique Japanese philosophical school, developed from Western phenomenology and Medieval Japanese Buddhist philosophy such as that of Dogen.
African philosophy
Painting of Zera Yacob from Claude Sumner’s Classical Ethiopian Philosophy
African philosophy is philosophy produced by African people, philosophy that presents African worldviews, ideas and themes, or philosophy that uses distinct African philosophical methods. Modern African thought has been occupied with Ethnophilosophy, that is, defining the very meaning of African philosophy and its unique characteristics and what it means to be African.[111]
During the 17th century, Ethiopian philosophy developed a robust literary tradition as exemplified by Zera Yacob. Another early African philosopher was Anton Wilhelm Amo (c. 1703–1759) who became a respected philosopher in Germany. Distinct African philosophical ideas include Ujamaa, the Bantu idea of ‘Force’, Négritude, Pan-Africanism and Ubuntu. Contemporary African thought has also seen the development of Professional philosophy and of Africana philosophy, the philosophical literature of the African diaspora which includes currents such as black existentialism by African-Americans. Some modern African thinkers have been influenced by Marxism, African-American literature, Critical theory, Critical race theory, Postcolonialism and Feminism.
Indigenous American philosophy
Indigenous-American philosophical thought consists of a wide variety of beliefs and traditions among different American cultures. Among some of U.S. Native American communities, there is a belief in a metaphysical principle called the ‘Great Spirit’ (Siouan: wakȟáŋ tȟáŋka; Algonquian: gitche manitou). Another widely shared concept was that of orenda (‘spiritual power’). According to Whiteley (1998), for the Native Americans, «mind is critically informed by transcendental experience (dreams, visions and so on) as well as by reason.»[112] The practices to access these transcendental experiences are termed shamanism. Another feature of the indigenous American worldviews was their extension of ethics to non-human animals and plants.[112][113]
In Mesoamerica, Nahua philosophy was an intellectual tradition developed by individuals called tlamatini (‘those who know something’)[114] and its ideas are preserved in various Aztec codices and fragmentary texts. Some of these philosophers are known by name, such as Nezahualcoyotl, Aquiauhtzin, Xayacamach, Tochihuitzin coyolchiuhqui and Cuauhtencoztli.[115][116] These authors were also poets and some of their work has survived in the original Nahuatl.[115][116]
Aztec philosophers developed theories of metaphysics, epistemology, values, and aesthetics. Aztec ethics was focused on seeking tlamatiliztli (‘knowledge’, ‘wisdom’) which was based on moderation and balance in all actions as in the Nahua proverb «the middle good is necessary».[117] The Nahua worldview posited the concept of an ultimate universal energy or force called Ōmeteōtl (‘Dual Cosmic Energy’) which sought a way to live in balance with a constantly changing, «slippery» world. The theory of Teotl can be seen as a form of Pantheism.[117] According to James Maffie, Nahua metaphysics posited that teotl is «a single, vital, dynamic, vivifying, eternally self-generating and self-conceiving as well as self-regenerating and self-reconceiving sacred energy or force».[116] This force was seen as the all-encompassing life force of the universe and as the universe itself.[116]
The Inca civilization also had an elite class of philosopher-scholars termed the amawtakuna or amautas who were important in the Inca education system as teachers of philosophy, theology, astronomy, poetry, law, music, morality and history.[118][119] Young Inca nobles were educated in these disciplines at the state college of Yacha-huasi in Cuzco, where they also learned the art of the quipu.[118] Incan philosophy (as well as the broader category of Andean thought) held that the universe is animated by a single dynamic life force (sometimes termed camaquen or camac, as well as upani and amaya).[120] This singular force also arises as a set of dual complementary yet opposite forces.[120] These «complementary opposites» are called yanantin and masintin. They are expressed as various polarities or dualities (such as male–female, dark–light, life and death, above and below) which interdependently contribute to the harmonious whole that is the universe through the process of reciprocity and mutual exchange called ayni.[121][120] The Inca worldview also included the belief in a creator God (Viracocha) and reincarnation.[119]
Branches of philosophy
Philosophical questions can be grouped into various branches. These groupings allow philosophers to focus on a set of similar topics and interact with other thinkers who are interested in the same questions.
These divisions are neither exhaustive nor mutually exclusive. (A philosopher might specialize in Kantian epistemology, or Platonic aesthetics, or modern political philosophy). Furthermore, these philosophical inquiries sometimes overlap with each other and with other inquiries such as science, religion or mathematics.[122]
Aesthetics
Aesthetics is the «critical reflection on art, culture and nature».[123][124] It addresses the nature of art, beauty and taste, enjoyment, emotional values, perception and the creation and appreciation of beauty.[125] It is more precisely defined as the study of sensory or sensori-emotional values, sometimes called judgments of sentiment and taste.[126] Its major divisions are art theory, literary theory, film theory and music theory. An example from art theory is to discern the set of principles underlying the work of a particular artist or artistic movement such as the Cubist aesthetic.[127]
Ethics
«The utilitarian doctrine is, that happiness is desirable, and the only thing desirable, as an end; all other things being only desirable as means to that end.» — John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism (1863)[128]
Ethics, also known as moral philosophy, studies what constitutes good and bad conduct, right and wrong values, and good and evil. Its primary investigations include exploring how to live a good life and identifying standards of morality. It also includes investigating whether there is a best way to live or a universal moral standard, and if so, how we come to learn about it. The main branches of ethics are normative ethics, meta-ethics and applied ethics.[129]
The three main views in ethics about what constitute moral actions are:[129]
- Consequentialism, which judges actions based on their consequences.[130] One such view is utilitarianism, which judges actions based on the net happiness (or pleasure) and/or lack of suffering (or pain) that they produce.
- Deontology, which judges actions based on whether they are in accordance with one’s moral duty.[130] In the standard form defended by Immanuel Kant, deontology is concerned with whether a choice respects the moral agency of other people, regardless of its consequences.[130]
- Virtue ethics, which judges actions based on the moral character of the agent who performs them and whether they conform to what an ideally virtuous agent would do.[130]
Epistemology
Epistemology is the branch of philosophy that studies knowledge.[131] Epistemologists examine putative sources of knowledge, including perceptual experience, reason, memory, and testimony. They also investigate questions about the nature of truth, belief, justification, and rationality.[132]
Philosophical skepticism, which raises doubts about some or all claims to knowledge, has been a topic of interest throughout the history of philosophy. It arose early in Pre-Socratic philosophy and became formalized with Pyrrho, the founder of the earliest Western school of philosophical skepticism. It features prominently in the works of modern philosophers René Descartes and David Hume and has remained a central topic in contemporary epistemological debates.[132]
One of the most notable epistemological debates is between empiricism and rationalism.[133] Empiricism places emphasis on observational evidence via sensory experience as the source of knowledge.[133] Empiricism is associated with a posteriori knowledge, which is obtained through experience (such as scientific knowledge).[133] Rationalism places emphasis on reason as a source of knowledge.[133] Rationalism is associated with a priori knowledge, which is independent of experience (such as logic and mathematics).
One central debate in contemporary epistemology is about the conditions required for a belief to constitute knowledge, which might include truth and justification. This debate was largely the result of attempts to solve the Gettier problem.[132] Another common subject of contemporary debates is the regress problem, which occurs when trying to offer proof or justification for any belief, statement, or proposition. The problem is that whatever the source of justification may be, that source must either be without justification (in which case it must be treated as an arbitrary foundation for belief), or it must have some further justification (in which case justification must either be the result of circular reasoning, as in coherentism, or the result of an infinite regress, as in infinitism).[132]
Metaphysics
Metaphysics is the study of the most general features of reality, such as existence, time, objects and their properties, wholes and their parts, events, processes and causation and the relationship between mind and body.[134] Metaphysics includes cosmology, the study of the world in its entirety and ontology, the study of being, along with the philosophy of space and time.
A major point of debate is between realism, which holds that there are entities that exist independently of their mental perception, and idealism, which holds that reality is mentally constructed or otherwise immaterial. Metaphysics deals with the topic of identity. Essence is the set of attributes that make an object what it fundamentally is and without which it loses its identity, while accident is a property that the object has, without which the object can still retain its identity. Particulars are objects that are said to exist in space and time, as opposed to abstract objects, such as numbers, and universals, which are properties held by multiple particulars, such as redness or a gender. The type of existence, if any, of universals and abstract objects is an issue of debate.
Logic
Logic is the study of reasoning and argument.
Deductive reasoning is when, given certain premises, conclusions are unavoidably implied.[135] Rules of inference are used to infer conclusions such as, modus ponens, where given «A» and «If A then B», then «B» must be concluded.
Because sound reasoning is an essential element of all sciences,[136] social sciences and humanities disciplines, logic became a formal science. Sub-fields include mathematical logic, philosophical logic, modal logic, computational logic and non-classical logics. A major question in the philosophy of mathematics is whether mathematical entities are objective and discovered, called mathematical realism, or invented, called mathematical antirealism.
Mind and language
Philosophy of language explores the nature, origins, and use of language. Philosophy of mind explores the nature of the mind and its relationship to the body, as typified by disputes between materialism and dualism. In recent years, this branch has become related to cognitive science.
Philosophy of science
The philosophy of science explores the foundations, methods, history, implications and purpose of science. Many of its subdivisions correspond to specific branches of science. For example, philosophy of biology deals specifically with the metaphysical, epistemological and ethical issues in the biomedical and life sciences.
Political philosophy
Political philosophy is the study of government and the relationship of individuals (or families and clans) to communities including the state. It includes questions about justice, law, property and the rights and obligations of the citizen. Political philosophy, ethics, and aesthetics are traditionally linked subjects, under the general heading of value theory as they involve a normative or evaluative aspect.[137]
Philosophy of religion
Philosophy of religion deals with questions that involve religion and religious ideas from a philosophically neutral perspective (as opposed to theology which begins from religious convictions).[138] Traditionally, religious questions were not seen as a separate field from philosophy proper, and the idea of a separate field only arose in the 19th century.[v]
Issues include the existence of God, the relationship between reason and faith, questions of religious epistemology, the relationship between religion and science, how to interpret religious experiences, questions about the possibility of an afterlife, the problem of religious language and the existence of souls and responses to religious pluralism and diversity.
Metaphilosophy
Metaphilosophy explores the aims, boundaries and methods of philosophy. It is debated as to whether metaphilosophy is a subject that comes prior to philosophy[139] or whether it is inherently part of philosophy.[140]
Other subdivisions
In section thirteen of his Lives and Opinions of the Eminent Philosophers, the oldest surviving history of philosophy (3rd century), Diogenes Laërtius presents a three-part division of ancient Greek philosophical inquiry:[141]
- Natural philosophy (i.e. physics, from Greek: ta physika, lit. ‘things having to do with physis [nature]’) was the study of the constitution and processes of transformation in the physical world.[142]
- Moral philosophy (i.e. ethics, from êthika, ‘having to do with character, disposition, manners’) was the study of goodness, right and wrong, justice and virtue.[143]
- Metaphysical philosophy (i.e. logic, from logikós, ‘of or pertaining to reason or speech’) was the study of existence, causation, God, logic, forms, and other abstract objects. (meta ta physika, ‘after the Physics‘)
In Against the Logicians the Pyrrhonist philosopher Sextus Empiricus detailed the variety of ways in which the ancient Greek philosophers had divided philosophy, noting that this three-part division was agreed to by Plato, Aristotle, Xenocrates, and the Stoics.[144] The Academic Skeptic philosopher Cicero also followed this three-part division.[145]
This division is not obsolete, but has changed: natural philosophy has split into the various natural sciences, especially physics, astronomy, chemistry, biology, and cosmology; moral philosophy has birthed the social sciences, while still including value theory (e.g. ethics, aesthetics, political philosophy, etc.); and metaphysical philosophy has given way to formal sciences such as logic, mathematics and philosophy of science, while still including epistemology, cosmology, etc. For example, Newton’s Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy (1687), since classified as a book of physics, uses the term natural philosophy as it was understood at the time, encompassing disciplines such as astronomy, medicine and physics that later became associated with the sciences.[16]
Methods of philosophy
Methods of philosophy are ways of conducting philosophical inquiry. They include techniques for arriving at philosophical knowledge and justifying philosophical claims as well as principles used for choosing between competing theories.[146][147][148] A great variety of methods has been employed throughout the history of philosophy. Many of them differ significantly from the methods used in the natural sciences in that they do not use experimental data obtained through measuring equipment.[149][150][151] The choice of one’s method usually has important implications both for how philosophical theories are constructed and for the arguments cited for or against them.[147][152][153] This choice is often guided by epistemological considerations about what constitutes philosophical evidence, how much support it offers, and how to acquire it.[149][147][154] Various disagreements on the level of philosophical theories have their source in methodological disagreements and the discovery of new methods has often had important consequences both for how philosophers conduct their research and for what claims they defend.[155][148][147] Some philosophers engage in most of their theorizing using one particular method while others employ a wider range of methods based on which one fits the specific problem investigated best.[150][156]
Methodological skepticism is a prominent method of philosophy. It aims to arrive at absolutely certain first principles by using systematic doubt to determine which principles of philosophy are indubitable.[157] The geometrical method tries to build a comprehensive philosophical system based on a small set of such axioms. It does so with the help of deductive reasoning to expand the certainty of its axioms to the system as a whole.[158][159] Phenomenologists seek certain knowledge about the realm of appearances. They do so by suspending their judgments about the external world in order to focus on how things appear independent of their underlying reality, a technique known as epoché.[160][148] Conceptual analysis is a well-known method in analytic philosophy. It aims to clarify the meaning of concepts by analyzing them into their fundamental constituents.[161][39][23] Another method often employed in analytic philosophy is based on common sense. It starts with commonly accepted beliefs and tries to draw interesting conclusions from them, which it often employs in a negative sense to criticize philosophical theories that are too far removed from how the average person sees the issue.[151][162][163] It is very similar to how ordinary language philosophy tackles philosophical questions by investigating how ordinary language is used.[148][164][165]
Various methods in philosophy give particular importance to intuitions, i.e. non-inferential impressions about the correctness of specific claims or general principles.[155][166] For example, they play an important role in thought experiments, which employ counterfactual thinking to evaluate the possible consequences of an imagined situation. These anticipated consequences can then be used to confirm or refute philosophical theories.[167][168][161] The method of reflective equilibrium also employs intuitions. It seeks to form a coherent position on a certain issue by examining all the relevant beliefs and intuitions, some of which often have to be deemphasized or reformulated in order to arrive at a coherent perspective.[155][169][170] Pragmatists stress the significance of concrete practical consequences for assessing whether a philosophical theory is true or false.[171][172] Experimental philosophy is of rather recent origin. Its methods differ from most other methods of philosophy in that it tries to answer philosophical questions by gathering empirical data in ways similar to social psychology and the cognitive sciences.[173][174]
Philosophical progress
Many philosophical debates that began in ancient times are still debated today. British philosopher Colin McGinn claims that no philosophical progress has occurred during that interval.[175] Australian philosopher David Chalmers, by contrast, sees progress in philosophy similar to that in science.[176] Meanwhile, Talbot Brewer, professor of philosophy at University of Virginia, argues that «progress» is the wrong standard by which to judge philosophical activity.[177]
Applied and professional philosophy
Some of those who study philosophy become professional philosophers, typically by working as professors who teach, research and write in academic institutions.[178] However, most students of academic philosophy later contribute to law, journalism, religion, sciences, politics, business, or various arts.[179][180] For example, public figures who have degrees in philosophy include comedians Steve Martin and Ricky Gervais, filmmaker Terrence Malick, Pope John Paul II, Wikipedia co-founder Larry Sanger, technology entrepreneur Peter Thiel, U.S. Supreme Court Justice Stephen Breyer, Jeopardy! host Alex Trebek, and US vice presidential candidate Carly Fiorina.[181][182] Curtis White has argued that philosophical tools are essential to humanities, sciences and social sciences.[183]
Recent efforts to avail the general public to the work and relevance of philosophers include the million-dollar Berggruen Prize, first awarded to Charles Taylor in 2016.[184] Some philosophers argue that this professionalization has negatively affected the discipline.[185]
Women in philosophy
Although men have generally dominated philosophical discourse, women philosophers have engaged in the discipline throughout history. The list of female philosophers throughout history is vast. Ancient examples include Hipparchia of Maroneia (active c. 325 BCE) and Arete of Cyrene (active 5th–4th centuries BCE). Some women philosophers were accepted during the medieval and modern eras, but none became part of the Western canon until the 20th and 21st century, when many suggest that G.E.M. Anscombe, Hannah Arendt, bell hooks, Simone de Beauvoir, Simone Weil and Susanne Langer entered the canon.[186][187][188]
In the early 1800s, some colleges and universities in the UK and the US began admitting women, producing more female academics. Nevertheless, U.S. Department of Education reports from the 1990s indicate that few women ended up in philosophy and that philosophy is one of the least gender-proportionate fields in the humanities, with women making up somewhere between 17% and 30% of philosophy faculty according to some studies.[189]
Prominent 21st century philosophers include: Judith Butler, Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, Martha Nussbaum, Onora O’Neill, and Nancy Fraser.[190] [191]
See also
- List of important publications in philosophy
- List of years in philosophy
- List of philosophy journals
- List of philosophy awards
- List of unsolved problems in philosophy
- Lists of philosophers
- Social theory
- Systems theory
- Wikipedia:Getting to Philosophy
References
Notes
- ^ Quinton, Anthony. The Ethics of Philosophical Practice. p. 666.
Philosophy is rationally critical thinking, of a more or less systematic kind about the general nature of the world (metaphysics or theory of existence), the justification of belief (epistemology or theory of knowledge), and the conduct of life (ethics or theory of value). Each of the three elements in this list has a non-philosophical counterpart, from which it is distinguished by its explicitly rational and critical way of proceeding and by its systematic nature. Everyone has some general conception of the nature of the world in which they live and of their place in it. Metaphysics replaces the unargued assumptions embodied in such a conception with a rational and organized body of beliefs about the world as a whole. Everyone has occasion to doubt and question beliefs, their own or those of others, with more or less success and without any theory of what they are doing. Epistemology seeks by argument to make explicit the rules of correct belief formation. Everyone governs their conduct by directing it to desired or valued ends. Ethics, or moral philosophy, in its most inclusive sense, seeks to articulate, in rationally systematic form, the rules or principles involved.
in Honderich 1995. - ^ Sharma, Arvind (1990). A Hindu Perspective on the Philosophy of Religion. Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 1–2. ISBN 978-1-349-20797-8. Archived from the original on 12 January 2020. Retrieved 11 November 2018.
The attitude towards the existence of God varies within the Hindu religious tradition. This may not be entirely unexpected given the tolerance for doctrinal diversity for which the tradition is known. Thus of the six orthodox systems of Hindu philosophy, only three address the question in some detail. These are the schools of thought known as Nyaya, Yoga and the theistic forms of Vedanta.
- ^ Wynne, Alexander (2011). «The ātman and its negation». Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies. 33 (1–2): 103–05.
The denial that a human being possesses a ‘self’ or ‘soul’ is probably the most famous Buddhist teaching. It is certainly its most distinct, as has been pointed out by G.P. Malalasekera: ‘In its denial of any real permanent Soul or Self, Buddhism stands alone.’ A similar modern Sinhalese perspective has been expressed by Walpola Rahula: ‘Buddhism stands unique in the history of human thought in denying the existence of such a Soul, Self or Ātman.’ The ‘no Self’ or ‘no soul’ doctrine (Sanskrit: anātman; Pali: anattan) is particularly notable for its widespread acceptance and historical endurance. It was a standard belief of virtually all the ancient schools of Indian Buddhism (the notable exception being the Pudgalavādins), and has persisted without change into the modern era.… [B]oth views are mirrored by the modern Theravādin perspective of Mahasi Sayadaw that ‘there is no person or soul’ and the modern Mahāyāna view of the fourteenth Dalai Lama that ‘[t]he Buddha taught that…our belief in an independent self is the root cause of all suffering.‘
- ^ Gombrich, Richard (2006). Theravada Buddhism. Routledge. p. 47. ISBN 978-1-134-90352-8. Archived from the original on 16 August 2019. Retrieved 10 November 2018.
All phenomenal existence [in Buddhism] is said to have three interlocking characteristics: impermanence, suffering and lack of soul or essence.
- ^ Wainwright, William J. (2005). «Introduction». In Wainwright, W. J. (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Religion. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 3–11. ISBN 978-0-19-803158-1. Archived from the original on 6 August 2020. p. 3:
The expression ‘philosophy of religion’ did not come into general use until the nineteenth century, when it was employed to refer to the articulation and criticism of humanity’s religious consciousness and its cultural expressions in thought, language, feeling, and practice.
Citations
- ^ «philosophy (n.)». Online Etymology Dictionary. Archived from the original on 2 July 2017. Retrieved 22 August 2010.
- ^ The definition of philosophy is: «1. orig., love of, or the search for, wisdom or knowledge 2. theory or logical analysis of the principles underlying conduct, thought, knowledge, and the nature of the universe». Webster’s New World Dictionary (Second College ed.).
- ^ «philosophy | Definition, Systems, Fields, Schools, & Biographies». Encyclopædia Britannica. Archived from the original on 23 February 2021. Retrieved 29 May 2022.
- ^ «Philosophy». Lexico. University of Oxford Press. 2020. Archived from the original on 28 March 2019. Retrieved 28 March 2019.
- ^ Sellars, Wilfrid (1963). Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind (PDF). Routledge and Kegan Paul Ltd. pp. 1, 40. Archived from the original (PDF) on 23 March 2019. Retrieved 28 March 2019.
- ^ Chalmers, David J. (1995). «Facing up to the problem of consciousness». Journal of Consciousness Studies. 2 (3): 200, 219. Archived from the original on 20 November 2019. Retrieved 28 March 2019.
- ^ Henderson, Leah (2019). «The problem of induction». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 27 March 2019. Retrieved 28 March 2019.
- ^ Cicero, Marcus Tullius (1877). Tusculan Disputations. New York: Harper & Brothers. p. 166. Archived from the original on 18 May 2021. Retrieved 12 June 2021.
From whence all who occupied themselves in the contemplation of nature were both considered and called wise men; and that name of theirs continued to the age of Pythagoras, who is reported to have gone to Phlius, as we find it stated by Heraclides Ponticus, a very learned man, and a pupil of Plato, and to have discoursed very learnedly and copiously on certain subjects with Leon, prince of the Phliasii; and when Leon, admiring his ingenuity and eloquence, asked him what art he particularly professed, his answer was, that he was acquainted with no art, but that he was a philosopher. Leon, surprised at the novelty of the name, inquired what he meant by the name of philosopher, and in what philosophers differed from other men; on which Pythagoras replied, «That the life of man seemed to him to resemble those games which were celebrated with the greatest possible variety of sports and the general concourse of all Greece. For as in those games there were some persons whose object was glory and the honor of a crown, to be attained by the performance of bodily exercises, so others were led thither by the gain of buying and selling, and mere views of profit; but there was likewise one class of persons, and they were by far the best, whose aim was neither applause nor profit, but who came merely as spectators through curiosity, to observe what was done, and to see in what manner things were carried on there. And thus, said he, we come from another life and nature unto this one, just as men come out of some other city, to some much frequented mart; some being slaves to glory, others to money; and there are some few who, taking no account of anything else, earnestly look into the nature of things; and these men call themselves studious of wisdom, that is, philosophers: and as there it is the most reputable occupation of all to be a looker-on without making any acquisition, so in life, the contemplating things, and acquainting one’s self with them, greatly exceeds every other pursuit of life.»
- ^ Cameron, Alister (1938). The Pythagorean Background of the theory of Recollection. George Banta Publishing Company.
- ^ Jaeger, W. ‘On the Origin and Cycle of the Philosophic Ideal of Life.’ First published in Sitzungsberichte der preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, philosophisch-historishce Klasse, 1928; Eng. Translation in Jaeger’s Aristotle, 2nd Ed. Oxford, 1948, 426-61.
- ^ Festugiere, A.J. (1958). «Les Trios Vies». Acta Congressus Madvigiani. Vol. 2. Copenhagen. pp. 131–78.
- ^ Guthrie, W. K. C. (1962–1981). A history of Greek philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 165–166. ISBN 978-0-521-05160-6. OCLC 22488892. Archived from the original on 21 January 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2021.
This does not of course amount to saying that the simile goes back to Pythagoras himself, but only that the Greek ideal of philosophia and theoria (for which we may compare Herodotus’s attribution of these activities to Solon I, 30) was at a fairly early date annexed by the Pythagoreans for their master
- ^ Adler, Mortimer J. (2000). How to Think About the Great Ideas: From the Great Books of Western Civilization. Chicago, Ill.: Open Court. ISBN 978-0-8126-9412-3.
- ^ Quinton, Anthony. The Ethics of Philosophical Practice. p. 666.
Philosophy is rationally critical thinking, of a more or less systematic kind about the general nature of the world (metaphysics or theory of existence), the justification of belief (epistemology or theory of knowledge), and the conduct of life (ethics or theory of value). Each of the three elements in this list has a non-philosophical counterpart, from which it is distinguished by its explicitly rational and critical way of proceeding and by its systematic nature. Everyone has some general conception of the nature of the world in which they live and of their place in it. Metaphysics replaces the unargued assumptions embodied in such a conception with a rational and organized body of beliefs about the world as a whole. Everyone has occasion to doubt and question beliefs, their own or those of others, with more or less success and without any theory of what they are doing. Epistemology seeks by argument to make explicit the rules of correct belief formation. Everyone governs their conduct by directing it to desired or valued ends. Ethics, or moral philosophy, in its most inclusive sense, seeks to articulate, in rationally systematic form, the rules or principles involved.
in Honderich 1995. - ^ «The English word «philosophy» is first attested to c. 1300, meaning «knowledge, body of knowledge».
Harper, Douglas (2020). «philosophy (n.)». Online Etymology Dictionary. Archived from the original on 2 July 2017. Retrieved 8 May 2020.
- ^ a b Lindberg 2007, p. 3.
- ^ «Epistemology in Classical Indian Philosophy». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2021.
- ^ Shapin, Steven (1998). The Scientific Revolution (1st ed.). University Of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-75021-7.
- ^ Briggle, Robert; Frodeman, Adam (11 January 2016). «When Philosophy Lost Its Way | The Opinionator». New York Times. Archived from the original on 5 March 2020. Retrieved 25 April 2016.
- ^ «Metaphysics». Merriam-Webster Dictionary. Archived from the original on 8 May 2020. Retrieved 8 May 2020.
- ^ «Epistemology». Merriam-Webster Dictionary. Archived from the original on 8 May 2020. Retrieved 8 May 2020.
- ^ «philosophy (n.)». Online Etymology Dictionary. Archived from the original on 13 September 2017. Retrieved 21 March 2022.
- ^ a b c Audi, Robert (2006). «Philosophy». Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. Archived from the original on 14 February 2022. Retrieved 15 February 2022.
- ^ a b Honderich, Ted (2005). «Philosophy». The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. Archived from the original on 29 January 2021. Retrieved 15 February 2022.
- ^ a b c d e f g Sandkühler, Hans Jörg (2010). «Philosophiebegriffe». Enzyklopädie Philosophie. Meiner. Archived from the original on 20 March 2022. Retrieved 15 February 2022.
- ^ a b c Joll, Nicholas. «Metaphilosophy». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 15 May 2019. Retrieved 1 February 2022.
- ^ a b c d e f g h i j k Overgaard, Søren; Gilbert, Paul; Burwood, Stephen (2013). «What is philosophy?». An Introduction to Metaphilosophy. Cambridge University Press. pp. 17–44. ISBN 978-0-521-19341-2. Archived from the original on 14 February 2022. Retrieved 15 February 2022.
- ^ «philosophy». Online Etymology Dictionary. Archived from the original on 13 September 2017. Retrieved 15 February 2022.
- ^ Baggini, Julian; Krauss, Lawrence (8 September 2012). «Philosophy v science: which can answer the big questions of life?». the Guardian. Archived from the original on 14 February 2022. Retrieved 11 February 2022.
- ^ a b Mittelstraß, Jürgen (2005). «Philosophie». Enzyklopädie Philosophie und Wissenschaftstheorie. Metzler. Archived from the original on 20 October 2021. Retrieved 27 February 2022.
- ^ Quine, Willard Van Orman (2008). «41. A Letter to Mr. Ostermann». Quine in Dialogue. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-03083-1. Archived from the original on 13 February 2022. Retrieved 27 February 2022.
- ^ a b Rescher, Nicholas (2 May 2013). «1. The Nature of Philosophy». On the Nature of Philosophy and Other Philosophical Essays. Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-032020-6. Archived from the original on 13 February 2022. Retrieved 15 February 2022.
- ^ a b c Nuttall, Jon (3 July 2013). «1. The Nature of Philosophy». An Introduction to Philosophy. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-0-7456-6807-9. Archived from the original on 13 February 2022. Retrieved 15 February 2022.
- ^ Hylton, Peter; Kemp, Gary (2020). «Willard Van Orman Quine: 3. The Analytic-Synthetic Distinction and the Argument Against Logical Empiricism». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 25 February 2021. Retrieved 27 February 2022.
- ^ a b Gelan, Victor Eugen (2020). «Husserl’s Idea of Rigorous Science and Its Relevance for the Human and Social Sciences». The Subject(s) of Phenomenology: Rereading Husserl. Contributions to Phenomenology. Vol. 108. Springer International Publishing. pp. 97–105. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-29357-4_6. ISBN 978-3-030-29357-4. S2CID 213082313. Archived from the original on 2 March 2022. Retrieved 27 February 2022.
- ^ Ingarden, Roman (1975). «The Concept of Philosophy as Rigorous Science». On the Motives which led Husserl to Transcendental Idealism. Phaenomenologica. Vol. 64. Springer Netherlands. pp. 8–11. doi:10.1007/978-94-010-1689-6_3. ISBN 978-94-010-1689-6. Archived from the original on 13 February 2022. Retrieved 27 February 2022.
- ^ Chalmers, David J. (2015). «Why Isn’t There More Progress in Philosophy?». Philosophy. 90 (1): 3–31. doi:10.1017/s0031819114000436. hdl:1885/57201. S2CID 170974260. Archived from the original on 13 February 2022. Retrieved 27 February 2022.
- ^ Dellsén, Finnur; Lawler, Insa; Norton, James (29 June 2021). «Thinking about Progress: From Science to Philosophy». Noûs. 56 (4): 814–840. doi:10.1111/nous.12383. S2CID 235967433.
- ^ a b SHAFFER, MICHAEL J. (2015). «The Problem of Necessary and Sufficient Conditions and Conceptual Analysis». Metaphilosophy. 46 (4/5): 555–563. doi:10.1111/meta.12158. ISSN 0026-1068. JSTOR 26602327. S2CID 148551744. Archived from the original on 13 February 2022. Retrieved 15 February 2022.
- ^ Biletzki, Anat; Matar, Anat (2021). «Ludwig Wittgenstein: 3.7 The Nature of Philosophy». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 8 September 2018. Retrieved 11 February 2022.
- ^ Piché, Claude (2016). «Kant on the «Conditions of the Possibility» of Experience». Transcendental Inquiry: Its History, Methods and Critiques. Springer International Publishing. pp. 1–20. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-40715-9_1. hdl:1866/21324. ISBN 978-3-319-40715-9. Archived from the original on 13 February 2022. Retrieved 15 February 2022.
- ^ Wheeler, Michael (2020). «Martin Heidegger». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 6 February 2022. Retrieved 11 February 2022.
- ^ Banicki, Konrad (2014). «Philosophy as Therapy: Towards a Conceptual Model». Philosophical Papers. 43 (1): 7–31. doi:10.1080/05568641.2014.901692. S2CID 144901869. Archived from the original on 13 February 2022. Retrieved 15 February 2022.
- ^ Hadot, Pierre (1997). «11. Philosophy as a Way of Life». Philosophy as a Way of Life: Spiritual Exercises From Socrates to Foucault. Blackwell. Archived from the original on 14 February 2022. Retrieved 15 February 2022.
- ^ Grimm, Stephen R.; Cohoe, Caleb (2021). «What is philosophy as a way of life? Why philosophy as a way of life?». European Journal of Philosophy. 29 (1): 236–251. doi:10.1111/ejop.12562. ISSN 1468-0378. S2CID 225504495. Archived from the original on 13 February 2022. Retrieved 15 February 2022.
- ^ McIvor, David W. «Weltanschauung». International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences. Archived from the original on 20 March 2022. Retrieved 15 February 2022.
- ^ Garfield, Jay L; Edelglass, William, eds. (9 June 2011). «Introduction». The Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195328998.001.0001. ISBN 9780195328998. Archived from the original on 31 March 2019. Retrieved 19 December 2019.
- ^ Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich; Brown, Robert F. (2006). Lectures on the History of Philosophy: Greek philosophy. Clarendon Press. p. 33. ISBN 978-0-19-927906-7.
- ^ Whitehead, Alfred North (11 May 2010). Process and Reality. Simon & Schuster. p. 39. ISBN 978-1-4391-1836-8.
- ^ Kenny, Anthony (17 June 2004). Ancient Philosophy: A New History of Western Philosophy. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-162252-6.
- ^ Kenny, Anthony (31 May 2007). Medieval Philosophy: A New History of Western Philosophy, Volume 2. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-162253-3.
- ^ Collinson, Diane. Fifty Major Philosophers, A Reference Guide. p. 125.
- ^ Kenny, Anthony (29 June 2006). The Rise of Modern Philosophy: A New History of Western Philosophy, Volume 3. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-875277-6.
- ^ Philosophy before the Greeks 2015, pp. vii–viii, 187–188.
- ^ Philosophy before the Greeks 2015, p. 218.
- ^ Lichtheim, Miriam (1976). Ancient Egyptian Literature, Volume II: The New Kingdom. University of California Press. pp. 61 ff. ISBN 0-520-03615-8.
- ^ Najovits, Simson (2004). Egypt, the Trunk of the Tree, A Modern Survey of and Ancient Land, Vol. II. New York: Algora Publishing. p. 131. ISBN 978-0875862569.
- ^ a b Assmann, Jan (2004). «Theological Responses to Amarna» (PDF). In Knoppers, Gary N.; Hirsch, Antoine (eds.). Egypt, Israel, and the Ancient Mediterranean World. Studies in Honor of Donald B. Redford. Leiden/Boston. pp. 179–191. Archived (PDF) from the original on 18 May 2020.
- ^ Frank, Daniel; Leaman, Oliver (20 October 2005). History of Jewish Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-89435-2.
- ^ Bartholomew, Craig G.; Goheen, Michael W. (15 October 2013). Christian Philosophy: A Systematic and Narrative Introduction. Baker Academic. ISBN 978-1-4412-4471-0.
- ^ Churton, Tobias (25 January 2005). Gnostic Philosophy: From Ancient Persia to Modern Times. Simon & Schuster. ISBN 978-1-59477-767-7.
- ^ Nasr, S. H.; Aminrazavi, Mehdi; Jozi, M. R. (30 September 2008). An Anthology of Philosophy in Persia, Vol. 2: Ismaili Thought in the Classical Age. Bloomsbury Academic. ISBN 978-1-84511-542-5.
- ^ Keddie, Nikki R. (28 October 2013). Iran: Religion, Politics and Society: Collected Essays. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-136-28041-2.
- ^ de Blois, François (2000). «Dualism in Iranian and Christian Traditions». Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society. 10 (1): 1–19. doi:10.1017/S1356186300011913. ISSN 1356-1863. JSTOR 25187928. S2CID 162835432.
- ^ Gutas, Dimitri (1998). Greek Thought, Arabic Culture: The Graeco-Arabic Translation Movement in Baghdad and Early Abbasid Society (2nd-4th/8th-10th centuries). Routledge. pp. 1–26.
- ^ Cooper, William W.; Yue, Piyu (2008). Challenges of the Muslim world: present, future and past. Emerald Group Publishing. ISBN 978-0-444-53243-5.
- ^ N.V. Isaeva (1992). Shankara and Indian Philosophy. State University of New York Press. pp. 1–5. ISBN 978-0-7914-1281-7. OCLC 24953669. Archived from the original on 14 January 2020. Retrieved 11 November 2018.
- ^ John Koller (2013). «Shankara». In Chad Meister and Paul Copan (ed.). Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203813010. ISBN 978-1-136-69685-5. Archived from the original on 12 November 2018. Retrieved 13 November 2018.
- ^ Johnson, W. J. (2009). «darśana». Oxford Reference. Archived from the original on 9 March 2021. From: Johnson, W. J., ed. (2009). «darśan(a)». A Dictionary of Hinduism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acref/9780198610250.001.0001. ISBN 9780191726705. Archived from the original on 3 September 2020.
- ^ «Epistemology in Classical Indian Philosophy». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2021.
- ^ Sedlmeier, Peter; Srinivas, Kunchapudi (2016). «How do Theories of Cognition and Consciousness in Ancient Indian Thought Systems Relate to Current Western Theorizing and Research?». Frontiers in Psychology. 7: 343. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2016.00343. PMC 4791389. PMID 27014150.
- ^ «What Erwin Schrödinger Said About the Upanishads – the Wire Science».
- ^ Young, William A. (2005). The World’s Religions: Worldviews and Contemporary Issues. Pearson Prentice Hall. pp. 61–64, 78–79. ISBN 978-0-13-183010-3. Archived from the original on 17 December 2019. Retrieved 10 November 2018.
- ^ Mittal, Sushil; Thursby, Gene (2017). Religions of India: An Introduction. Taylor & Francis. pp. 3–5, 15–18, 53–55, 63–67, 85–88, 93–98, 107–15. ISBN 978-1-134-79193-4. Archived from the original on 17 December 2019. Retrieved 11 November 2018.
- ^ Bowker, John (1999). The Oxford Dictionary of World Religions. Oxford University Press, Incorporated. p. 259. ISBN 978-0-19-866242-6.
- ^ Doniger, Wendy (2014). On Hinduism. Oxford University Press. p. 46. ISBN 978-0-19-936008-6. Archived from the original on 30 January 2017. Retrieved 25 December 2016.
- ^ Kesarcodi-Watson, Ian (1978). «Hindu Metaphysics and Its Philosophies: Śruti and Darsána». International Philosophical Quarterly. 18 (4): 413–432. doi:10.5840/ipq197818440.
- ^ Chadha, M. (2015). Oppy, G. (ed.). The Routledge Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy of Religion. London: Routledge. pp. 127–28. ISBN 978-1844658312.
- ^ Frazier, Jessica (2011). The Continuum companion to Hindu studies. London: Continuum. pp. 1–15. ISBN 978-0-8264-9966-0.
- ^ Olson, Carl (2007). The Many Colors of Hinduism: A Thematic-historical Introduction. Rutgers University Press. pp. 101–19. ISBN 978-0813540689.
- ^ Deutsch, Eliot S. (2000). «Karma as a ‘Convenient Fiction’ in the Advaita Vedānta». In Perrett, R. (ed.). Philosophy of Religion: Indian Philosophy. Vol. 4. Routledge. pp. 245–48. ISBN 978-0815336112.
- ^ Grimes, John A. (January 1996). A Concise Dictionary of Indian Philosophy: Sanskrit Terms Defined in English. Albany: State University of New York Press. p. 238. ISBN 978-0791430675.
- ^ Hiltebeitel, Alf (2007). «Hinduism». In Kitagawa, J. (ed.). The Religious Traditions of Asia: Religion, History, and Culture. London: Routledge.
- ^ Minor, Robert (1986). Modern Indian Interpreters of the Bhagavad Gita. Albany: State University of New York Press. pp. 74–75, 81. ISBN 0-88706-297-0.
- ^ Doniger, Wendy (2018) [1998]. «Bhagavad Gita». Encyclopædia Britannica. Archived from the original on 21 August 2018. Retrieved 10 November 2018.
- ^ Cowell and Gough (1882, Translators), The Sarva-Darsana-Samgraha or Review of the Different Systems of Hindu Philosophy by Madhva Acharya, Trubner’s Oriental Series.
- ^ a b Bilimoria, Puruṣottama (2000). «Hindu Doubts About God: Towards a Mīmāṃsā Deconstruction». In Perrett, Roy W. (ed.). Indian Philosophy. London: Routledge. p. 88. ISBN 978-1135703226.
- ^ Bhattacharya, R (2011). Studies on the Carvaka/Lokayata. Anthem. pp. 53, 94, 141–142. ISBN 978-0857284334.
- ^ Bronkhorst, Johannes (2012). «Free will and Indian philosophy». Antiquorum Philosophia. Roma Italy. 6: 19–30.
- ^ Lochtefeld, James (2002). «Ajivika». The Illustrated Encyclopedia of Hinduism, Vol. 1: A–M. Rosen Publishing. p. 22. ISBN 978-0823931798.
- ^ Basham, A. L. (2009). History and Doctrines of the Ajivikas – a Vanished Indian Religion, Motilal Banarsidass. Chapter 1. ISBN 978-8120812048.
- ^ Jayatilleke, K. N. (2010). Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge. pp. 246–49, note 385 onwards. ISBN 978-8120806191.
- ^ Dundas, Paul (2002). The Jains (2nd ed.). London: Routledge. pp. 1–19, 40–44. ISBN 978-0415266055.
- ^ Hemacandra (1998). The Lives of the Jain Elders. Oxford University Press. pp. 258–60. ISBN 978-0-19-283227-6. Archived from the original on 23 December 2016. Retrieved 19 November 2018.
- ^ Tiwari, Kedar Nath (1983). Comparative Religion. Motilal Banarsidass. pp. 78–83. ISBN 978-81-208-0293-3. Archived from the original on 24 December 2016. Retrieved 19 November 2018.
- ^ Jaini, Padmanabh S. (1998) [1979]. The Jaina Path of Purification. Motilal Banarsidass. pp. 81–83. ISBN 81-208-1578-5. Archived from the original on 16 February 2020. Retrieved 19 November 2018.
- ^ Umāsvāti (1994) [c. 2nd – 5th century]. That Which Is: Tattvartha Sutra. Translated by Tatia, N. HarperCollins. pp. xvii–xviii. ISBN 978-0-06-068985-8. Archived from the original on 6 August 2020.
- ^ «What Erwin Schrödinger Said About the Upanishads – the Wire Science».
- ^ Westerhoff 2018, p. 13.
- ^ Westerhoff 2018, p. 8.
- ^ Buswell, Robert E. Jr.; Lopez, Donald S. Jr. (2013). The Princeton Dictionary of Buddhism. Princeton University Press. pp. 42–47. ISBN 978-1-4008-4805-8. Archived from the original on 17 May 2020. Retrieved 10 November 2018.
- ^ Westerhoff 2018, p. 37.
- ^ Westerhoff 2018, p. xxiv.
- ^ Dreyfus, Georges B. J. (1997). Recognizing Reality: Dharmakirti’s Philosophy and Its Tibetan Interpretations (Suny Series in Buddhist Studies). p. 22.
- ^ JeeLoo Liu. Tian-tai Metaphysics vs. Hua-yan Metaphysics A Comparative Study.
- ^ Garfield, Jay L.; Edelglass, William, eds. (2011). «Chinese Philosophy». The Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780195328998.
- ^ Ebrey, Patricia (2010). The Cambridge Illustrated History of China. New York: Cambridge University Press. p. 42.
- ^ O’Brien, Barbara (25 June 2019). «How Buddhism Came to China: A History of the First Thousand Years». Learn Religions. Archived from the original on 27 January 2021. Retrieved 21 January 2021.
- ^ «Chinese Religions and Philosophies». Asia Society. Archived from the original on 16 January 2021. Retrieved 21 January 2021.
- ^ Perez, Louis G. (1998). The History of Japan. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press. pp. 57–59. ISBN 978-0-313-30296-1.
- ^ Janz, Bruce B. (2009). Philosophy in an African Place. Plymouth, UK: Lexington Books. pp. 74–79.
- ^ a b Whiteley, Peter M. (1998). «Native American philosophy». Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Taylor & Francis. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-N078-1. ISBN 9780415250696. Archived from the original on 6 August 2020.
- ^ Pierotti, Raymond (2003). «Communities as both Ecological and Social entities in Native American thought» (PDF). Native American Symposium 5. Durant, OK: Southeastern Oklahoma State University. Archived from the original (PDF) on 4 April 2016.
- ^ Portilla, Miguel León (1990). Use of «Tlamatini» in Aztec Thought and Culture: A Study of the Ancient Nahuatl Mind – Miguel León Portilla. ISBN 9780806122953. Archived from the original on 17 December 2019. Retrieved 12 December 2014.
- ^ a b Leonardo Esteban Figueroa Helland (2012). Indigenous Philosophy and World Politics: Cosmopolitical Contributions from across the Americas (PDF) (PhD dissertation). Arizona State University. Archived (PDF) from the original on 18 November 2021.
- ^ a b c d Maffie, James (March 2002). «Why Care about Nezahualcoyotl? Veritism and Nahua Philosophy». Philosophy of the Social Sciences. Sage Publications. 32 (1): 71–91. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.878.7615. doi:10.1177/004839310203200104. S2CID 144901245. Archived from the original on 18 November 2021.
- ^ a b «Aztec Philosophy». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 25 May 2020. Retrieved 25 December 2016.
- ^ a b Yeakel, John A. (Fall 1983). «Accountant-Historians of the Incas» (PDF). Accounting Historians Journal. 10 (2): 39–51. doi:10.2308/0148-4184.10.2.39. Archived (PDF) from the original on 12 November 2021.
- ^ a b Adames, Hector Y.; Chavez-Dueñas, Nayeli Y. (2016). Cultural Foundations and Interventions in Latino/a Mental Health: History, Theory and within Group Differences. Routledge. pp. 20–21.
- ^ a b c Maffie, James (2013). «Pre-Columbian Philosophies». A Companion to Latin American Philosophy. By Nuccetelli, Susana; Schutte, Ofelia; Bueno, Otávio. Wiley Blackwell.
- ^ Webb, Hillary S. (2012). Yanantin and Masintin in the Andean World: Complementary Dualism in Modern Peru.
- ^ Plantinga, Alvin (2014). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Religion and Science (Spring 2014 ed.). Archived from the original on 18 March 2019. Retrieved 25 April 2016.
- ^ Kelly, Michael (Editor in Chief) (1998) Encyclopedia of Aesthetics. New York, Oxford, Oxford University Press. 4 vol. p. ix. ISBN 978-0-19-511307-5.
- ^ Riedel, Tom. «[Review:] Encyclopedia of Aesthetics» (PDF). Art Documentation. 18 (2). Archived from the original (PDF) on 13 February 2006.
- ^ «Aesthetic». Merriam-Webster dictionary. Retrieved 9 May 2020.
- ^ Zangwill, Nick (2019) [2003]. «Aesthetic Judgment». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (revised ed.). Archived from the original on 2 August 2019. Retrieved 9 May 2020.
- ^ «aesthetic». Lexico. Oxford University Press and Dictionary.com. Archived from the original on 6 August 2020.
- ^ Mill, John Stuart (1863). Utilitarianism. London: Parker, Son, and Bourn, West Strand. p. 51. OCLC 78070085.
- ^ a b «Ethics». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 18 January 2018. Retrieved 6 July 2020.
- ^ a b c d «Major Ethical Perspectives». saylordotorg.github.io. Archived from the original on 21 January 2021. Retrieved 21 January 2021.
- ^ «Epistemology». Encyclopædia Britannica. Archived from the original on 10 July 2019. Retrieved 22 June 2020.
- ^ a b c d «Epistemology». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 21 July 2020. Retrieved 30 June 2020.
- ^ a b c d Steup, Matthias; Neta, Ram (2020). «Epistemology». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 20 January 2021. Retrieved 21 January 2021.
- ^ van Inwagen, Peter; Sullivan, Meghan (2020). «Metaphysics». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 16 September 2018. Retrieved 21 January 2021.
- ^ Alina, Bradford (July 2017). «Deductive Reasoning vs. Inductive Reasoning». Live Science. Archived from the original on 28 January 2021. Retrieved 21 January 2021.
- ^ Carnap, Rudolf (1953). «Inductive Logic and Science». Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. 80 (3): 189–197. doi:10.2307/20023651. JSTOR 20023651.
- ^ Schroeder, Mark (2021). «Value Theory». In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2021 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 31 March 2021. Retrieved 27 March 2021.
In its broadest sense, ‘value theory’ is a catch-all label used to encompass all branches of moral philosophy, social and political philosophy, aesthetics, and sometimes feminist philosophy and the philosophy of religion – whatever areas of philosophy are deemed to encompass some ‘evaluative’ aspect.
- ^ Louth, Andrew; Thielicke, Helmut (2014) [1999]. «Relationship to Philosophy | Theology». Encyclopædia Britannica. Archived from the original on 6 August 2020.
- ^ Charles L. Griswold Jr. (2010). Platonic Writings/Platonic Readings. Penn State Press. pp. 144–146. ISBN 978-0271044811. Archived from the original on 1 July 2020. Retrieved 26 July 2021.
- ^ Martin Heidegger (1956). Was Ist Das – die Philosophie?. Rowman & Littlefield. p. 21. ISBN 978-0808403197. Archived from the original on 12 August 2021. Retrieved 26 July 2021.
- ^ Kant, Immanuel (2012). Kant: Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (2nd ed.). Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9781107401068.
Ancient Greek philosophy was divided into three branches of knowledge: natural science, ethics, and logic.
- ^ Del Soldato, Eva (2020). «Natural Philosophy in the Renaissance». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 27 November 2020. Retrieved 21 January 2021.
- ^ «Moral Philosophy». Ethics Unwrapped. Archived from the original on 27 November 2020. Retrieved 21 January 2021.
- ^ Sextus Empiricus. Against the Logicians. Book I, Section 16.
- ^ Cicero. Academica. Book I, Section 1.
- ^ McKeon, R. «Methodology (Philosophy)». New Catholic Encyclopedia. Archived from the original on 30 April 2022. Retrieved 18 April 2022.
- ^ a b c d Overgaard, Søren; D’Oro, Giuseppina (2017). «Introduction». The Cambridge Companion to Philosophical Methodology. Cambridge University Press. pp. 1–10. ISBN 978-1-107-54736-0. Archived from the original on 1 May 2022. Retrieved 18 April 2022.
- ^ a b c d Sandkühler, Hans Jörg, ed. (2010). «Methode/Methodologie». Enzyklopädie Philosophie. Meiner. Archived from the original on 20 March 2022. Retrieved 15 February 2022.
- ^ a b Daly, Christopher (20 July 2010). «Introduction». An Introduction to Philosophical Methods. Broadview Press. ISBN 978-1-55111-934-2. Archived from the original on 30 July 2022. Retrieved 7 June 2022.
- ^ a b Williamson, Timothy (2020). 1. Introduction. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-184724-0. Archived from the original on 7 March 2022. Retrieved 18 April 2022.
- ^ a b Ichikawa, Jonathan (3 April 2011). «Chris Daly: An Introduction to Philosophical Methods». Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. Archived from the original on 7 March 2022. Retrieved 22 February 2022.
- ^ Nado, Jennifer (1 September 2017). «How To Think About Philosophical Methodology». Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research. 34 (3): 447–463. doi:10.1007/s40961-017-0116-8. ISSN 2363-9962. S2CID 171569977. Archived from the original on 7 March 2022. Retrieved 18 April 2022.
- ^ Cappelen, Herman; Gendler, Tamar Szabó; Hawthorne, John (19 May 2016). «Preface». The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Methodology. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199668779.013.34. ISBN 978-0-19-966877-9. Archived from the original on 5 December 2020. Retrieved 18 April 2022.
- ^ Dever, Josh (19 May 2016). «What is Philosophical Methodology?». In Cappelen, Herman; Gendler, Tamar Szabó; Hawthorne, John (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Methodology. pp. 3–24. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199668779.013.34. ISBN 978-0-19-966877-9. Archived from the original on 5 December 2020. Retrieved 18 April 2022.
- ^ a b c Daly, Chris (2015). «Introduction and Historical Overview». The Palgrave Handbook of Philosophical Methods. Palgrave Macmillan UK. pp. 1–30. doi:10.1057/9781137344557_1. ISBN 978-1-137-34455-7. Archived from the original on 1 May 2022. Retrieved 18 April 2022.
- ^ Horwich, Paul (19 May 2016). «Wittgenstein’s Global Deflationism». In Cappelen, Herman; Gendler, Tamar Szabó; Hawthorne, John (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Methodology. Oxford. pp. 130–146. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199668779.013.35. ISBN 978-0-19-966877-9. Archived from the original on 5 December 2020. Retrieved 18 April 2022.
- ^ Malachowski, Alan (1 September 1993). «Methodological scepticism, metaphysics and meaning». International Journal of Philosophical Studies. 1 (2): 302–312. doi:10.1080/09672559308570774. ISSN 0967-2559. Archived from the original on 7 March 2022. Retrieved 18 April 2022.
- ^ Goldenbaum, Ursula. «Geometrical Method». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 7 March 2022. Retrieved 17 February 2022.
- ^ Nadler, Steven (2006). «The geometric method». Spinoza’s ‘Ethics’: An Introduction. Cambridge University Press. pp. 35–51. ISBN 978-0-521-83620-3. Archived from the original on 7 March 2022. Retrieved 18 April 2022.
- ^ Cogan, John. «Phenomenological Reduction, The». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 4 April 2020. Retrieved 27 February 2022.
- ^ a b Eder, Anna-Maria A.; Lawler, Insa; van Riel, Raphael (1 March 2020). «Philosophical methods under scrutiny: introduction to the special issue philosophical methods». Synthese. 197 (3): 915–923. doi:10.1007/s11229-018-02051-2. ISSN 1573-0964. S2CID 54631297.
- ^ REYNOLDS, JACK (4 August 2010). «Common Sense and Philosophical Methodology: Some Metaphilosophical Reflections on Analytic Philosophy and Deleuze». The Philosophical Forum. 41 (3): 231–258. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9191.2010.00361.x. hdl:10536/DRO/DU:30061043. ISSN 0031-806X. Archived from the original on 7 March 2022. Retrieved 18 April 2022.
- ^ «philosophy of common sense». Encyclopædia Britannica. Archived from the original on 7 March 2022. Retrieved 27 February 2022.
- ^ Parker-Ryan, Sally. «Ordinary Language Philosophy». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 7 March 2022. Retrieved 28 February 2022.
- ^ «ordinary language analysis». Encyclopædia Britannica. Archived from the original on 7 March 2022. Retrieved 28 February 2022.
- ^ «Intuitionism (ethics)». Encyclopædia Britannica. Archived from the original on 7 March 2022. Retrieved 28 February 2022.
- ^ Brown, James Robert; Fehige, Yiftach (2019). «Thought Experiments». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 21 November 2017. Retrieved 29 October 2021.
- ^ Goffi, Jean-Yves; Roux, Sophie (2011). «On the Very Idea of a Thought Experiment». Thought Experiments in Methodological and Historical Contexts. Brill: 165–191. doi:10.1163/ej.9789004201767.i-233.35. ISBN 9789004201774. Archived from the original on 30 October 2021. Retrieved 18 April 2022.
- ^ Daniels, Norman (2020). «Reflective Equilibrium». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 22 February 2022. Retrieved 28 February 2022.
- ^ Little, Daniel (1984). «Reflective Equilibrium and Justification». Southern Journal of Philosophy. 22 (3): 373–387. doi:10.1111/j.2041-6962.1984.tb00354.x. Archived from the original on 1 May 2022. Retrieved 18 April 2022.
- ^ McDermid, Douglas. «Pragmatism». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 23 May 2019. Retrieved 22 February 2022.
- ^ Bawden, H. Heath (1904). «What is Pragmatism?». The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods. 1 (16): 421–427. doi:10.2307/2011902. ISSN 0160-9335. JSTOR 2011902. Archived from the original on 7 March 2022. Retrieved 18 April 2022.
- ^ Knobe, Joshua; Nichols, Shaun (2017). «Experimental Philosophy». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 19 March 2020. Retrieved 1 March 2022.
- ^ Plakias, Alexandra (3 February 2015). «Experimental Philosophy». Oxford Handbooks Online. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199935314.013.17. ISBN 978-0-19-993531-4. Archived from the original on 21 January 2022. Retrieved 1 March 2022.
- ^ McGinn, Colin (1993). Problems in Philosophy: The Limits of Inquiry (1st ed.). Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-55786-475-8.
- ^ Chalmers, David (7 May 2013). Why isn’t there more progress in philosophy?. Moral Sciences Club (video lecture). Faculty of Philosophy, University of Cambridge. Archived from the original on 12 June 2017. Retrieved 8 May 2020.
- ^ Brewer, Talbot (2011). The Retrieval of Ethics (1st ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-969222-4.
- ^ «Where Can Philosophy Take Me? | Philosophy». University of Kentucky College of Arts & Sciences. Archived from the original on 10 April 2016. Retrieved 2 May 2016.
- ^ «Why Study Philosophy? An Unofficial ‘Daily Nous’ Affiliate». WhyStudyPhilosophy.com. Archived from the original on 29 April 2016. Retrieved 2 May 2016.
- ^ Cropper, Carol Marie (26 December 1997). «Philosophers Find the Degree Pays Off in Life And in Work». The New York Times. ISSN 0362-4331. Archived from the original on 28 January 2017. Retrieved 2 May 2016.
- ^ «Famous Philosophy Majors». Mansfield University Department of Marketing. Archived from the original on 31 March 2016. Retrieved 2 May 2016.
- ^ Weinberg, Justin (8 December 2014). «Famous Philosophy Majors Poster (updated with new link)». Daily Nous. Archived from the original on 14 May 2016. Retrieved 2 May 2016.
- ^ White, Curtis (2014). The Science Delusion: Asking the Big Questions in a Culture of Easy Answers. Brooklyn, NY: Melville House. ISBN 9781612193908.
- ^ Schuessler, Jennifer (4 October 2016). «Canadian Philosopher Wins $1 Million Prize». The New York Times. ISSN 0362-4331. Archived from the original on 15 December 2017. Retrieved 4 October 2016.
- ^ «Socrates Tenured». Rowman & Littlefield International. Archived from the original on 9 May 2016. Retrieved 25 April 2016.
- ^ Duran, Jane (2005). Eight women philosophers: theory, politics, and feminism. University of Illinois Press.
- ^ «Why I Left Academia: Philosophy’s Homogeneity Needs Rethinking – Hippo Reads». Archived from the original on 9 June 2017.
- ^ Haldane, John (June 2000). «In Memoriam: G. E. M. Anscombe (1919–2001)». The Review of Metaphysics. 53 (4): 1019–1021. JSTOR 20131480.
- ^ «Salary, Promotion, and Tenure Status of Minority and Women Faculty in U.S. Colleges and Universities». National Center for Education Statistics, Statistical Analysis Report, March 2000; U.S. Department of Education, Office of Education Research and Improvement, Report # NCES 2000–173; 1993 National Study of Postsecondary Faculty (NSOPF:93). See also «Characteristics and Attitudes of Instructional Faculty and Staff in the Humanities». National Center For Education Statistics, E.D. Tabs, July 1997. U.S. Department of Education, Office of Education Research and Improvement, Report # NCES 97-973;1993 National Study of Postsecondary Faculty (NSOPF-93).
- ^ «Influential Women in Philosophy from the Last 10 Years | Academic Influence».
- ^ «Feminist History of Philosophy». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2021.
Bibliography
- Edwards, Paul, ed. (1967). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Macmillan & Free Press.
- Kant, Immanuel (1881). Critique of Pure Reason. Macmillan.
- Baldwin, Thomas, ed. (2003). The Cambridge History of Philosophy 1870–1945. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-59104-1.
- Copenhaver, Brian P.; Schmitt, Charles B. (1992). Renaissance philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-219203-5.
- Lindberg, David C. (2007). «Science before the Greeks». The beginnings of Western science: the European Scientific tradition in philosophical, religious, and institutional context (Second ed.). Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago Press. pp. 1–27. ISBN 978-0-226-48205-7.
- Nadler, Steven (2008). A Companion to Early Modern Philosophy. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-0-470-99883-0.
- Rutherford, Donald (2006). The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82242-8.
- Schmitt, C.B.; Skinner, Quentin, eds. (1988). The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-39748-3.
- Kenny, Anthony (2012). A New History of Western Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-958988-3.
- Honderich, T., ed. (1995). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-866132-0.
- Bunnin, Nicholas; Tsui-James, Eric, eds. (2008). The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-0-470-99787-1.
- Copleston, Frederick Charles (1953). A history of philosophy: volume III: Ockham to Suárez. Paulist Press. ISBN 978-0-8091-0067-5.
- Leaman, Oliver; Morewedge, Parviz (2000). «Islamic philosophy modern». In Craig, Edward (ed.). Concise Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Psychology Press. ISBN 978-0-415-22364-5.
- Buccellati, Giorgio (1981). «Wisdom and Not: The Case of Mesopotamia». Journal of the American Oriental Society. 101 (1): 35–47. doi:10.2307/602163. JSTOR 602163.
- Philosophy before the Greeks. The Pursuit of Truth in Ancient Babylonia. Princeton University Press. 2015. ISBN 978-0691157184.
- Westerhoff, Jan (2018). The Golden Age of Indian Buddhist Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Further reading
General introduction
- Aristotle (1941). Richard McKeon (ed.). The Basic Works of Aristotle. New York: Random House.
- Blumenau, Ralph. Philosophy and Living. ISBN 978-0-907845-33-1
- Craig, Edward. Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction. ISBN 978-0-19-285421-6
- Harrison-Barbet, Anthony, Mastering Philosophy. ISBN 978-0-333-69343-8
- Russell, Bertrand. The Problems of Philosophy. ISBN 978-0-19-511552-9
- Sinclair, Alistair J. What is Philosophy? An Introduction, 2008, ISBN 978-1-903765-94-4
- Sober, Elliott. (2001). Core Questions in Philosophy: A Text with Readings. Upper Saddle River, Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0-13-189869-1
- Solomon, Robert C. Big Questions: A Short Introduction to Philosophy. ISBN 978-0-534-16708-0
- Warburton, Nigel. Philosophy: The Basics. ISBN 978-0-415-14694-4
- Nagel, Thomas. What Does It All Mean? A Very Short Introduction to Philosophy. ISBN 978-0-19-505292-3
- Classics of Philosophy (Vols. 1, 2, & 3) by Louis P. Pojman
- Cottingham, John. Western Philosophy: An Anthology. 2nd ed. Malden, MA: Blackwell Pub., 2008. Print. Blackwell Philosophy Anthologies.
- Tarnas, Richard. The Passion of the Western Mind: Understanding the Ideas That Have Shaped Our World View. ISBN 978-0-345-36809-6
Topical introductions
African
- Imbo, Samuel Oluoch. An Introduction to African Philosophy. ISBN 978-0-8476-8841-8
Eastern
- A Source Book in Indian Philosophy by Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan, Charles A. Moore
- Hamilton, Sue. Indian Philosophy: a Very Short Introduction. ISBN 978-0-19-285374-5
- Kupperman, Joel J. Classic Asian Philosophy: A Guide to the Essential Texts. ISBN 978-0-19-513335-6
- Lee, Joe and Powell, Jim. Eastern Philosophy For Beginners. ISBN 978-0-86316-282-4
- Smart, Ninian. World Philosophies. ISBN 978-0-415-22852-7
- Copleston, Frederick. Philosophy in Russia: From Herzen to Lenin and Berdyaev. ISBN 978-0-268-01569-5
Islamic
- Medieval Islamic Philosophical Writings edited by Muhammad Ali Khalidi
- Leaman, Oliver (14 April 2000). A Brief Introduction to Islamic Philosophy. ISBN 978-0-7456-1960-6.
- Corbin, Henry (23 June 2014) [1993]. History Of Islamic Philosophy. Translated by Sherrard, Liadain; Sherrard, Philip. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-135-19888-6.
- Aminrazavi, Mehdi Amin Razavi; Nasr, Seyyed Hossein; Nasr, PH.D., Seyyed Hossein (16 December 2013). The Islamic Intellectual Tradition in Persia. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-136-78105-6.
Historical introductions
General
- Oizerman, Teodor (1988). The Main Trends in Philosophy. A Theoretical Analysis of the History of Philosophy (PDF). translated by H. Campbell Creighton, M.A., Oxon (2nd ed.). Moscow: Progress Publishers. ISBN 978-5-01-000506-1. Archived from the original (DjVu, etc.) on 6 March 2012. Retrieved 20 January 2011. First published in Russian as Главные философские направления.
- Higgins, Kathleen M. and Solomon, Robert C. A Short History of Philosophy. ISBN 978-0-19-510196-6
- Durant, Will, Story of Philosophy: The Lives and Opinions of the World’s Greatest Philosophers, Pocket, 1991, ISBN 978-0-671-73916-4
- Oizerman, Teodor (1973). Problems of the History of Philosophy. translated from Russian by Robert Daglish (1st ed.). Moscow: Progress Publishers. Archived from the original on 6 July 2011. Retrieved 20 January 2011. First published in Russian as Проблемы историко-философской науки.
Ancient
- Knight, Kelvin. Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre. ISBN 978-0-7456-1977-4
Medieval
- The Phenomenology Reader by Dermot Moran, Timothy Mooney
- Kim, J. and Ernest Sosa, Ed. (1999). Metaphysics: An Anthology. Blackwell Philosophy Anthologies. Oxford, Blackwell Publishers Ltd.
- Husserl, Edmund; Welton, Donn (1999). The Essential Husserl: Basic Writings in Transcendental Phenomenology. Indiana University Press. ISBN 978-0-253-21273-3.
Modern and contemporary
- The English Philosophers from Bacon to Mill by Edwin Arthur
- European Philosophers from Descartes to Nietzsche by Monroe Beardsley
- Existentialism: Basic Writings (Second Edition) by Charles Guignon, Derk Pereboom
- Curley, Edwin, A Spinoza Reader, Princeton, 1994, ISBN 978-0-691-00067-1
- Bullock, Alan, R.B. Woodings, and John Cumming, eds. The Fontana Dictionary of Modern Thinkers, in series, Fontana Original[s]. Hammersmith, Eng.: Fontana Press, 1992 [1983]. xxv, 867 p. ISBN 978-0-00-636965-3
- Scruton, Roger. A Short History of Modern Philosophy. ISBN 978-0-415-26763-2
- Contemporary Analytic Philosophy: Core Readings by James Baillie
- Appiah, Kwame Anthony. Thinking it Through – An Introduction to Contemporary Philosophy, 2003, ISBN 978-0-19-513458-2
- Critchley, Simon. Continental Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction. ISBN 978-0-19-285359-2
Reference works
- Chan, Wing-tsit (1963). A Source Book in Chinese Philosophy. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-01964-2.
- Huang, Siu-chi (1999). Essentials of Neo-Confucianism: Eight Major Philosophers of the Song and Ming Periods. Greenwood Publishing Group. ISBN 978-0-313-26449-8.
- The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy by Robert Audi
- The Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (10 vols.) edited by Edward Craig, Luciano Floridi (available online by subscription); or
- The Concise Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy edited by Edward Craig (an abridgement)
- Edwards, Paul, ed. (1967). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Macmillan & Free Press.; in 1996, a ninth supplemental volume appeared that updated the classic 1967 encyclopedia.
- International Directory of Philosophy and Philosophers. Charlottesville, Philosophy Documentation Center.
- Directory of American Philosophers. Charlottesville, Philosophy Documentation Center.
- Routledge History of Philosophy (10 vols.) edited by John Marenbon
- History of Philosophy (9 vols.) by Frederick Copleston
- A History of Western Philosophy (5 vols.) by W.T. Jones
- History of Italian Philosophy (2 vols.) by Eugenio Garin. Translated from Italian and Edited by Giorgio Pinton. Introduction by Leon Pompa.
- Encyclopaedia of Indian Philosophies (8 vols.), edited by Karl H. Potter et al. (first 6 volumes out of print)
- Indian Philosophy (2 vols.) by Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan
- A History of Indian Philosophy (5 vols.) by Surendranath Dasgupta
- History of Chinese Philosophy (2 vols.) by Fung Yu-lan, Derk Bodde
- Instructions for Practical Living and Other Neo-Confucian Writings by Wang Yang-ming by Chan, Wing-tsit
- Encyclopedia of Chinese Philosophy edited by Antonio S. Cua
- Encyclopedia of Eastern Philosophy and Religion by Ingrid Fischer-Schreiber, Franz-Karl Ehrhard, Kurt Friedrichs
- Companion Encyclopedia of Asian Philosophy by Brian Carr, Indira Mahalingam
- A Concise Dictionary of Indian Philosophy: Sanskrit Terms Defined in English by John A. Grimes
- History of Islamic Philosophy edited by Seyyed Hossein Nasr, Oliver Leaman
- History of Jewish Philosophy edited by Daniel H. Frank, Oliver Leaman
- A History of Russian Philosophy: From the Tenth to the Twentieth Centuries by Valerii Aleksandrovich Kuvakin
- Ayer, A.J. et al., Ed. (1994) A Dictionary of Philosophical Quotations. Blackwell Reference Oxford. Oxford, Basil Blackwell Ltd.
- Blackburn, S., Ed. (1996)The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
- Mautner, T., Ed. The Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy. London, Penguin Books.
- Runes, D., ed. (1942). The Dictionary of Philosophy. New York: The Philosophical Library, Inc. Archived from the original on 24 April 2014. Retrieved 27 December 2005.
- Angeles, P.A., Ed. (1992). The HarperCollins Dictionary of Philosophy. New York, Harper Perennial.
- Bunnin, Nicholas; Tsui-James, Eric, eds. (15 April 2008). The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-0-470-99787-1.
- Hoffman, Eric, Ed. (1997) Guidebook for Publishing Philosophy. Charlottesville, Philosophy Documentation Center.
- Popkin, R.H. (1999). The Columbia History of Western Philosophy. New York, Columbia University Press.
- Bullock, Alan, and Oliver Stallybrass, jt. eds. The Harper Dictionary of Modern Thought. New York: Harper & Row, 1977. xix, 684 p. N.B.: First published in England under the title, «The Fontana Dictionary of Modern Thought«. ISBN 978-0-06-010578-5
- Reese, W.L. Dictionary of Philosophy and Religion: Eastern and Western Thought. Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1980. iv, 644 p. ISBN 978-0-391-00688-1
External links
- Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project
- PhilPapers – a comprehensive directory of online philosophical articles and books by academic philosophers
- Philosophy at Curlie
- Philosophy (review)
- Philosophy Documentation Center
- Popular Philosophy
Asked by: Prof. Jacey Orn
Score: 4.6/5
(44 votes)
The original meaning of the word philosophy comes from the Greek roots philo- meaning «love» and -sophos, or «wisdom.» When someone studies philosophy they want to understand how and why people do certain things and how to live a good life.
What is EtymologicAl philosophy?
Philosophia means ‘love of knowledge‘, ‘pursuit of wisdom’, ‘systematic investigation. … English word ‘Philosophy’ comes from a combination of two Greek word, which are ‘Philo’ and ‘Sophia’.
What is philosophy and its EtymologicAl definition?
EtymologicAl mEAning of philosophy • The word philosophy is derived from Greek words – Pholos and Sophia. Philos means love and Sophia means wisdom. • Thus philosophy means love of wisdom. In this way search of wisdom or truth is called philosophy, and the man who engages himself in this search is called a philosopher.
What is the real definition of philosophy?
Quite literally, the term «philosophy» means, «love of wisdom.» In a broad sense, philosophy is an activity people undertake when they seek to understand fundamental truths about themselves, the world in which they live, and their relationships to the world and to each other.
What is philosophy in simple words?
Philosophy is the study or creation of theories about basic things such as the nature of existence, knowledge, and thought, or about how people should live. … A philosophy is a particular set of ideas that a philosopher has.
33 related questions found
What is the modern definition of philosophy?
The term generally refers to a broad philosophical tradition characterized by an emphasis on clarity and argument (often achieved via modern formal logic and analysis of language) and a respect for the natural sciences.
What does etymological mean?
Something etymological relates to the way a word originated. … Etymology is the history of words, including the way they’ve changed through the years. The adjective etymological describes anything that has to do with etymology. Etymological research of English words often leads back to Old English, Greek, or Latin roots.
What are two definitions of philosophy?
1 : the study of the basic ideas about knowledge, right and wrong, reasoning, and the value of things. 2 : a specific set of ideas of a person or a group Greek philosophy. 3 : a set of ideas about how to do something or how to live Live and let live—that’s my philosophy.
What is the etymological definition of ethics?
The word «ethics» is derived from the Greek word ethos (character), and from the Latin word mores (customs). … In philosophy, ethics defines what is good for the individual and for society and establishes the nature of duties that people owe themselves and one another.
What are the difference between etymological and technical philosophy?
Differences in etymological & technical philosophy are as follows: Etymology is the study of the history of words. … Technical philosophy is a formal area of discipline which contains tested and verified beliefs, assumptions, principles, or ideas in some clearly identifiable and special form of experience.
What is the etymological meaning of psychology?
The word ‘psychology’ is derived from two Greek words, ‘psyche’, meaning the mind, soul or spirit and ‘logos’, meaning discourse or to. study. These words combined produce the ‘Study of the mind’.
What are the differences between etymological and technical?
is that etymological is of or relating to etymology while technical is of or pertaining to the useful or mechanic arts, or to any academic, legal, science, engineering, business, or the like terminology with specific and precise meaning or (frequently, as a degree of distinction) shades of meaning; specially …
What is the etymological definition of ethics How is it related to morality?
The term ethics is derived from the Greek word ethikos which itself is derived from the Greek word ethos, meaning custom or character. In philosophy, ethical behavior is that which is “good.” The field of ethics or moral philosophy involves developing, defending, and recommending concepts of right and wrong behavior.
What is the simple definition of ethics?
At its simplest, ethics is a system of moral principles. … Ethics is concerned with what is good for individuals and society and is also described as moral philosophy. The term is derived from the Greek word ethos which can mean custom, habit, character or disposition.
What is the complete definition of ethics?
ethics, also called moral philosophy, the discipline concerned with what is morally good and bad and morally right and wrong. The term is also applied to any system or theory of moral values or principles.
What are the two types of definitions?
Definitions can be classified into two large categories, intensional definitions (which try to give the sense of a term) and extensional definitions (which try to list the objects that a term describes).
What are the 4 types of definition?
Dictionaries and social discourse both help us determine the status of such words. When in doubt, it is usually a good practice to stipulate the way in which you are using a word (or phrase). (4) Analytical definitions are the definitions most commonly prized by mathematicians and Western philosophers and scientists.
What are the five types of definitions?
The Various Types of Definitions
- The two general kinds of definitions.
- Intensional definitions.
- Extensional definitions.
- Stipulative definitions.
- Lexical definitions.
- Partitive definitions.
- Functional definitions.
- Encyclopedic definitions.
What does etymology mean?
1 : an explanation of where a word came from : the history of a word According to its etymology, the English word «dope» comes from the Dutch word «doop» (which means «sauce»). Several different etymologies have been proposed. 2 : the study of word histories an expert in etymology.
What is an example of etymology?
The definition of etymology is the source of a word, or the study of the source of specific words. An example of etymology is tracing a word back to its Latin roots.
Which is the best definition for the word etymology?
Etymology is the study of the origin of words and how the meaning of words has changed over the course of history. … “Etymology” derives from the Greek word etumos, meaning “true.” Etumologia was the study of words’ “true meanings.” This evolved into “etymology” by way of the Old French ethimologie.
What is the difference between ancient and modern philosophy?
Ancient ethics is about living a good and virtuous life according to the ethical virtues, that is, to become a virtuous person, while the modern notion of morality is primarily focused on the interests of other people and the idea of deontological constraints.
What is the importance of modern philosophy?
Philosophy is the foundation of critical thinking.
Philosophy brings the important questions to the table and works towards an answer. It encourages us to think critically about the world; it is the foundation of all knowledge and when utilized properly, can provide us with huge benefits.”
What is philosophy in your own words essay?
Philosophy is a Greek word that is often translated as “the love of wisdom.” In other words, philosophy is the study of the fundamental nature of knowledge, reality, and existence, especially when considered as an academic discipline. Applying philosophy into daily living, it can definitely help me live a better life.
Which is the best definition of ethics?
Ethics is defined as a moral philosophy or code of morals practiced by a person or group of people. An example of ethics is a the code of conduct set by a business. noun.
The word Philosophy comes from the Greek philo (love) and sophia (wisdom) and so is literally defined as “the love of wisdom”. More broadly understood, it is the study of the most basic and profound matters of human existence. Philosophical schools frequently develop in response to some perceived failure of religion to provide answers to fundamental questions.
The topic of exactly when and where philosophy first began to develop is still debated, but the simplest answer is that it would have begun – at any place in the distant past – the first time someone asked why they were born, what their purpose was, and how they were supposed to understand their lives. The term philosophy may apply to a formalized secular or religious system of thought, a personal construct, or a communal understanding of proper attitude and conduct, but in each case, the purpose of the system is to answer such questions.
Philosophical systems are thought to have developed first in the East, and a working outline proceeds from Mesopotamia to Rome and on to the present:
YouTube
Follow us on YouTube!
- Egypt by c. 4000 BCE: depictions of gods and the afterlife appear on tomb walls
- Mesopotamia by c. 2150 BCE: written form of the philosophical narrative of The Epic of Gilgamesh
- India c. 1500 — c. 500 BCE: the Vedic Period
- Persia by c. 1500 BCE: development of Zoroastrianism
- China c. 1046-256 BCE: the Zhou Dynasty
- Greece c. 585-322 BCE: Time of Thales of Miletus to the death of Aristotle of Stagira
- Rome c. 155 BCE onwards: Beginning with the arrival of Stoicism in Rome.
Philosophical systems would continue in Europe during the Middle Ages (c. 476-1500 CE), primarily focused on Christian teachings, and would develop further during the Renaissance in the West. In the East, Islamic scholars after the 7th century CE as well as those of other faiths continued to develop their own systems. Philosophical schools have continued on this same trajectory up through the modern day as people continue to ask the same fundamental questions as their ancient ancestors and work to develop systems of thought to answer them.
Historical Overview
When religion fails to fully answer a people’s questions or address their needs, the people turn to philosophy.
A philosophical system may develop independently but usually is a response to religion; when religion fails to fully answer a people’s questions or address their needs, the people turn to philosophy. People’s existential questions traditionally have been answered by the development of religious systems which assured them of the existence of supernatural entities (gods, divine spirits, one’s departed ancestors) who created them, cared for them, and watched over them. These belief structures, institutionalized as part of a culture, work to form a cohesive cultural understanding of one’s place in the world and the philosophies which developed in response to that understanding either sought to explain it more clearly or replace it with a new paradigm.
Although it is impossible to determine, it seems probable that philosophy was already established in Egypt by c. 4000 BCE, the date depictions of gods and the afterlife of the Field of Reeds first begin appearing on tomb walls. It developed in Mesopotamia at some point before the time The Epic of Gilgamesh was committed to writing between c. 2150-1400 BCE. In India, philosophy develops during the Vedic Period between c. 1500 — c. 500 BCE with the Upanishads. At about the same time, Zoroaster (c. 1500-1000 BCE) was developing his philosophic vision in ancient Persia while, in China, philosophy is first committed to writing during the time of the Zhou Dynasty (1046-256 BCE) and later developed during the Spring and Autumn Period (c. 772-476 BCE) and the Warring States Period (c. 481-221 BCE) in the time associated with the Hundred Schools of Thought.
Love History?
Sign up for our free weekly email newsletter!
Confucius, Buddha and Lao-Tzu Lucas (CC BY)
Philosophy in the West begins in the Ionian Greek colonies of Asia Minor with Thales of Miletus (l. c. 585 BCE) who inspired the later writers known as the Pre-Socratic philosophers whose ideas would then inform and influence the iconic works of Plato (l. 424/423-348/347 BCE) and his student Aristotle of Stagira (l. 384-322 BCE) which form the foundation of Western philosophical thought. Roman philosophy developed from the Greek after the arrival in the city of Diogenes of Babylon (l. c. 230 — c. 140 BCE) in 155 BCE, a stoic philosopher from the Athenian school founded by Zeno of Citium (l. c. 336-265 BCE) whose system was inspired by Socrates. Stoicism would afterwards become the most popular philosophical system in Rome and inform aspects of Christian philosophical systems which came later.
Philosophy in Egypt & Mesopotamia
The earliest philosophical system seems to have developed in Egypt as a response to the religious vision of a paradise after death known as the Field of Reeds, a mirror image of one’s life on earth, where the souls of the justified dead would live eternally. The question which seems to have inspired Egyptian philosophy is how one should live in order to ensure a place in this paradise. Evidence of the development of an answer to this question comes from tomb paintings c. 4000 BCE instructing people on where they came from, why they existed, and how to live well and attain paradise.
Egyptian philosophy developed the concept of ma’at (harmony and balance) as the central value by which one could live the best life and be assured of paradise but then addressed itself to the aspects of the soul, the concept of immortality, the possibility of reincarnation, and the nature of the divine.
The Offering of Ma’at Terry Feuerborn (CC BY-NC-SA)
In Mesopotamia, the people understood themselves as co-workers with the gods. As in Egypt, the gods had created humanity and humans owed them a debt of gratitude which was paid through worship and proper behavior. In keeping with other ancient religious systems, the Mesopotamians understood their gods as operating on a quid pro quo (“this for that”) basis, which worked well as long as the individual felt the agreement was being honored, but when it seemed to fail, one naturally questioned its validity, and this sort of existential crisis inspires philosophical inquiry.
This situation is illustrated in The Epic of Gilgamesh in which Gilgamesh, King of Uruk, loses his best friend, Enkidu and embarks on a quest to find an escape from inevitable death. His story has been interpreted as a parable of philosophical development in that there is no evidence that Gilgamesh questions his relationship with the gods until the death of Enkidu which requires answers his religious beliefs cannot provide.
Indian Philosophy
In India, philosophy developed in response to the Vedas, the scriptures of Hinduism (known as Sanatan Dharma, “Eternal Order”, to adherents), in the form of the Upanishads (the earliest written c. 800-500 BCE). The Vedas were understood as the emanations of the Universe, the literal words of God, and the Upanishads were composed to clarify and explain aspects of this message.
Kena Upanishad Ms Sarah Welch (CC BY-SA)
Around 600 BCE, a social and religious reform movement in the region resulted in the development of other philosophical systems which rejected orthodox Hinduism. These included the materialist school of Charvaka (c. 600 BCE), the system of Jainism (formulated by Mahavira/Vardhamana, l. c. 599-527 BCE), and Buddhism (founded by Siddhartha Gautama, the Buddha, l. c. 563 — c. 483 BCE). Although Jainism and Buddhism would later take on religious dimensions, they were originally philosophical schools of thought, although it should be noted there was no distinction between “religious” and “philosophical” thought in Asia at that time nor is there in the present.
Persian Philosophy
Persian philosophy was almost certainly already developed before c. 1500 BCE as evidenced by the Avesta (Zoroastrian scriptures) which draws on concepts from the polytheistic Early Iranian Religion. Zoroaster conceived of a new religious paradigm of a single god, Ahura Mazda, creator and sustainer of the universe, whose supernatural adversary was Angra Mainyu (also known as Ahriman), the lord of darkness and chaos.
A Faravahar symbol in a Fire Temple ninara (CC BY-NC-SA)
The question left unanswered by Zoroaster’s construct, however, was the source of evil and suffering in the world since Ahriman was understood as a created being and Ahura Mazda, who had no evil in him, as the source of all creation. This problem encouraged the development of the philosophical school of Zorvanism, sometime in the late Achaemenid Empire (c. 550-330 BCE) which claimed Zorvan, god of Infinite Time, created both Ahura Mazda and Ahriman and these two brother-deities were locked in an eternal struggle which human beings had no choice but to take sides in. One’s purpose in life was the exercise of free will in deciding to devote one’s self to the cause of good or evil.
Chinese Philosophy
Chinese philosophy was initially a response to social disorder as well as the failure of religious belief to explain the world & reassure people of a divine plan.
The Spring and Autumn Period and the Warring States Period in China were times of chaos as the Zhou Dynasty was declining, and Chinese philosophy was developed in response to this disorder. The early texts of Confucianism are thought to have been composed during the Zhou Dynasty and later developed by the sage Confucius (l. 551-479 BCE). Confucianism was only one belief structure of many which developed during this time referred to as the Hundred Schools of Thought and which included many others including Taoism (founded by Lao Tzu c. 500 BCE) and Legalism (founded by Han Feizi, l. c. 280-233 BCE).
These schools, and the many others, differed from each other significantly but were all an attempt to establish order in a time of chaos. The traditional understanding of Tian (heaven) as maintaining order through a mandate which legitimized a monarch’s rule could no longer be sustained as the monarchs of different states fought each other for supremacy. Chinese philosophy, then, was initially a response to social disorder as well as the failure of religious belief to explain the world and reassure people of a divine plan.
Greek Philosophy
Greek philosophy began in the 6th century BCE with Thales of Miletus who initiated it with the question “What is the basic ‘stuff’ of the universe?” (Ancient Philosophy, 8). Thales’ inquiry seems an anomaly because of the religious beliefs of his time which seem to have been meeting the needs of the people. Ancient Greek religion held that the gods had created the world and human beings and, as with other world religions of the time, questioning this basic premise was not appreciated nor encouraged. Thales seems to have avoided problems with the religious authorities by never denying the existence of gods, but this does not explain his initial impulse. Scholars suggest that, since he studied at Babylon, he most likely drew on Mesopotamian and Egyptian philosophies in formulating his own.
Thales of Miletus Peter Paul Rubens (Copyright)
Thales established the Milesian School, considered the first philosophical school in the West, and was followed by Anaximander (l. c. 610 — c. 546 BCE) and Anaximenes (l. c. 546 BCE) who rejected Thales’ claim that the First Cause was water and suggested their own. Philosophical thought then developed through the efforts of the other Pre-Socratic philosophers, finally culminating in the works of Plato and then of Aristotle. Later thinkers, notably Plotinus (l. c. 202-274 CE), would develop these concepts further in establishing the foundation of Western Philosophy.
Branches of Philosophy
The areas of interest of modern-day philosophy apply equally to the East and West but the names by which they are known were developed by the Greeks. Although various schools may break some into sub-sections, the branches of study are:
Metaphysics – The Study of Existence, so named for Aristotle’s work on the subject. Far from being a definitive term in Aristotle’s day to denote the study of philosophy or religion, the term ‘metaphysics’ was given to Aristotle’s book on the subject by his editor who placed it after his work ‘Physics’. In Greek, meta simply means ‘after’, and the title was originally only meant to clarify that the one piece came after the first. However that may be, the term has since been applied to the study of first causes, underlying form of existence, and definitions concerning the meaning of time and even the meaning of “meaning”.
Aristotle Bust, Palazzo Altemps SquinchPix.com (Copyright)
Epistemology – The Study of Knowledge (from the Greek episteme, knowledge, and logos, word). Epistemology asks how one knows what one knows, what exactly is ‘knowledge’, how can it be defined, and how can one know that the meaning one defines a word by will be the meaning another person will understand. Epistemological questions do not seem to have concerned the ancients until the subject is addressed by the Pre-Socratic philosophers of Greece and Plato after them.
Ethics – The Study of Behavior/Action (from the Greek ta ethika, on character), a term popularized by Aristotle in his Nichomachean Ethics, which he wrote for his son, Nichomachus, as a guide to living well. Ethics is concerned with morality, how one should live and upon what basis to make decisions. Ethics was a central concern of all ancient philosophies from Mesopotamia onwards in trying to determine the best way for people to live, not only for their own self-interest but the interests of the wider community and, finally, in accordance with the will of the gods.
Questions concerning how one should best live with one’s neighbors & what is owed to the community go back thousands of years.
Politics – The Study of Governance (from the Greek polis, city, and politikos, meaning ‘that which has to do with the city’). Far from simply being concerned with running a government, however, politikos also has to do with how to be a good citizen and neighbor and what one should contribute to one’s community. This branch, like all the others, was first definitively examined and popularized in the works of Aristotle in the West but questions concerning how one should best live with one’s neighbors and what is owed to the community go back thousands of years to Mesopotamian, Egyptian, Persian, and Indian texts.
Aesthetics – The Study of Art (from the Greek aisthetikos, sense/sentience, or aisthanomai, to perceive or feel). Aesthetics concerns itself with the study of beauty, perception of beauty, culture, and even nature, asking the fundamental question, “What makes something that is beautiful or meaningful ‘beautiful’ or ‘meaningful’?” Both Plato and Aristotle give answers to this question attempting to standardize objectively what is ‘beautiful’ while the famous Greek Sophist Protagoras (l. c. 485-415 BCE) argued that if one believes something to be ‘beautiful’ then it is beautiful and that all judgments are and must be subjective because any experience is relative to the one experiencing it.
These branches were not defined in this way until the time of the Greeks, but the questions they ask and seek to address were voiced by peoples throughout the Near East, South Asia, and all over the ancient world.
Conclusion
Plato attributed the vision of his philosophy to his teacher, Socrates, who wrote nothing himself. Almost all of what is known of Socrates’ life and teaching comes from Plato and another of Socrates’ students, Xenophon (l. 430 — c. 354 BCE). Whether Plato’s work accurately reflects Socrates’ teachings is unknown and will never be known, but scholars generally believe that it does, more or less, and that Socrates is the foundational figure of Western Philosophy. Following his martyrdom in 399 BCE, his followers established their own schools, and the works of Plato and Xenophon were copied and spread throughout the Mediterranean. One copy of Xenophon’s Memorabilia was acquired by Zeno of Citium who would go on to establish the Stoic School in Athens based on Socrates’ vision.
Stoicism would travel to Rome via the philosopher Diogenes of Babylon and would influence the thought of Epictetus (l. c. 50 — c. 130 CE), the most famous Stoic philosopher, whose works would establish Stoicism as the most popular philosophy of ancient Rome, even to the point of informing the reign of Marcus Aurelius (r. 161-180 CE). Stoicism’s claim that there was a natural force (the logos) which was the First Cause and which maintained the universe would contribute to the philosophical concepts of Saint Paul the Apostle (l. c. 5-64 CE) in formulating his vision of Christianity which informs the epistles and gospels of the Christian New Testament.
Philosophy continued to develop, hand in hand, with religion through the Middle Ages and on into the present day. Medieval philosophy sought to explain the world, in the West, according to the Jewish and Christian belief systems and, in the East, in accordance with the Hindu, Buddhist, and Islamic visions. In the present day, philosophical schools and movements continue to develop in response to religious beliefs, accepted knowledge, or traditional understanding in any area when these authorities fail to fully address the higher needs of the people.
This article has been reviewed for accuracy, reliability and adherence to academic standards prior to publication.
What is the origin of Philosophy? What were the civilizing landmarks that made this new way of thinking and trying to understand the world possible? Who were the first philosophers? What were your questions, your intentions and your motives? Are you curious? See the answers to these questions below.
Content Index:
- What is
- History
- first philosophers
- Video classes
what is philosophy
The word Philosophy means love of wisdom. The creation of the term is traditionally attributed to Pythagoras of Samos and, in Greek, philosophia is the combination of two words: philos (friendship, love, respect between equals) and sophia (wisdom, knowledge). In addition to etymology, what is Philosophy?
First, it is necessary to understand that Philosophy is a typically Greek phenomenon, and then to understand it as a way of thinking and critically and rationally disposing thought to know the world. Philosophy is contemplating, observing, questioning and arguing following a certain method, that is, each philosopher will have a way of exposing his thoughts and questions.
Historical context of the origin of philosophy
Philosophy emerged in Greece at a very favorable time. According to historians, it was created at the end of the 7th century BC. C and beginning of the sixth century BC. C in Ionia (region of the Greek colonies in Asia Minor, present-day Turkey), in the city of Miletus. The first philosopher in history was Thales of Miletus (who remembers him in math?). At this time, known as the Archaic Period, the Greeks prospered in trade and colonization in the basins of the Mediterranean Sea and the Black Sea.
Such cultural exchange provided, therefore, Philosophy. It is noteworthy that, although they were influenced by different peoples (and their respective knowledge developed until then), it was up to the Greeks to creation of Philosophy as an expression of thought, as they were able to make qualitative changes in the ways of knowing possible until the time. According to Marilena Chauí, these changes were:
- mythical thought: Hesiod and Homer had the important function of humanizing the gods and deifying men. Both explain the origin of worldly things (men, laws, things) in a rational way.
- In relation to knowledge: the Greeks were able to transform everyday knowledge and common sense into universal and abstract knowledge, that is, science. For example, the Egyptians had excellent tools for measuring and calculating. The Greeks managed to transform this practical knowledge into theoretical, thus creating arithmetic and geometry (or simply Mathematics).
- In relation to society: it was the Greeks who invented politics. All societies had a form of social organization. It was the Greeks, however, who created the idea of politics, a way of organizing in the polis (city governed by laws and institutions) in which there were public debates to think about the political decisions that should be sockets. In addition, the creation of the policy provided the division of the public sphere from the others (family and religious).
- in relation to thinking: the Greeks were responsible for inventing the Western idea of reason. That is, a systematized thought, governed by universal and constant laws. A mathematical principle, for example: 1+1 will always equal 2, because the Greeks were able to create concepts.
Other important points that enabled the emergence of Philosophy were the invention of currency and calendar and the emergence of urban life. Currency made the exchange of goods to be done in an abstract way, improving the trade relationship. The calendar generated a new perception and mastery of time. These two factors helped to develop urban life. A new way of living requires a new way of thinking – in this case, Philosophy.
the first philosophers
The first philosophers are the pre-Socratics. They shared the principle that there is no creation of the world, that is, there was no “nothing” for something to be created afterwards. This implies that the world is eternal and constantly changing. Another principle is the arche, which understands that everything that exists in the world has a single element in common. These philosophers understood that there was an eternal bottom from which everything was born, called the physis.
The physis, which is imperishable, gives rise to all beings in the world, which in turn are perishable. The physis is Nature, while the arché is the principle from which that Nature is constituted. Another shared principle was that of becoming. Becoming is the idea of change and transformation; the idea that everything passes from its state to the opposite state, without chaos, since the world is ordered by physis. Let’s look at the main philosophers of the pre-Socratic period:
Ionic School
1. Tales of Mileto (624-546 a. Ç)
For Thales, the primary element was the Water or the wet. Noting that plants dried, bodies dehydrated, and food contained sap, Thales attributed the beginning of everything to water. Water, for Thales, is the arche and is in all things in different states. The state of water is what shapes how everything in the world is.
2. Anaximander of Miletus (611-547 a. Ç)
For Anaximander, unlike Thales, the primordial element could not be something limited, that’s why he understood that the arché was the apeiron (Greek: infinite or unlimited). The apeiron is present in everything, however it is invisible. One of the main arguments, especially against Thales, to defend that the arché could not be a The only visible element was to observe that water is wet, however fire is hot – they are elements opposites. In this way, Anaximander understood that the primordial element needed to be neutral.
3. Anaximens of Miletus (588-524 a. Ç)
Starting from Anaximander, Anaximenes understood that the arché was the air. Air, therefore, would be the origin of all things, depending on its state of condensation or rarefaction. Condensed air would give rise to earth and rarefied air to fire, for example.
Eleatic School
4. Elea’s Parmenides (530-460 a. Ç)
“The being is, the non-being is not”. Parmenides did not work with the notion of arché, but focused his philosophy on the To be. For him, Being was one, indivisible, infinite and immutable. Reality, in Parmenides, is one, infinite, immobile and immutable. For him, transformations were illusions and contrary ideas were just appearances. So, the opposite is just absence: what exists is light, because the dark is actually non-light (lack of light).
Ephesian school
5. Heraclitus of Ephesus (40-470 a. Ç)
For Heraclitus, the arché was the fire and things originate according to the movement of the fire of kindling and quenching. Unlike Parmenides (who said that nothing changed), Heraclitus, based on fire, defended that reality was in constant movement and, therefore, he is considered the father of dialectics. Things always change from one state to another opposite state, from immobile to mobile, from hot to cold, and so on. This change of state generates a unity, as it is movement and contradiction that give rise to things in the world.
italian school
6. Pythagoras of Samos (570-495 a. Ç)
For Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans, the primordial element was the number. The number was harmony, understood as the essence of things, composed of the sum of opposites (odd and even numbers). The odd and even numbers represent a mutating relationship, so it can be said that the Pythagoreans also thought that reality had movement.
For them, the universe was governed by mathematical relationships (expressed by number). Unlike other philosophers who presented a physical element such as the arché, the Pythagoreans understood that there were four elements (air, water, fire and earth), but the principle of everything, which ordered and gave form, was the number.
Pluralist School
7. Empedocles of Agrigento (490-430 a. Ç)
Empedocles tried to solve the problem posed by Heraclitus and Parmenides in relation to the movement. For Heraclitus, everything flowed; for Parmenides, nothing changed. Empedocles was the one who managed to find a way out of this problem, attributing the arché to the roots or to four elements: earth, fire, water and air.
For him, these four elements combine, then separate and then combine again and thus give rise to things. The principles responsible for combining and separating the elements are love and hate, respectively. Principles are eternal and unchanging, whereas substances created by such procedures are finite and changeable. In this way, Empedocles managed to bring together the theory of Heraclitus and Parmenides to explain the origin of things in the world.
8. Democritus of Abdera
Democritus centered the arche on the atom. For him, the atom was an extremely small particle, invisible, infinite, immutable and indivisible. These atoms were different from each other and, when they came together, they formed the substance. When this substance broke apart, the atoms that made it up could rearrange themselves and form another substance.
These are the main philosophers who composed the first moment of Greek philosophy. Called pre-Socratics because they predate Socrates, a philosopher who also revolutionized Greek philosophical thought. But that’s discussion for another time.
See more details about the origin of Philosophy
In the selected videos below, you will be able to better follow how Philosophy came about. Check out:
Why was Philosophy born?
In this video, we have brushstrokes of where Philosophy was born. One sees mainly the dilemma of its emergence: those who argue that she was born in other regions of the world, such as China, and those who attribute her birthplace to Greece. We also see the influences of other peoples’ thoughts on Greek philosophy.
How was philosophy born?
This video deals with the three pillars on which Philosophy was founded: art, religiosity and historical conditions. It’s cool because, here, each pillar is detailed. In art, the contributions of Homer and Hesiod. In religion, the difference between public religion (mythology) and the Orphic mysteries (related to Orpheus). In social conditions, the entire context that made the existence of Philosophy possible.
What is the history of philosophy?
In this video, the story of the rise of Philosophy in Greece is more precisely presented, about the first philosopher, about the word and the great philosophical questions. In addition, the phases of ancient Philosophy are also exposed.
Animation with the first philosophers
This video from the Animated Abstracts channel, in addition to the history of Philosophy, tells a little about the first philosophers. The summary made is very interesting, it’s a good summary video!
Did you like to know the origin of Philosophy? How about meeting the watershed philosopher in Ancient Greece as well? Socrates!
References
What are originating words of philosophy?
The word philosophy comes from the Greek philo (love) and sophia (wisdom) and so is literally defined as “the love of wisdom”. More broadly understood, it is the study of the most basic and profound matters of human existence.
What is the origin of the word philosopher?
A philosopher is someone who practices philosophy. The term philosopher comes from the Ancient Greek: φιλόσοφος, romanized: philosophos, meaning ‘lover of wisdom’.
What is the Latin root for philosophy?
1300, philosophie, “knowledge, learning, scholarship, scholarly works, body of knowledge,” from Old French filosofie “philosophy, knowledge” (12c., Modern French philosophie) and directly from Latin philosophia, from Greek philosophia “love of knowledge, pursuit of wisdom; systematic investigation,” from philo- “loving …
What is the Greek origin of the word philosophy?
Philosophy is a combination of two Greek words, philein sophia, meaning lover of wisdom. In ancient times a lover of wisdom could be related to any area where intelligence was expressed. This could be in business, politics, human relations, or carpentry and other skills.
What is the first philosophy?
Aristotle. In Aristotle: Physics and metaphysics. … metaphysics: he calls it “first philosophy” and defines it as the discipline that studies “being as being.”
Where do I start in philosophy?
10 Books For Beginners to Start With
- Plato, The Last Days of Socrates — this includes four dialogues: the Euthyphro , the Apology , the Crito , and the Phaedo.
- Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics.
- Epictetus, Discourses, Fragments, Handbook.
- Augustine of Hippo, Confessions.
- Boethius, Consolation of Philosophy.
Which philosopher should I read first?
If you are just starting out, then your first step should be to read some dialogues of Socrates. That’s where Western Philosophy begins, 2,400 years ago. Your next step would be to read Aristotle’s, Nicomachean Ethics (2,300 BC).
Who are the best philosophers?
Here are 10 Greatest Philosophers who ever lived
- Aristotle. The list of the greatest philosophers is incomplete without Aristotle.
- Immanuel Kant. After Aristotle, Immanuel Kant comes at number #2 in the list of the greatest philosopher who ever lived.
- John Locke.
- Epicurus.
- Zeno of Citium.
- Plato.
- Confucius.
- David Hume.
How can I learn philosophy on my own?
6 tips for teaching yourself philosophy
- Start from a position of ignorance.
- Expect to go slowly.
- Read when you are most alert.
- Pick whatever interests you the most.
- Get a philosophical dictionary.
- Familiarize yourself with the history of Western Thought.
What is the best way to study philosophy?
Here are a few suggestions:
- Do the assigned reading. The philosophical texts simply are the content of the course; if you do not read, you will not learn.
- Consider the context.
- Take your time.
- Spot crucial passages.
- Identify central theses.
- Locate supportive arguments.
- Assess the arguments.
- Look for connections.
Can you be a philosopher without a degree?
There are no official philosophers. A degree in philosophy does not transform a person into a philosopher, nor does the absence of a degree ensure that the person is not.
What are the 4 things to be considered in studying philosophy?
Philosophy – the love of wisdom – is an activity of attempting to understand the world, in all its aspects. There are four pillars of philosophy: theoretical philosophy (metaphysics and epistemology), practical philosophy (ethics, social and political philosophy, aesthetics), logic, and history of philosophy.
What comes in your mind when you hear the word philosophy?
Answer. Answer: Thoughts, possibilities, plans, theories constructed to explore obscurities. Philosophy is a way to connect the known in ways to better understand and (maybe) find a path to solutions.
What are the 5 types of philosophy?
Introduction to the Five Branches of Philosophy
Metaphysics | Study of Existence | What’s out there? |
---|---|---|
Epistemology | Study of Knowledge | How do I know about it? |
Ethics | Study of Action | What should I do? |
Politics | Study of Force | What actions are permissible? |
Esthetics | Study of Art | What can life be like? |
What are the important requirements in doing philosophy?
Students must take at least one course in each of three areas: Contemporary Metaphysics and Epistemology [M&E], Contemporary Value Theory [V], and History [H]. In addition at least one of the electives must be a tutorial.
Who are the major philosophers?
- Saint Thomas Aquinas (1225–1274)
- Aristotle (384–322 BCE)
- Confucius (551–479 BCE)
- René Descartes (1596–1650)
- Ralph Waldo Emerson (1803 82)
- Michel Foucault (1926-1984)
- David Hume (1711–77)
- Immanuel Kant (1724–1804)
What jobs do philosophers have?
Careers in Philosophy
- Law. Philosophy is one of the best, if not the best major to prepare you for law school.
- Architecture and Art.
- Teaching.
- Publishing.
- Public Relations.
- Politics and Public Policy.
- Religion and Ministry.
- Business and Management.
What classes do you take for philosophy?
What classes do philosophy majors actually take? It depends on your college’s program, but some basic classes involve logic, ethics, metaphysics, political theory, sociology and anthropology.
Is philosophy a hard degree?
Readings for philosophy courses are generally not long, but they are difficult and challenging. You cannot expect to go through an assigned reading once and have an adequate grasp of it. Some students seem to thrive on the painstaking study required, while others simply don’t have the patience for it.
Is philosophy an easy class?
While some branches of philosophy are relatively easy, like ethics, some are complicated. This is where a good professor will shine as he/she will be able to turn even the most complicated in to something understandable. I really think that this is the most factor in whether or not the course is hard.
What are the hardest majors?
CollegeVine’s Top 10 Hardest Majors
- Chemistry. Average GPA: 2.9.
- Chemical Engineering. Average GPA: 3.2.
- Electrical Engineering. Average GPA: 3.3.
- Physics. Average GPA: 3.1.
- Architecture. Average GPA: 3.3.
- Nursing. Average GPA: 3.2.
- Accounting. Average GPA: 3.2.
- Cellular and Molecular Biology. Average GPA: 3.2.
What is the easiest major?
The 14 Easiest Majors to Study in College
- #1: Psychology. Psychology majors study the inner workings of the human psyche.
- #2: Criminal Justice.
- #3: English.
- #4: Education.
- #5: Social Work.
- #6: Sociology.
- #7: Communications.
- #8: History.
What are easy majors that pay well?
The Top 10 Quick and Easy Degrees that Pay Well
- Business Administration.
- Communications.
- Healthcare Administration.
- Information Technology.
- Supply Chain Management.
What is the hardest bachelor’s degree to get?
Recap: What Is the Hardest Major in College?
College Major | Time Spent Preparing for Class per Week |
---|---|
1. Architecture | 22.20 hrs |
2. Chemical Engineering | 19.66 hrs |
3. Aero and Astronautical Engineering | 19.24 hrs |
4. Biomedical Engineering | 18.82 hrs |
What is the most stressful degree?
10 Most Stressful College Majors
- Fine Arts. Average studying time per week: 12-17h.
- Nursing. Average studying time per week: 14-17h.
- Theoretical & Experimental Physics. Average studying time per week: 15-17h.
- Philosophy.
- Architecture.
- Molecular Biology.
- Electrical Engineering.
- Chemical Engineering.
What is the toughest degree in the world?
Given below is the list of toughest courses in the world that can boost your career:
- Engineering.
- Chartered Accountancy.
- Medicine.
- Pharmacy.
- Architecture.
- Law.
- Psychology.
- Aeronautics.
Origins[edit | edit source]
Etymology[edit | edit source]
The term philosophy is derived from the Greek words phylos meaning «to love» and sophie meaning «wisdom».
Introduction to Philosophy[edit | edit source]
In the Phaedo, Socrates says that philosophy is a preparation for the death that awaits us all. When the mind is engaged in philosophy it is free of concerns and dwells in the domain of ideas. Our minds enter a spiritual region transcending the death of our corporeal experience. Another, better known, view of Socrates is that of philosophy as ‘the love of wisdom’. This love discovers truth, and we become wise by practical application in our daily lives of what has been discovered.
These definitions highlight the nature of philosophical inquiry. Philosophers ask questions. These questions try to understand the metaphysical and physical universe including humans and their world
Pre-Socratics[edit | edit source]
The history of philosophy in the west begins with the Greeks, and particularly with a group of philosophers commonly called the pre-Socratics. This is not to deny the occurrence of other pre-philosophical rumblings in Egyptian and Babylonian cultures. Certainly great thinkers and writers existed in each of these cultures, and we have evidence that some of the earliest Greek philosophers may have had contact with at least some of the products of Egyptian and Babylonian thought. However, the early Greek thinkers added at least one element which differentiates their thoughts from all those who came before them. For the first time in history, we discover in their writings something more than dogmatic assertions about the ordering of the world — we find reasoned arguments for various beliefs about the world.
Thales[edit | edit source]
Thales (in Greek: Θαλης) of Miletus (circa 624 BC — 546 BC), also known as Thales the Milesian, was a pre-Socratic Greek philosopher. Many regard him as the first philosopher in the Greek tradition. He has also been traditionally considered the father of science, although it is also contended that the beginnings of science may be traced to Ancient Egypt.
Life[edit | edit source]
Thales lived in the city of Miletus, in Ionia, now western Turkey. According to Herodotus, he was of Phoenician descent.
The well-traveled Ionians had many dealings with Egypt and Babylon; Thales may have studied in Egypt as a young man. In any event, Thales almost certainly had exposure to Egyptian mythology, astronomy, and mathematics, as well as to other traditions alien to the Homeric traditions of Greece. Perhaps because of this, his inquiries into the nature of things extends beyond traditional mythology.
Several anecdotes suggest that Thales was not solely a thinker; he was involved in business and politics. One story recounts that he bought all the olive presses in Miletus after predicting the weather and a good harvest for a particular year. Another version of this same story states that he bought the presses to demonstrate to his fellow Milesians that he could use his intelligence to enrich himself. Herodotus recorded that Thales advised the city-states of Ionia to form a federation.
Thales is said to have died in his seat, while watching an athletic contest.
Theories and influence[edit | edit source]
Before Thales, the Greeks explained the origin and nature of the world through myths of anthropomorphic gods and heroes. Phenomena like lightning or earthquakes were attributed to the actions of the gods.
By contrast, Thales attempted to find naturalistic explanations of the world, without reference to the supernatural. He explained earthquakes by imagining that the Earth floats on water and that earthquakes occur when the Earth is rocked by waves. Herodotus cites him as having predicted the solar eclipse of 585 BC that put an end to the fighting between the Lydians and the Medes.
Thales’s most famous belief was his cosmological doctrine, which held that the world originated from water. It is sometimes assumed that Thales considered everything to be made from water. According to others, however, it’s likely that while Thales saw water as an origin, he never pondered whether water continued to be the substance of the world.
Many philosophers followed Thales’s lead in searching for explanations in nature rather than in the supernatural; others returned to supernatural explanations, but couched them in the language of philosophy rather than myth or religion.
Thales is credited for having first popularized Geometry to ancient Greek culture, mainly that of spatial relationships.
The best explanation of Thales’s view is the following passage from Aristotle’s Metaphysics (983 BC). The passage is given in translation with key phrases transliterated from the Greek for the reader’s benefit. The reader will see in the transliteration words from the theory of matter and form that were adopted by science with quite different meanings. The translation is somewhat literal, for purposes of accuracy.
- «That from which is everything that exists (ta onta) and from which it first becomes (ex hou gignetai protou) and into which it is rendered at last (eis ho phtheiretai teleutaion), its substance remaining under it (tes men ousias hypomenouses), but transforming in qualities (pathesi metaballouses), that they say is the element (stoicheion) and principle (archen) of things that are (ton onton).»
And again:
- «For it is necessary (dei) that there be some nature (physin), either one or more than one, from which become (gignetai) the other things (t’alla) of the object being preserved (sozomenes ekeines)… Thales says that it is water (hydor).»
Aristotle’s depiction of the change problem and the definition of substance could not be more clear. If an object changes, is it the same or different? In either case how can there be a change (metabollein) from one to the other? The answer is the substance (ousia or physis), which «is saved», but acquires or loses different qualities (pathe, the things you «experience»).
A deeper dip into the waters of the theory of matter and form is properly reserved to other articles. The question for this article is, how far does Aristotle reflect Thales? He was probably not far off, and Thales was probably an incipient matter-and-formist.
The essentially non-philosophic DL states that Thales taught as follows:
- «Water constituted (hypestesato, «stood under») the principle of all things.»
Heraclitus Homericus (Quaes. Hom. 22, not the same as Heraclitus of Ephesus) states that Thales drew his conclusion from seeing moist substance (hygra physis) turn into air, slime and earth. It seems clear that Thales viewed the Earth as solidifying from the water on which it floated and which surrounded it as Ocean.
Thales applied his method to objects that changed to become other objects, such as water into earth (he thought). But what about the changing itself? Thales did address the topic, approaching it through magnets and amber—which, when electrified by rubbing, attracts in the same way.
How was the power to move other things without the mover’s changing to be explained? Thales saw a commonality with the powers of living things to act. The magnet and the amber must be alive, and if that were so, there could be no difference between the living and the dead. When asked why he didn’t die if there was no difference, he replied “because there is no difference.”
Aristotle defined the soul as the principle of life, that which permeates the matter and makes it live, giving it the animation, or power to act. The idea did not originate with him, as the Greeks in general believed in the distinction between mind and matter, which was ultimately to lead to a distinction not only between body and soul but also between matter and energy.
If things were alive, they must have souls. This belief was no innovation, as the ordinary ancient populations of the Mediterranean did believe that natural actions were caused by divinities. Accordingly, the sources say that Thales believed all things possessed divinities. In their zeal to make him the first in everything they said he was the first to hold the belief, which even they must have known was not true.
However, Thales was looking for something more general, a universal substance of mind. That also was true to the polytheism of the times. Zeus was the very personification of supreme mind, dominating all the subordinate manifestations. From Thales on, however, philosophers had a tendency to depersonify or objectify mind, as though it were the substance of animation per se and not actually a god like the other gods. The end result was a total removal of mind from substance, opening the door to a non-divine principle of action. This tradition persisted until Einstein, whose cosmology is quite a different one and does not distinguish between matter and energy.
Classical thought, however, had proceded only a little way along that path. Instead of referring to the person, Zeus, they talked about the great mind:
- «Thales», says Cicero, «assures that water is the principle of all things; and that God is that Mind which shaped and created all things from water.» (Cicero:»De Nat.Deorum,»i.,10.)
The universal mind appears as a Roman belief in Vergil as well:
- «In the beginning, SPIRIT within strengthens Heaven and Earth,
- The watery fields, and the lucid globe of Lina, and then —
- Titan stars; and mind infused through the limbs
- Agitates the whole mass, and mixes itself with GREAT MATTER»
- (Virgil: «Aeneid,» vi., 724 ff.)
Socrates[edit | edit source]
Socrates (c.470 – 399 BC) (Greek Σωκράτης Sōkrátēs) was a Greek (Athenian) philosopher.
Like Thales and the other pre-Socratics, Socrates too had the ambition to ask questions of life. However, where the pre-Socratics were more concerned with the cosmological questions, Socrates was concerned with questions of the following nature: What is piety? What kind of life is worthwhile for a human to live? Can virtue be taught? What is justice? Is there more than one’s virtue? What is human excellence?
Socrates did not actually write any of these ideas down. The only written information about his philosophy can be found in the dialogues of Plato and Xenophon. These dialogues deal mostly with questions of the good life, human excellence, and the cultivation of knowledge. One of Plato’s most important and best known works is «The Republic» in which we find the allegory of The Cave that explains the difference between perceived reality and «real» reality which, according to Plato, can only be found in the realm of ideas.
More: Greek Philosophy: Socrates
Long before the origin of philosophy, our ancestors used to turn to myths and magic (pre-rational knowledge) to find the answers to the disturbing questions of the time. Nevertheless, in the Ancient Greece the way of thinking and seeing the world changed thanks to a group of sages, or rather, philosophers, who were dissatisfied with mythical explanations. For instance, they did not believe that seasons were a consequence of gods’ will. This first group of philosophers, called “Presocratic philosophers”, thought that the explanations had to be found in nature, by watching and developing rational theories. They were the first ones to show that critical and systematic attitude defining philosophy.
So, in the sixth century BC, in Miletus or Asia Minor (Greece), the concept of rational thought was developed. The Greeks were the first civilization in the Western culture to come into contact with new cultures, new ways of thinking and understanding the world, which ultimately causes a crisis of values. This culture is the first to ponder the question of “what is the meaning of life?”, the concept of “right thought” and how to explain reality. Influenced by other possibilities of life, Greece begins to consider new challenges, new ways of viewing life and explaining it. This period is known as “the transition from myth to logos” which we are going to explain in more detail.
WHAT IS A MYTH?
A myth is any traditional story consisting of events that are ostensibly historical, though often supernatural, explaining the origins of a cultural practice or natural phenomenon. Myths are often stories that are currently understood as being exaggerated or fictitious.[4] It is derived from the Greek word mythos (μῦθος), which simply means “story”. Mythology can refer either to the study of myths, or to a body or collection of myths. A myth also can be a story to explain why something exists.
Human cultures usually include a cosmogonical or creation myth, concerning the origins of the world, or how the world came to exist. The active beings in myths are generally gods and goddesses, heroes and heroines, or animals and plants. Most myths are set in a timeless past before recorded time or beginning of the critical history. A myth can be a story involving symbols that are capable of multiple meanings.
A myth is a sacred narrative because it holds religious or spiritual significance for those who tell it. Myths also contribute to and express a culture’s systems of thought and values.[1]
A myth is a traditional or legendary story, usually concerning some being or hero or event, with or without a determinable basis of fact or a natural explanation, especially one that is concerned with deities or demigods and explains some practice, rite, or phenomenon of nature.
CHARACTERISTICS OF MYTHS: What is the difference between “mythos” and “logos”?
MYTHOS | LOGOS |
Mythical thought is an anthropomorphic way of thinking. The main characters are men or figures with human shape, like gods or heroes. | Rational thought is not anthropomorphic. Rational explanations search the natural causes of phenomena. |
Mythical thought is arbitrary. Facts in this world happen because of deities’ will. [Things happen using unlimited personal power without considering other people’s wishes.]“Arbitrary” is what someone wants to happen: e.g. “It was God’s will.” | Rational thought is not arbitrary because it looks for explanatory laws and theories in order to understand the universe. |
Mythical thought is traditional. Mythical beliefs pass down from parents to children. | Rational thought is innovative and critical. It is continuously discovering new laws about the universe and it casts doubt on old beliefs and convictions. |
Mythical thought is collective. Myths are usually anonymous and shared by a community who feel identified with them. | Rational thought is individual. Theories are not anonymous because they are defended by someone (a philosopher, a thinker…). |
Mythical thought is fantastic. Imagination is the main source of explanation. | Rational thought is logical. Its main source is observation, experience and critical rationality. |
TYPES/KINDS OF MYTHS
- Cosmogonic myth: describes the creation of the world.
- Etiological myth: explains an origin, particularly how an object or custom came into existence.
- Eschatological myth: is concerned with the future or the end of the world or of humankind.
- Moral myth: is concerned with behavioural patterns.
***************************************************
HOMEWORK
Answer these questions:
- What are myths?
- What are myths for?
Choose one of the following myths. Then, answer these questions:
- Write a summary of this myth (10-15 lines).
- What does this myth explain?
- What kind of myth is it? Why?
- What are the characteristics of myths in this story?
PRACTICAL ACTIVITIES
1/ Do you think that mythical thought is still present in our society nowadays? Use an example in order to justify your answer.
2/ Create a short story using the mythical thought. You must explain a natural phenomenon such as the eruption of a volcano, an earthquake or a hurricane.
3/ Explain a situtation in which imagination and logos are used together.
[1] https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Myth