Beauty is commonly described as a feature of objects that makes these objects pleasurable to perceive. Such objects include landscapes, sunsets, humans and works of art. Beauty, together with art and taste, is the main subject of aesthetics, one of the major branches of philosophy. As a positive aesthetic value, it is contrasted with ugliness as its negative counterpart.
One difficulty in understanding beauty is because it has both objective and subjective aspects: it is seen as a property of things but also as depending on the emotional response of observers. Because of its subjective side, beauty is said to be «in the eye of the beholder».[2] It has been argued that the ability on the side of the subject needed to perceive and judge beauty, sometimes referred to as the «sense of taste», can be trained and that the verdicts of experts coincide in the long run. This would suggest that the standards of validity of judgments of beauty are intersubjective, i.e. dependent on a group of judges, rather than fully subjective or fully objective.
Conceptions of beauty aim to capture what is essential to all beautiful things. Classical conceptions define beauty in terms of the relation between the beautiful object as a whole and its parts: the parts should stand in the right proportion to each other and thus compose an integrated harmonious whole. Hedonist conceptions see a necessary connection between pleasure and beauty, e.g. that for an object to be beautiful is for it to cause disinterested pleasure. Other conceptions include defining beautiful objects in terms of their value, of a loving attitude towards them or of their function.
Overview
Beauty, together with art and taste, is the main subject of aesthetics, one of the major branches of philosophy.[3][4] Beauty is usually categorized as an aesthetic property besides other properties, like grace, elegance or the sublime.[5][6][7] As a positive aesthetic value, beauty is contrasted with ugliness as its negative counterpart. Beauty is often listed as one of the three fundamental concepts of human understanding besides truth and goodness.[5][8][6]
Objectivists or realists see beauty as an objective or mind-independent feature of beautiful things, which is denied by subjectivists.[3][9] The source of this debate is that judgments of beauty seem to be based on subjective grounds, namely our feelings, while claiming universal correctness at the same time.[10] This tension is sometimes referred to as the «antinomy of taste».[4] Adherents of both sides have suggested that a certain faculty, commonly called a sense of taste, is necessary for making reliable judgments about beauty.[3][10] David Hume, for example, suggests that this faculty can be trained and that the verdicts of experts coincide in the long run.[3][9]
Beauty is mainly discussed in relation to concrete objects accessible to sensory perception. It has been suggested that the beauty of a thing supervenes on the sensory features of this thing.[10] It has also been proposed that abstract objects like stories or mathematical proofs can be beautiful.[11] Beauty plays a central role in works of art and nature.[12][10]
An influential distinction among beautiful things, according to Immanuel Kant, is that between dependent and free beauty. A thing has dependent beauty if its beauty depends on the conception or function of this thing, unlike free or absolute beauty.[10] Examples of dependent beauty include an ox which is beautiful as an ox but not beautiful as a horse[3] or a photograph which is beautiful, because it depicts a beautiful building but that lacks beauty generally speaking because of its low quality.[9]
Objectivism and subjectivism
Judgments of beauty seem to occupy an intermediary position between objective judgments, e.g. concerning the mass and shape of a grapefruit, and subjective likes, e.g. concerning whether the grapefruit tastes good.[13][10][9] Judgments of beauty differ from the former because they are based on subjective feelings rather than objective perception. But they also differ from the latter because they lay claim on universal correctness.[10] This tension is also reflected in common language. On the one hand, we talk about beauty as an objective feature of the world that is ascribed, for example, to landscapes, paintings or humans.[14] The subjective side, on the other hand, is expressed in sayings like «beauty is in the eye of the beholder».[3]
These two positions are often referred to as objectivism (or realism) and subjectivism.[3] Objectivism is the traditional view, while subjectivism developed more recently in western philosophy. Objectivists hold that beauty is a mind-independent feature of things. On this account, the beauty of a landscape is independent of who perceives it or whether it is perceived at all.[3][9] Disagreements may be explained by an inability to perceive this feature, sometimes referred to as a «lack of taste».[15] Subjectivism, on the other hand, denies the mind-independent existence of beauty.[5][3][9] Influential for the development of this position was John Locke’s distinction between primary qualities, which the object has independent of the observer, and secondary qualities, which constitute powers in the object to produce certain ideas in the observer.[3][16][5] When applied to beauty, there is still a sense in which it depends on the object and its powers.[9] But this account makes the possibility of genuine disagreements about claims of beauty implausible, since the same object may produce very different ideas in distinct observers. The notion of «taste» can still be used to explain why different people disagree about what is beautiful, but there is no objectively right or wrong taste, there are just different tastes.[3]
The problem with both the objectivist and the subjectivist position in their extreme form is that each has to deny some intuitions about beauty. This issue is sometimes discussed under the label «antinomy of taste».[3][4] It has prompted various philosophers to seek a unified theory that can take all these intuitions into account. One promising route to solve this problem is to move from subjective to intersubjective theories, which hold that the standards of validity of judgments of taste are intersubjective or dependent on a group of judges rather than objective. This approach tries to explain how genuine disagreement about beauty is possible despite the fact that beauty is a mind-dependent property, dependent not on an individual but a group.[3][4] A closely related theory sees beauty as a secondary or response-dependent property.[9] On one such account, an object is beautiful «if it causes pleasure by virtue of its aesthetic properties».[5] The problem that different people respond differently can be addressed by combining response-dependence theories with so-called ideal-observer theories: it only matters how an ideal observer would respond.[10] There is no general agreement on how «ideal observers» are to be defined, but it is usually assumed that they are experienced judges of beauty with a fully developed sense of taste. This suggests an indirect way of solving the antinomy of taste: instead of looking for necessary and sufficient conditions of beauty itself, one can learn to identify the qualities of good critics and rely on their judgments.[3] This approach only works if unanimity among experts was ensured. But even experienced judges may disagree in their judgments, which threatens to undermine ideal-observer theories.[3][9]
Conceptions
Various conceptions of the essential features of beautiful things have been proposed but there is no consensus as to which is the right one.
Classical
The «classical conception»[further explanation needed] defines beauty in terms of the relation between the beautiful object as a whole and its parts: the parts should stand in the right proportion to each other and thus compose an integrated harmonious whole.[3][5][9] On this account, which found its most explicit articulation in the Italian Renaissance, the beauty of a human body, for example, depends, among other things, on the right proportion of the different parts of the body and on the overall symmetry.[3] One problem with this conception is that it is difficult to give a general and detailed description of what is meant by «harmony between parts» and raises the suspicion that defining beauty through harmony results in exchanging one unclear term for another one.[3] Some attempts have been made to dissolve this suspicion by searching for laws of beauty, like the golden ratio.
18th century philosopher Alexander Baumgarten, for example, saw laws of beauty in analogy with laws of nature and believed that they could be discovered through empirical research.[5] As of 2003, these attempts have failed to find a general definition of beauty and several authors take the opposite claim that such laws cannot be formulated, as part of their definition of beauty.[10]
Hedonism
A very common element in many conceptions of beauty is its relation to pleasure.[11][5] Hedonism makes this relation part of the definition of beauty by holding that there is a necessary connection between pleasure and beauty, e.g. that for an object to be beautiful is for it to cause pleasure or that the experience of beauty is always accompanied by pleasure.[12] This account is sometimes labeled as «aesthetic hedonism» in order to distinguish it from other forms of hedonism.[17][18] An influential articulation of this position comes from Thomas Aquinas, who treats beauty as «that which pleases in the very apprehension of it».[19] Immanuel Kant explains this pleasure through a harmonious interplay between the faculties of understanding and imagination.[11] A further question for hedonists is how to explain the relation between beauty and pleasure. This problem is akin to the Euthyphro dilemma: is something beautiful because we enjoy it or do we enjoy it because it is beautiful?[5] Identity theorists solve this problem by denying that there is a difference between beauty and pleasure: they identify beauty, or the appearance of it, with the experience of aesthetic pleasure.[11]
Hedonists usually restrict and specify the notion of pleasure in various ways in order to avoid obvious counterexamples. One important distinction in this context is the difference between pure and mixed pleasure.[11] Pure pleasure excludes any form of pain or unpleasant feeling while the experience of mixed pleasure can include unpleasant elements.[20] But beauty can involve mixed pleasure, for example, in the case of a beautifully tragic story, which is why mixed pleasure is usually allowed in hedonist conceptions of beauty.[11]
Another problem faced by hedonist theories is that we take pleasure from many things that are not beautiful. One way to address this issue is to associate beauty with a special type of pleasure: aesthetic or disinterested pleasure.[3][4][7] A pleasure is disinterested if it is indifferent to the existence of the beautiful object or if it did not arise owing to an antecedent desire through means-end reasoning.[21][11] For example, the joy of looking at a beautiful landscape would still be valuable if it turned out that this experience was an illusion, which would not be true if this joy was due to seeing the landscape as a valuable real estate opportunity.[3] Opponents of hedonism usually concede that many experiences of beauty are pleasurable but deny that this is true for all cases.[12] For example, a cold jaded critic may still be a good judge of beauty because of her years of experience but lack the joy that initially accompanied her work.[11] One way to avoid this objection is to allow responses to beautiful things to lack pleasure while insisting that all beautiful things merit pleasure, that aesthetic pleasure is the only appropriate response to them.[12]
Others
G. E. Moore explained beauty in regard to intrinsic value as «that of which the admiring contemplation is good in itself».[21][5] This definition connects beauty to experience while managing to avoid some of the problems usually associated with subjectivist positions since it allows that things may be beautiful even if they are never experienced.[21]
Another subjectivist theory of beauty comes from George Santayana, who suggested that we project pleasure onto the things we call «beautiful». So in a process akin to a category mistake, one treats one’s subjective pleasure as an objective property of the beautiful thing.[11][3][5] Other conceptions include defining beauty in terms of a loving or longing attitude towards the beautiful object or in terms of its usefulness or function.[3][22] In 1871, functionalist Charles Darwin explained beauty as result of accumulative sexual selection in «The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex».[5]
In philosophy
Greco-Roman tradition
The classical Greek noun that best translates to the English-language words «beauty» or «beautiful» was κάλλος, kallos, and the adjective was καλός, kalos. However, kalos may and is also translated as «good» or «of fine quality» and thus has a broader meaning than mere physical or material beauty. Similarly, kallos was used differently from the English word beauty in that it first and foremost applied to humans and bears an erotic connotation.[23] The Koine Greek word for beautiful was ὡραῖος, hōraios,[24] an adjective etymologically coming from the word ὥρα, hōra, meaning «hour». In Koine Greek, beauty was thus associated with «being of one’s hour».[25] Thus, a ripe fruit (of its time) was considered beautiful, whereas a young woman trying to appear older or an older woman trying to appear younger would not be considered beautiful. In Attic Greek, hōraios had many meanings, including «youthful» and «ripe old age».[25] Another classical term in use to describe beauty was pulchrum (Latin).[26]
Beauty for ancient thinkers existed both in form, which is the material world as it is, and as embodied in the spirit, which is the world of mental formations.[27] Greek mythology mentions Helen of Troy as the most beautiful woman.[28][29][30][31][32] Ancient Greek architecture is based on this view of symmetry and proportion.
Pre-Socratic
In one fragment of Heraclitus’s writings (Fragment 106) he mentions beauty, this reads: «To God all things are beautiful, good, right…»[33] The earliest Western theory of beauty can be found in the works of early Greek philosophers from the pre-Socratic period, such as Pythagoras, who conceived of beauty as useful for a moral education of the soul.[34] He wrote of how people experience pleasure when aware of a certain type of formal situation present in reality, perceivable by sight or through the ear[35] and discovered the underlying mathematical ratios in the harmonic scales in music.[34] The Pythagoreans conceived of the presence of beauty in universal terms, which is, as existing in a cosmological state, they observed beauty in the heavens.[27] They saw a strong connection between mathematics and beauty. In particular, they noted that objects proportioned according to the golden ratio seemed more attractive.[36]
Classical period
The classical concept of beauty is one that exhibits perfect proportion (Wolfflin).[37] In this context, the concept belonged often within the discipline of mathematics.[26] An idea of spiritual beauty emerged during the classical period,[27] beauty was something embodying divine goodness, while the demonstration of behaviour which might be classified as beautiful, from an inner state of morality which is aligned to the good.[38]
The writing of Xenophon shows a conversation between Socrates and Aristippus. Socrates discerned differences in the conception of the beautiful, for example, in inanimate objects, the effectiveness of execution of design was a deciding factor on the perception of beauty in something.[27] By the account of Xenophon, Socrates found beauty congruent with that to which was defined as the morally good, in short, he thought beauty coincident with the good.[39]
Beauty is a subject of Plato in his work Symposium.[34] In the work, the high priestess Diotima describes how beauty moves out from a core singular appreciation of the body to outer appreciations via loved ones, to the world in its state of culture and society (Wright).[35] In other words, Diotoma gives to Socrates an explanation of how love should begin with erotic attachment, and end with the transcending of the physical to an appreciation of beauty as a thing in itself. The ascent of love begins with one’s own body, then secondarily, in appreciating beauty in another’s body, thirdly beauty in the soul, which cognates to beauty in the mind in the modern sense, fourthly beauty in institutions, laws and activities, fifthly beauty in knowledge, the sciences, and finally to lastly love beauty itself, which translates to the original Greek language term as auto to kalon.[40] In the final state, auto to kalon and truth are united as one.[41] There is the sense in the text, concerning love and beauty they both co-exist but are still independent or, in other words, mutually exclusive, since love does not have beauty since it seeks beauty.[42] The work toward the end provides a description of beauty in a negative sense.[42]
Plato also discusses beauty in his work Phaedrus,[41] and identifies Alcibiades as beautiful in Parmenides.[43] He considered beauty to be the Idea (Form) above all other Ideas.[44] Platonic thought synthesized beauty with the divine.[35] Scruton (cited: Konstan) states Plato states of the idea of beauty, of it (the idea), being something inviting desirousness (c.f seducing), and, promotes an intellectual renunciation (c.f. denouncing) of desire.[45] For Alexander Nehamas, it is only the locating of desire to which the sense of beauty exists, in the considerations of Plato.[46]
Aristotle defines beauty in Metaphysics as having order, symmetry and definiteness which the mathematical sciences exhibit to a special degree.[37] He saw a relationship between the beautiful (to kalon) and virtue, arguing that «Virtue aims at the beautiful.»[47]
Roman
In De Natura Deorum Cicero wrote: «the splendour and beauty of creation», in respect to this, and all the facets of reality resulting from creation, he postulated these to be a reason to see the existence of a God as creator.[48]
Western Middle Ages
In the Middle Ages, Catholic philosophers like Thomas Aquinas included beauty among the transcendental attributes of being.[49] In his Summa Theologica, Aquinas described the three conditions of beauty as: integritas (wholeness), consonantia (harmony and proportion), and claritas (a radiance and clarity that makes the form of a thing apparent to the mind).[50]
In the Gothic Architecture of the High and Late Middle Ages, light was considered the most beautiful revelation of God, which was heralded in design.[1] Examples are the stained glass of Gothic Cathedrals including Notre-Dame de Paris and Chartres Cathedral.[51]
St. Augustine said of beauty «Beauty is indeed a good gift of God; but that the good may not think it a great good, God dispenses it even to the wicked.»[52]
Renaissance
Classical philosophy and sculptures of men and women produced according to the Greek philosophers’ tenets of ideal human beauty were rediscovered in Renaissance Europe, leading to a re-adoption of what became known as a «classical ideal». In terms of female human beauty, a woman whose appearance conforms to these tenets is still called a «classical beauty» or said to possess a «classical beauty», whilst the foundations laid by Greek and Roman artists have also supplied the standard for male beauty and female beauty in western civilization as seen, for example, in the Winged Victory of Samothrace. During the Gothic era, the classical aesthetical canon of beauty was rejected as sinful. Later, Renaissance and Humanist thinkers rejected this view, and considered beauty to be the product of rational order and harmonious proportions. Renaissance artists and architects (such as Giorgio Vasari in his «Lives of Artists») criticised the Gothic period as irrational and barbarian. This point of view of Gothic art lasted until Romanticism, in the 19th century. Vasari aligned himself to the classical notion and thought of beauty as defined as arising from proportion and order.[38]
Age of Reason
The Age of Reason saw a rise in an interest in beauty as a philosophical subject. For example, Scottish philosopher Francis Hutcheson argued that beauty is «unity in variety and variety in unity».[54] He wrote that beauty was neither purely subjective nor purely objective—it could be understood not as «any Quality suppos’d to be in the Object, which should of itself be beautiful, without relation to any Mind which perceives it: For Beauty, like other Names of sensible Ideas, properly denotes the Perception of some mind; … however we generally imagine that there is something in the Object just like our Perception.»[55]
Immanuel Kant believed that there could be no «universal criterion of the beautiful» and that the experience of beauty is subjective, but that an object is judged to be beautiful when it seems to display «purposiveness»; that is, when its form is perceived to have the character of a thing designed according to some principle and fitted for a purpose.[56] He distinguished «free beauty» from «merely dependent beauty», explaining that «the first presupposes no concept of what the object ought to be; the second does presuppose such a concept and the perfection of the object in accordance therewith.»[57] By this definition, free beauty is found in seashells and wordless music; dependent beauty in buildings and the human body.[57]
The Romantic poets, too, became highly concerned with the nature of beauty, with John Keats arguing in Ode on a Grecian Urn that:
- Beauty is truth, truth beauty, —that is all
- Ye know on earth, and all ye need to know.
Western 19th and 20th century
In the Romantic period, Edmund Burke postulated a difference between beauty in its classical meaning and the sublime.[58] The concept of the sublime, as explicated by Burke and Kant, suggested viewing Gothic art and architecture, though not in accordance with the classical standard of beauty, as sublime.[59]
The 20th century saw an increasing rejection of beauty by artists and philosophers alike, culminating in postmodernism’s anti-aesthetics.[60] This is despite beauty being a central concern of one of postmodernism’s main influences, Friedrich Nietzsche, who argued that the Will to Power was the Will to Beauty.[61]
In the aftermath of postmodernism’s rejection of beauty, thinkers have returned to beauty as an important value. American analytic philosopher Guy Sircello proposed his New Theory of Beauty as an effort to reaffirm the status of beauty as an important philosophical concept.[62][63] He rejected the subjectivism of Kant and sought to identify the properties inherent in an object that make it beautiful. He called qualities such as vividness, boldness, and subtlety «properties of qualitative degree» (PQDs) and stated that a PQD makes an object beautiful if it is not—and does not create the appearance of—»a property of deficiency, lack, or defect»; and if the PQD is strongly present in the object.[64]
Elaine Scarry argues that beauty is related to justice.[65]
Beauty is also studied by psychologists and neuroscientists in the field of experimental aesthetics and neuroesthetics respectively. Psychological theories see beauty as a form of pleasure.[66][67] Correlational findings support the view that more beautiful objects are also more pleasing.[68][69][70] Some studies suggest that higher experienced beauty is associated with activity in the medial orbitofrontal cortex.[71][72] This approach of localizing the processing of beauty in one brain region has received criticism within the field.[73]
Philosopher and novelist Umberto Eco wrote On Beauty: A History of a Western Idea (2004)[74] and On Ugliness (2007).[75] The narrator of his novel The Name of the Rose follows Aquinas in declaring: «three things concur in creating beauty: first of all integrity or perfection, and for this reason, we consider ugly all incomplete things; then proper proportion or consonance; and finally clarity and light», before going on to say «the sight of the beautiful implies peace».[76][77]
Chinese philosophy
Chinese philosophy has traditionally not made a separate discipline of the philosophy of beauty.[78] Confucius identified beauty with goodness, and considered a virtuous personality to be the greatest of beauties: In his philosophy, «a neighborhood with a ren man in it is a beautiful neighborhood.»[79] Confucius’s student Zeng Shen expressed a similar idea: «few men could see the beauty in some one whom they dislike.»[79] Mencius considered «complete truthfulness» to be beauty.[80] Zhu Xi said: «When one has strenuously implemented goodness until it is filled to completion and has accumulated truth, then the beauty will reside within it and will not depend on externals.»[80]
As an attribute to humans
The word «beauty» is often[how often?] used as a countable noun to describe a beautiful woman.[81][82]
The characterization of a person as «beautiful», whether on an individual basis or by community consensus, is often[how often?] based on some combination of inner beauty, which includes psychological factors such as personality, intelligence, grace, politeness, charisma, integrity, congruence and elegance, and outer beauty (i.e. physical attractiveness) which includes physical attributes which are valued on an aesthetic basis.[citation needed]
Standards of beauty have changed over time, based on changing cultural values. Historically, paintings show a wide range of different standards for beauty.[83][84] However, humans who are relatively young, with smooth skin, well-proportioned bodies, and regular features, have traditionally been considered the most beautiful throughout history.[citation needed]
A strong indicator of physical beauty is «averageness».[85][86][87][88][89] When images of human faces are averaged together to form a composite image, they become progressively closer to the «ideal» image and are perceived as more attractive. This was first noticed in 1883, when Francis Galton overlaid photographic composite images of the faces of vegetarians and criminals to see if there was a typical facial appearance for each. When doing this, he noticed that the composite images were more attractive compared to any of the individual images.[90] Researchers have replicated the result under more controlled conditions and found that the computer-generated, mathematical average of a series of faces is rated more favorably than individual faces.[91] It is argued that it is evolutionarily advantageous that sexual creatures are attracted to mates who possess predominantly common or average features, because it suggests the absence of genetic or acquired defects.[85][92][93][94]
Since the 1970’s there has been increasing evidence that a preference for beautiful faces emerges early in infancy, and is probably innate,[95][96][86][97][98]
and that the rules by which attractiveness is established are similar across different genders and cultures.[99][100]
A feature of beautiful women which has been explored by researchers is a waist–hip ratio of approximately 0.70. As of 2004, physiologists had shown that women with hourglass figures were more fertile than other women because of higher levels of certain female hormones, a fact that may subconsciously condition males choosing mates.[101][102] However, in 2008 other commentators have suggested that this preference may not be universal. For instance, in some non-Western cultures in which women have to do work such as finding food, men tend to have preferences for higher waist-hip ratios.[103][104][105]
Exposure to the thin ideal in mass media, such as fashion magazines, directly correlates with body dissatisfaction, low self-esteem, and the development of eating disorders among female viewers.[106][107] Further, the widening gap between individual body sizes and societal ideals continues to breed anxiety among young girls as they grow, highlighting the dangerous nature of beauty standards in society.[108]
Western concept
Beauty standards are rooted in cultural norms crafted by societies and media over centuries. As of 2018, it has been argued that the predominance of white women featured in movies and advertising leads to a Eurocentric concept of beauty, which assigns inferiority to women of color.[109] Thus, societies and cultures across the globe struggle to diminish the longstanding internalized racism.[110]
Eurocentric standards for men include tallness, leanness, and muscularity, which have been idolized through American media, such as in Hollywood films and magazine covers.[111]
The prevailing Eurocentric concept of beauty has varying effects on different cultures. Primarily, adherence to this standard among African American women has bred a lack of positive reification of African beauty, and philosopher Cornel West elaborates that, «much of black self-hatred and self-contempt has to do with the refusal of many black Americans to love their own black bodies-especially their black noses, hips, lips, and hair.»[112] These insecurities can be traced back to global idealization of women with light skin, green or blue eyes, and long straight or wavy hair in magazines and media that starkly contrast with the natural features of African women.[113]
Much criticism has been directed at models of beauty which depend solely upon Western ideals of beauty as seen for example in the Barbie model franchise. Criticisms of Barbie are often centered around concerns that children consider Barbie a role model of beauty and will attempt to emulate her. One of the most common criticisms of Barbie is that she promotes an unrealistic idea of body image for a young woman, leading to a risk that girls who attempt to emulate her will become anorexic.[114]
As of 1998, these criticisms, the lack of diversity in such franchises as the Barbie model of beauty in Western culture, had led to a dialogue to create non-exclusive models of Western ideals in body type and beauty.[115] Mattel responded to these criticisms. Starting in 1980, it produced Hispanic dolls, and later came models from across the globe. For example, in 2007, it introduced «Cinco de Mayo Barbie» wearing a ruffled red, white, and green dress (echoing the Mexican flag). Hispanic magazine reports that:
[O]ne of the most dramatic developments in Barbie’s history came when she embraced multi-culturalism and was released in a wide variety of native costumes, hair colors and skin tones to more closely resemble the girls who idolized her. Among these were Cinco De Mayo Barbie, Spanish Barbie, Peruvian Barbie, Mexican Barbie and Puerto Rican Barbie. She also has had close Hispanic friends, such as Teresa.[116]
Black concept
This section needs expansion. You can help by adding to it. (November 2022) |
In the 1960s the black is beautiful cultural movement sought to dispel the notion of a Eurocentric concept of beauty.[117]
Asian concept
An Indian woman in her traditional attire
In East Asian cultures, familial pressures and cultural norms shape beauty ideals; a 2017 experimental study concluded that expecting that men in Asian culture did not like women who look «fragile» was impacting Asian American women’s lifestyle, eating, and appearance choices.[118][119] In addition to the «male gaze», media portrayals of Asian women as petite and the portrayal of beautiful women in American media as fair complexioned and slim-figured have induced anxiety and depressive symptoms among Asian American women who do not fit either of these beauty ideals.[118][119] Further, the high status associated with fairer skin can be attributed to Asian societal history, as upper-class people hired workers to perform outdoor, manual labor, cultivating a visual divide over time between lighter complexioned, wealthier families and sun tanned, darker laborers.[119] This along with the Eurocentric beauty ideals embedded in Asian culture has made skin lightening creams, rhinoplasty, and blepharoplasty (an eyelid surgery meant to give Asians a more European, «double-eyelid» appearance) commonplace among Asian women, illuminating the insecurity that results from cultural beauty standards.[119]
In Japan, the concept of beauty in men is known as ‘bishōnen’. Bishōnen refers to males with distinctly feminine features, physical characteristics establishing the standard of beauty in Japan and typically exhibited in their pop culture idols. A multibillion-dollar industry of Japanese Aesthetic Salons exists for this reason.[citation needed]
Effects on society
Researchers have found that good-looking students get higher grades from their teachers than students with an ordinary appearance.[120] Some studies using mock criminal trials have shown that physically attractive «defendants» are less likely to be convicted—and if convicted are likely to receive lighter sentences—than less attractive ones (although the opposite effect was observed when the alleged crime was swindling, perhaps because jurors perceived the defendant’s attractiveness as facilitating the crime).[121] Studies among teens and young adults, such as those of psychiatrist and self-help author Eva Ritvo show that skin conditions have a profound effect on social behavior and opportunity.[122]
How much money a person earns may also be influenced by physical beauty. One study found that people low in physical attractiveness earn 5 to 10 percent less than ordinary-looking people, who in turn earn 3 to 8 percent less than those who are considered good-looking.[123] In the market for loans, the least attractive people are less likely to get approvals, although they are less likely to default. In the marriage market, women’s looks are at a premium, but men’s looks do not matter much.[124] The impact of physical attractiveness on earnings varies across races, with the largest beauty wage gap among black women and black men.[125]
Conversely, being very unattractive increases the individual’s propensity for criminal activity for a number of crimes ranging from burglary to theft to selling illicit drugs.[126]
Discrimination against others based on their appearance is known as lookism.[127]
See also
- Adornment
- Aesthetics
- Beauty pageant
- Body modification
- Feminine beauty ideal
- Glamour (presentation)
- Masculine beauty ideal
- Mathematical beauty
- Processing fluency theory of aesthetic pleasure
- Unattractiveness
- Cosmetics
References
- ^ a b Stegers, Rudolf (2008). Sacred Buildings: A Design Manual. Berlin: De Gruyter. p. 60. ISBN 3764382767.
- ^ Gary Martin (2007). «Beauty is in the eye of the beholder». The Phrase Finder. Archived from the original on November 30, 2007. Retrieved December 4, 2007.
- ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v Sartwell, Crispin (2017). «Beauty». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on February 26, 2022. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
- ^ a b c d e «Aesthetics». Encyclopedia Britannica. Archived from the original on February 28, 2022. Retrieved February 9, 2021.
- ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l «Beauty and Ugliness». Encyclopedia.com. Archived from the original on December 24, 2021. Retrieved February 9, 2021.
- ^ a b «Beauty in Aesthetics». Encyclopedia.com. Archived from the original on January 13, 2022. Retrieved February 9, 2021.
- ^ a b Levinson, Jerrold (2003). «Philosophical Aesthetics: An Overview». The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics. Oxford University Press. pp. 3–24. Archived from the original on February 10, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
- ^ Kriegel, Uriah (2019). «The Value of Consciousness». Analysis. 79 (3): 503–520. doi:10.1093/analys/anz045. Archived from the original on January 11, 2022. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
- ^ a b c d e f g h i j De Clercq, Rafael (2013). «Beauty». The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics. Routledge. Archived from the original on January 13, 2022. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
- ^ a b c d e f g h i Zangwill, Nick (2003). «Beauty». In Levinson, Jerrold (ed.). Oxford Handbook to Aesthetics. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199279456.003.0018. Archived from the original on January 11, 2022. Retrieved February 16, 2021.
- ^ a b c d e f g h i De Clercq, Rafael (2019). «Aesthetic Pleasure Explained». Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism. 77 (2): 121–132. doi:10.1111/jaac.12636.
- ^ a b c d Gorodeisky, Keren (2019). «On Liking Aesthetic Value». Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 102 (2): 261–280. doi:10.1111/phpr.12641. S2CID 204522523.
- ^ Honderich, Ted (2005). «Aesthetic judgment». The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
- ^ Scruton, Roger (2011). Beauty: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press. p. 5. Archived from the original on March 10, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
- ^ Rogerson, Kenneth F. (1982). «The Meaning of Universal Validity in Kant’s Aesthetics». The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism. 40 (3): 304. doi:10.2307/429687. JSTOR 429687. Archived from the original on February 10, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
- ^ Uzgalis, William (2020). «John Locke». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on April 24, 2021. Retrieved February 9, 2021.
- ^ Berg, Servaas Van der (2020). «Aesthetic Hedonism and Its Critics». Philosophy Compass. 15 (1): e12645. doi:10.1111/phc3.12645. S2CID 213973255. Archived from the original on February 11, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
- ^ Matthen, Mohan; Weinstein, Zachary. «Aesthetic Hedonism». Oxford Bibliographies. Archived from the original on January 18, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
- ^ Honderich, Ted (2005). «Beauty». The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
- ^ Spicher, Michael R. «Aesthetic Taste». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on February 14, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
- ^ a b c Craig, Edward (1996). «Beauty». Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. Archived from the original on January 16, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
- ^ Hansson, Sven Ove (2005). «Aesthetic Functionalism». Contemporary Aesthetics. 3. Archived from the original on February 13, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
- ^ Konstan, David (2014). Beauty — The Fortunes of an Ancient Greek Idea. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 30–35. ISBN 978-0-19-992726-5.
- ^ Matthew 23:27, Acts 3:10, Flavius Josephus, 12.65
- ^ a b Euripides, Alcestis 515.
- ^ a b G Parsons (2008). Aesthetics and Nature. A&C Black. p. 7. ISBN 978-0826496768. Archived from the original on February 3, 2023. Retrieved May 11, 2015.
- ^ a b c d J. Harrell; C. Barrett; D. Petsch, eds. (2006). History of Aesthetics. A&C Black. p. 102. ISBN 0826488552. Archived from the original on February 3, 2023. Retrieved May 11, 2015.
- ^ P.T. Struck — The Trojan War Archived December 22, 2021, at the Wayback Machine Classics Department of University of Penn [Retrieved 2015-05-12]( < 1250> )
- ^ R Highfield — Scientists calculate the exact date of the Trojan horse using eclipse in Homer Archived December 24, 2021, at the Wayback Machine Telegraph Media Group Limited 24 Jun 2008 [Retrieved 2015-05-12]
- ^ Bronze Age first source C Freeman — Egypt, Greece, and Rome: Civilizations of the Ancient Mediterranean — p.116 Archived February 3, 2023, at the Wayback Machine, verified at A. F. Harding — European Societies in the Bronze Age — p.1 Archived February 3, 2023, at the Wayback Machine [Retrieved 2015-05-12]
- ^ Sources for War with Troy Archived December 8, 2015, at the Wayback Machine Cambridge University Classics Department [Retrieved 2015-05-12]( < 750, 850 > )
- ^ the most beautiful — C.Braider — The Cambridge History of Literary Criticism: Volume 3 Archived February 3, 2023, at the Wayback Machine, The Renaissance: Zeuxis portrait (p.174) ISBN 0521300088 — Ed. G.A. Kennedy, G.P. Norton & The British Museum — Helen runs off with Paris Archived October 11, 2015, at the Wayback Machine [Retrieved 2015-05-12]
- ^ W.W. Clohesy — The Strength of the Invisible: Reflections on Heraclitus (p.177) Archived August 12, 2017, at the Wayback Machine Auslegung Volume XIII ISSN 0733-4311 [Retrieved 2015-05-12]
- ^ a b c Fistioc, M.C. (December 5, 2002). The Beautiful Shape of the Good: Platonic and Pythagorean Themes in Kant’s Critique of the Power of Judgment. Review by S Naragon, Manchester College. Routledge, 2002 (University of Notre Dame philosophy reviews). Archived from the original on January 22, 2016. Retrieved May 11, 2015.
- ^ a b c J.L. Wright. Review of The Beautiful Shape of the Good:Platonic and Pythagorean Themes in Kant’s Critique of the Power of Judgment by M.C.Fistioc Volume 4 Issue 2 Medical Research Ethics. Pacific University Library. Archived from the original on March 4, 2016. Retrieved May 11, 2015.(ed. 4th paragraph — beauty and the divine)
- ^ Seife, Charles (2000). Zero: The Biography of a Dangerous Idea. Penguin. p. 32. ISBN 0-14-029647-6.
- ^ a b Sartwell, C. Edward N. Zalta (ed.). Beauty. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition). Archived from the original on January 18, 2021. Retrieved May 11, 2015.
- ^ a b L Cheney (2007). Giorgio Vasari’s Teachers: Sacred & Profane Art. Peter Lang. p. 118. ISBN 978-0820488134. Archived from the original on February 3, 2023. Retrieved May 11, 2015.
- ^ N Wilson — Encyclopedia of Ancient Greece (p.20) Routledge, 31 Oct 2013 ISBN 113678800X [Retrieved 2015-05-12]
- ^ K Urstad. Loving Socrates:The Individual and the Ladder of Love in Plato’s Symposium (PDF). Res Cogitans 2010 no.7, vol. 1. Archived from the original (PDF) on October 10, 2015. Retrieved May 11, 2015.
- ^ a b W. K. C. Guthrie; J. Warren (2012). The Greek Philosophers from Thales to Aristotle (p.112). Routledge. ISBN 978-0415522281. Retrieved May 12, 2015.
- ^ a b A Preus (1996). Notes on Greek Philosophy from Thales to Aristotle (parts 198 and 210). Global Academic Publishing. ISBN 1883058090. Retrieved May 12, 2015.
- ^ S Scolnicov (2003). Plato’s Parmenides. University of California Press. p. 21. ISBN 0520925114. Retrieved May 12, 2015.
- ^ Phaedrus
- ^ D. Konstan (2014). Beauty — The Fortunes of an Ancient Greek Idea. published by Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0199927265. Retrieved November 24, 2015.
- ^ F. McGhee — review of text written by David Konstan Archived March 10, 2021, at the Wayback Machine published by the Oxonian Review March 31, 2015 [Retrieved 2015-11-24](references not sources: Bryn Mawr Classical Review 2014.06.08 (Donald Sells) Archived November 26, 2014, at the Wayback Machine + DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199605507.001.0001 Archived July 16, 2020, at the Wayback Machine)
- ^ Nicomachean Ethics
- ^ M Garani (2007). Empedocles Redivivus: Poetry and Analogy in Lucretius. Routledge. ISBN 978-1135859831. Archived from the original on February 3, 2023. Retrieved May 12, 2015.
- ^ Eco, Umberto (1988). The Aesthetics of Thomas Aquinas. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard Univ. Press. p. 98. ISBN 0674006755.
- ^ McNamara, Denis Robert (2009). Catholic Church Architecture and the Spirit of the Liturgy. Hillenbrand Books. pp. 24–28. ISBN 1595250271.
- ^ Duiker, William J., and Spielvogel, Jackson J. (2019). World History. United States: Cengage Learning. p. 351. ISBN 1337401048
- ^ «NPNF1-02. St. Augustine’s City of God and Christian Doctrine — Christian Classics Ethereal Library». CCEL. Archived from the original on July 1, 2017. Retrieved May 1, 2018.
- ^ Ames-Lewis, Francis (2000), The Intellectual Life of the Early Renaissance Artist, New Haven, Connecticut: Yale University Press, p. 194, ISBN 0-300-09295-4
- ^ Francis Hutcheson (1726). An Inquiry Into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue: In Two Treatises. J. Darby. ISBN 9780598982698. Archived from the original on February 3, 2023. Retrieved June 14, 2020.
- ^ Kennick, William Elmer (1979). Art and Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics; 2nd ed. New York: St. Martin’s Press. p. 421. ISBN 0312053916.
- ^ Kennick, William Elmer (1979). Art and Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics; 2nd ed. New York: St. Martin’s Press. pp. 482–483. ISBN 0312053916.
- ^ a b Kennick, William Elmer (1979). Art and Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics; 2nd ed. New York: St. Martin’s Press. p. 517. ISBN 0312053916.
- ^ Doran, Robert (2017). The Theory of the Sublime from Longinus to Kant. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 144. ISBN 1107499151.
- ^ Monk, Samuel Holt (1960). The Sublime: A Study of Critical Theories in XVIII-century England. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. pp. 6–9, 141. OCLC 943884.
- ^ Hal Foster (1998). The Anti-aesthetic: Essays on Postmodern Culture. New Press. ISBN 978-1-56584-462-9.
- ^ Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche (1967). The Will To Power. Random House. ISBN 978-0-394-70437-1.
- ^ Guy Sircello, A New Theory of Beauty. Princeton Essays on the Arts, 1. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1975.
- ^ Love and Beauty. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989.
- ^ Kennick, William Elmer (1979). Art and Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics; 2nd ed. New York: St. Martin’s Press. pp. 535–537. ISBN 0312053916.
- ^ Elaine Scarry (November 4, 2001). On Beauty and Being Just. Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-08959-0.
- ^ Reber, Rolf; Schwarz, Norbert; Winkielman, Piotr (November 2004). «Processing Fluency and Aesthetic Pleasure: Is Beauty in the Perceiver’s Processing Experience?». Personality and Social Psychology Review. 8 (4): 364–382. doi:10.1207/s15327957pspr0804_3. hdl:1956/594. PMID 15582859. S2CID 1868463.
- ^ Armstrong, Thomas; Detweiler-Bedell, Brian (December 2008). «Beauty as an Emotion: The Exhilarating Prospect of Mastering a Challenging World». Review of General Psychology. 12 (4): 305–329. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.406.1825. doi:10.1037/a0012558. S2CID 8375375.
- ^ Vartanian, Oshin; Navarrete, Gorka; Chatterjee, Anjan; Fich, Lars Brorson; Leder, Helmut; Modroño, Cristián; Nadal, Marcos; Rostrup, Nicolai; Skov, Martin (June 18, 2013). «Impact of contour on aesthetic judgments and approach-avoidance decisions in architecture». Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 110 (Suppl 2): 10446–10453. doi:10.1073/pnas.1301227110. PMC 3690611. PMID 23754408.
- ^ Marin, Manuela M.; Lampatz, Allegra; Wandl, Michaela; Leder, Helmut (November 4, 2016). «Berlyne Revisited: Evidence for the Multifaceted Nature of Hedonic Tone in the Appreciation of Paintings and Music». Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. 10: 536. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2016.00536. PMC 5095118. PMID 27867350.
- ^ Brielmann, Aenne A.; Pelli, Denis G. (May 2017). «Beauty Requires Thought». Current Biology. 27 (10): 1506–1513.e3. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2017.04.018. PMC 6778408. PMID 28502660.
- ^ Kawabata, Hideaki; Zeki, Semir (April 2004). «Neural Correlates of Beauty». Journal of Neurophysiology. 91 (4): 1699–1705. doi:10.1152/jn.00696.2003. PMID 15010496.
- ^ Ishizu, Tomohiro; Zeki, Semir (July 6, 2011). «Toward A Brain-Based Theory of Beauty». PLOS ONE. 6 (7): e21852. Bibcode:2011PLoSO…621852I. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0021852. PMC 3130765. PMID 21755004.
- ^ Conway, Bevil R.; Rehding, Alexander (March 19, 2013). «Neuroaesthetics and the Trouble with Beauty». PLOS Biology. 11 (3): e1001504. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.1001504. PMC 3601993. PMID 23526878.
- ^ Eco, Umberto (2004). On Beauty: A historyof a western idea. London: Secker & Warburg. ISBN 978-0436205170.[non-primary source needed]
- ^ Eco, Umberto (2007). On Ugliness. London: Harvill Secker. ISBN 9781846551222.[non-primary source needed]
- ^ Eco, Umberto (1980). The Name of the Rose. London: Vintage. p. 65. ISBN 9780099466031.
- ^ Fasolini, Diego (2006). «The Intrusion of Laughter into the Abbey of Umberto Eco’s The Name of the Rose: The Christian paradox of Joy Mingling with Sorrow». Romance Notes. 46 (2): 119–129. JSTOR 43801801.
- ^ The Chinese Text: Studies in Comparative Literature (1986). Cocos (Keeling) Islands: Chinese University Press. p. 119. ISBN 962201318X.
- ^ a b Chang, Chi-yun (2013). Confucianism: A Modern Interpretation (2012 Edition). Singapore: World Scientific Publishing Company. p. 213. ISBN 9814439894
- ^ a b Tang, Yijie (2015). Confucianism, Buddhism, Daoism, Christianity and Chinese Culture. Springer Berlin Heidelberg. p. 242. ISBN 3662455331
- ^ «Beauty | Definition of Beauty by Oxford Dictionary on Lexico.com». Lexico Dictionaries | English. Archived from the original on August 9, 2020. Retrieved August 1, 2020.
- ^ «BEAUTY (noun) American English definition and synonyms | Macmillan Dictionary». Macmillan Dictionary. Archived from the original on July 9, 2017. Retrieved August 1, 2020.
- ^ Artists’ Types of Beauty Archived February 3, 2023, at the Wayback Machine», The Strand Magazine. United Kingdom, G. Newnes, 1904. pp. 291–298.
- ^ Chō, Kyō (2012). The Search for the Beautiful Woman: A Cultural History of Japanese and Chinese Beauty. Translated by Selden, Kyoko Iriye. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 100–102. ISBN 978-1442218956..
- ^ a b Langlois, Judith H.; Roggman, Lori A. (1990). «Attractive Faces Are Only Average». Psychological Science. 1 (2): 115–121. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.1990.tb00079.x. S2CID 18557871.
- ^ a b Strauss, Mark S. (1979). «Abstraction of prototypical information by adults and 10-month-old infants». Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory. 5 (6): 618–632. doi:10.1037/0278-7393.5.6.618. PMID 528918.
- ^ Rhodes, Gillian; Tremewan, Tanya (1996). «Averageness, Exaggeration, and Facial Attractiveness». Psychological Science. SAGE Publications. 7 (2): 105–110. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.1996.tb00338.x. S2CID 145245882.
- ^ Valentine, Tim; Darling, Stephen; Donnelly, Mary (2004). «Why are average faces attractive? The effect of view and averageness on the attractiveness of female faces». Psychonomic Bulletin & Review. Springer Science and Business Media LLC. 11 (3): 482–487. doi:10.3758/bf03196599. ISSN 1069-9384. PMID 15376799. S2CID 25389002.
- ^ «The Beauty of Averageness». Langlois Social Development Lab. Archived from the original on February 4, 2015. Retrieved May 1, 2018.
- ^ Galton, Francis (1879). «Composite Portraits, Made by Combining Those of Many Different Persons Into a Single Resultant Figure». The Journal of the Anthropological Institute of Great Britain and Ireland. JSTOR. 8: 132–144. doi:10.2307/2841021. ISSN 0959-5295. JSTOR 2841021. Archived from the original on July 26, 2020. Retrieved June 14, 2020.
- ^ Langlois, Judith H.; Roggman, Lori A.; Musselman, Lisa (1994). «What Is Average and What Is Not Average About Attractive Faces?». Psychological Science. SAGE Publications. 5 (4): 214–220. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.1994.tb00503.x. ISSN 0956-7976. S2CID 145147905.
- ^ Koeslag, Johan H. (1990). «Koinophilia groups sexual creatures into species, promotes stasis, and stabilizes social behaviour». Journal of Theoretical Biology. Elsevier BV. 144 (1): 15–35. Bibcode:1990JThBi.144…15K. doi:10.1016/s0022-5193(05)80297-8. ISSN 0022-5193. PMID 2200930.
- ^ Symons, D. (1979) The Evolution of Human Sexuality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- ^ Highfield, Roger (May 7, 2008). «Why beauty is an advert for good genes». The Daily Telegraph. Archived from the original on January 11, 2022. Retrieved February 13, 2012.
- ^ Slater, Alan; Von der Schulenburg, Charlotte; Brown, Elizabeth; Badenoch, Marion; Butterworth, George; Parsons, Sonia; Samuels, Curtis (1998). «Newborn infants prefer attractive faces». Infant Behavior and Development. Elsevier BV. 21 (2): 345–354. doi:10.1016/s0163-6383(98)90011-x. ISSN 0163-6383.
- ^ Kramer, Steve; Zebrowitz, Leslie; Giovanni, Jean Paul San; Sherak, Barbara (February 21, 2019). «Infants’ Preferences for Attractiveness and Babyfaceness». Studies in Perception and Action III. Routledge. pp. 389–392. doi:10.4324/9781315789361-103. ISBN 978-1-315-78936-1. S2CID 197734413.
- ^ Rubenstein, Adam J.; Kalakanis, Lisa; Langlois, Judith H. (1999). «Infant preferences for attractive faces: A cognitive explanation». Developmental Psychology. American Psychological Association (APA). 35 (3): 848–855. doi:10.1037/0012-1649.35.3.848. ISSN 1939-0599. PMID 10380874.
- ^ Langlois, Judith H.; Ritter, Jean M.; Roggman, Lori A.; Vaughn, Lesley S. (1991). «Facial diversity and infant preferences for attractive faces». Developmental Psychology. American Psychological Association (APA). 27 (1): 79–84. doi:10.1037/0012-1649.27.1.79. ISSN 1939-0599.
- ^ Apicella, Coren L; Little, Anthony C; Marlowe, Frank W (2007). «Facial Averageness and Attractiveness in an Isolated Population of Hunter-Gatherers». Perception. SAGE Publications. 36 (12): 1813–1820. doi:10.1068/p5601. ISSN 0301-0066. PMID 18283931. S2CID 37353815.
- ^ Rhodes, Gillian (2006). «The Evolutionary Psychology of Facial Beauty». Annual Review of Psychology. Annual Reviews. 57 (1): 199–226. doi:10.1146/annurev.psych.57.102904.190208. ISSN 0066-4308. PMID 16318594.
- ^ «Hourglass figure fertility link». BBC News. May 4, 2004. Archived from the original on October 11, 2011. Retrieved July 1, 2018.
- ^ Bhattacharya, Shaoni (May 5, 2004). «Barbie-shaped women more fertile». New Scientist. Archived from the original on July 10, 2018. Retrieved July 1, 2018.
- ^ «Best Female Figure Not an Hourglass». Live Science. December 3, 2008. Archived from the original on July 10, 2018. Retrieved July 1, 2018.
- ^ Locke, Susannah (June 22, 2014). «Did evolution really make men prefer women with hourglass figures?». Vox. Archived from the original on July 10, 2018. Retrieved July 1, 2018.
- ^ Begley, Sharon. «Hourglass Figures: We Take It All Back». Sharon Begley. Archived from the original on July 10, 2018. Retrieved July 1, 2018.
- ^ «Media & Eating Disorders». National Eating Disorders Association. October 5, 2017. Archived from the original on December 2, 2018. Retrieved November 27, 2018.
- ^ «Model’s link to teenage anorexia». BBC News. May 30, 2000. Archived from the original on April 13, 2020. Retrieved October 25, 2009.
- ^ Jade, Deanne. «National Centre for Eating Disorders — The Media & Eating Disorders». National Centre for Eating Disorders. Archived from the original on December 24, 2018. Retrieved November 27, 2018.
- ^ Harper, Kathryn; Choma, Becky L. (October 5, 2018). «Internalised White Ideal, Skin Tone Surveillance, and Hair Surveillance Predict Skin and Hair Dissatisfaction and Skin Bleaching among African American and Indian Women». Sex Roles. 80 (11–12): 735–744. doi:10.1007/s11199-018-0966-9. ISSN 0360-0025. S2CID 150156045.
- ^ Weedon, Chris (December 6, 2007). «Key Issues in Postcolonial Feminism: A Western Perspective». Gender Forum Electronic Journal.
- ^ «The New (And Impossible) Standards of Male Beauty». Paging Dr. NerdLove. January 26, 2015. Archived from the original on December 29, 2018. Retrieved November 27, 2018.
- ^ West, Cornel (1994). Race Matters. Vintage Books. ISBN 978-0-679-74986-8.[page needed]
- ^ Patton, Tracey Owens (July 2006). «Hey Girl, Am I More than My Hair?: African American Women and Their Struggles with Beauty, Body Image, and Hair». NWSA Journal. 18 (2): 24–51. JSTOR 4317206. Project MUSE 199496 ProQuest 233235409.
- ^ Dittmar, Helga; Halliwell, Emma; Ive, Suzanne (March 2006). «Does Barbie make girls want to be thin? The effect of experimental exposure to images of dolls on the body image of 5- to 8-year-old girls». Developmental Psychology. 42 (2): 283–292. doi:10.1037/0012-1649.42.2.283. PMID 16569167.
- ^ Marco Tosa (1998). Barbie: Four Decades of Fashion, Fantasy, and Fun. H.N. Abrams. ISBN 978-0-8109-4008-6.[page needed]
- ^ «A Barbie for Everyone». Hispanic. 22 (1). February–March 2009.
- ^ DoCarmo, Stephen. «Notes on the Black Cultural Movement». Bucks County Community College. Archived from the original on April 8, 2005. Retrieved November 27, 2007.
- ^ a b Wong, Stephanie N.; Keum, Brian TaeHyuk; Caffarel, Daniel; Srinivasan, Ranjana; Morshedian, Negar; Capodilupo, Christina M.; Brewster, Melanie E. (December 2017). «Exploring the conceptualization of body image for Asian American women». Asian American Journal of Psychology. 8 (4): 296–307. doi:10.1037/aap0000077. S2CID 151560804.
- ^ a b c d Le, C.N. (June 4, 2014). «The Homogenization of Asian Beauty». The Society Pages. Archived from the original on December 2, 2018. Retrieved December 1, 2018.[self-published source?]
- ^ Begley, Sharon (July 14, 2009). «The Link Between Beauty and Grades». Newsweek. Archived from the original on April 20, 2010. Retrieved May 31, 2010.
- ^ Amina A Memon; Aldert Vrij; Ray Bull (October 31, 2003). Psychology and Law: Truthfulness, Accuracy and Credibility. John Wiley & Sons. pp. 46–47. ISBN 978-0-470-86835-5.
- ^ «Image survey reveals «perception is reality» when it comes to teenagers» (Press release). multivu.prnewswire.com. Archived from the original on July 10, 2012.
- ^ Lorenz, K. (2005). «Do pretty people earn more?». CNN News. Time Warner. Cable News Network. Archived from the original on October 12, 2015. Retrieved January 31, 2007.
- ^ Daniel Hamermesh; Stephen J. Dubner (January 30, 2014). «Reasons to not be ugly: full transcript». Freakonomics. Archived from the original on March 1, 2014. Retrieved March 4, 2014.
- ^ Monk, Ellis P.; Esposito, Michael H.; Lee, Hedwig (July 1, 2021). «Beholding Inequality: Race, Gender, and Returns to Physical Attractiveness in the United States». American Journal of Sociology. 127 (1): 194–241. doi:10.1086/715141. S2CID 235473652.
- ^ Erdal Tekin; Stephen J. Dubner (January 30, 2014). «Reasons to not be ugly: full transcript». Freakonomics. Archived from the original on March 1, 2014. Retrieved March 4, 2014.
- ^ Leo Gough (June 29, 2011). C. Northcote Parkinson’s Parkinson’s Law: A modern-day interpretation of a management classic. Infinite Ideas. p. 36. ISBN 978-1-908189-71-4.
Further reading
- Richard O. Prum (2018). The Evolution of Beauty: How Darwin’s Forgotten Theory of Mate Choice Shapes the Animal World — and Us. Anchor. ISBN 978-0345804570.
- Liebelt, C. (2022), Beauty: What Makes Us Dream, What Haunts Us. Feminist Anthropology. https://doi.org/10.1002/fea2.12076
External links
Wikimedia Commons has media related to Beauty.
Wikiquote has quotations related to Beauty.
Look up beauty or pretty in Wiktionary, the free dictionary.
- Sartwell, Crispin. «Beauty». In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Beauty at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project
- BBC Radio 4’s In Our Time programme on Beauty (requires RealAudio)
- Dictionary of the History of Ideas: Theories of Beauty to the Mid-Nineteenth Century
- beautycheck.de/english Regensburg University – Characteristics of beautiful faces
- Eli Siegel’s «Is Beauty the Making One of Opposites?»
- Art and love in Renaissance Italy , Issued in connection with an exhibition held Nov. 11, 2008-Feb. 16, 2009, Metropolitan Museum of Art, New York (see Belle: Picturing Beautiful Women; pages 246–254).
- Plato — Symposium in S. Marc Cohen, Patricia Curd, C. D. C. Reeve (ed.)
- Arabic: جَمَال (ar) m (jamāl), زَيْن (ar) m (zayn)
- Egyptian Arabic: جمال m (gamāl)
- Moroccan Arabic: زين m (zayn), زين m (zīn)
- Armenian: գեղեցկություն (hy) (gełecʿkutʿyun)
- Aramaic:
- Assyrian Neo-Aramaic: ܫܘܼܦܪܵܐ (šupra)
- Azerbaijani: gözəllik (az), hüsn (poetic)
- Belarusian: прыгажо́сць f (pryhažóscʹ), хараство́ n (xarastvó), краса́ f (krasá)
- Bengali: খুবসুরতী (khubsurôtī), জামাল (jamal), সৌন্দর্য (bn) (śōundorjo)
- Berber: aẓři, aẓli, tiẓilt
- Bulgarian: ху́бост (bg) f (húbost), красота́ (bg) f (krasotá), пре́лест (bg) f (prélest)
- Catalan: bellesa (ca) f
- Chinese:
- Mandarin: 美麗/美丽 (zh) (měilì), 漂亮 (zh) (piàoliang), 美 (zh) (měi)
- Wu: 美 (‘me1)
- Coptic: ⲙⲛⲧⲥⲁⲉⲓⲉ (mntsaeie)
- Czech: krása (cs) f
- Danish: skønhed c
- Dutch: schoonheid (nl) f
- Egyptian: (nfrw)
- Esperanto: belo
- Estonian: ilu
- Finnish: kauneus (fi)
- French: beauté (fr) f
- Friulian: bielece f
- Galician: beleza (gl) f, fermosura f
- Georgian: please add this translation if you can
- German: Schönheit (de) f
- Greek: ομορφιά (el) f (omorfiá)
- Ancient: κάλλος f (kállos)
- Hebrew: יופי m (yófi)
- Hindi: सौन्दर्य (saundarya), सुंदरता (hi) (sundartā), ख़ूबसूरती f (xūbsūrtī), हुस्न (hi) m (husna)
- Hungarian: szépség (hu)
- Icelandic: fegurð (is) f
- Ido: beleso (io)
- Ingrian: käpehys
- Irish: áilleacht f, spéiriúlacht f, áille f, scéimh f, maise f, breáichte f
- Istriot: balissa f
- Italian: bellezza (it) f
- Japanese: 美しさ (ja) (うつくしさ, utsukushisa), (component) 美 (ja) (び, bi)
- Korean: 아름다움 (ko) (areumdaum), 미(美) (ko) (mi)
- Kurdish:
- Central Kurdish: جوانی (ckb) (cwanî)
- Kyrgyz: сулуулук (ky) (suluuluk), кооздук (ky) (koozduk)
- Latin: pulchritūdō f, formōsitās f
- Latvian: daiļums m, skaistums m, glītums m
- Lithuanian: gražumas m, grožis (lt) m
- Low German: Schöönheit f
- Macedonian: уба́вина f (ubávina), красо́та f (krasóta), у́бост f (úbost)
- Maharastri Prakrit: 𑀭𑀽𑀅 (rūa)
- Malayalam: സൗന്ദര്യം (ml) (saundaryaṃ), മനോഹാരിത (ml) (manōhārita)
- Maltese: sbuħija f
- Manx: aalid m, aalinid, bwoyid m, stoamid
- Maori: rerehua
- Mongolian: гоо үзэсгэлэн (goo üzesgelen), сайхан байдал (sajxan bajdal)
- Nheengatu: purangasawa
- Norman: bieauté f (Jersey)
- Norwegian:
- Bokmål: skjønnhet (no) m or f
- Nynorsk: venleik (nn) m, skjønnheit (nn) f
- Occitan: belesa (oc) f
- Old English: fægernes f
- Old French: biauté f
- Persian: زیبایی (fa), جمال (fa), حسن (fa), قشنگی (fa)
- Plautdietsch: Scheenheit f
- Polish: piękno (pl) n, uroda (pl) f
- Portuguese: beleza (pt) f
- Romanian: frumusețe (ro) f
- Romansch: bellezza f (Rumantsch Grischun, Puter, Vallader), bellezia f (Sursilvan), baleztgia f (Sutsilvan), balegia f (Sutsilvan), belezza f (Surmiran)
- Russian: красота́ (ru) f (krasotá), пре́лесть (ru) f (prélestʹ), краса́ (ru) f (krasá) (dated), лепота́ (ru) f (lepotá) (dated, poetic)
- Sanskrit: इन्दिरा (sa) f (indirā)
- Sardinian: bellesa f
- Scots: beauty, brawness
- Scottish Gaelic: àilleachd f, maise f, sgèimh f, bòidhchead f
- Serbo-Croatian:
- Cyrillic: лепота f, красота f (poetic), бај m (poetic), дивота
- Roman: lepota (sh) f, krasota (sh) f (poetic), baj (sh) m (poetic), divota (sh)
- Sicilian: bidizza f
- Slovak: krása f
- Slovene: lepota (sl) f
- Somali: qurux
- Sorbian:
- Lower Sorbian: rědnosć f
- Spanish: belleza (es) f, hermosura (es) f, preciosidad f, preciosura f, beldad (es) f, lindeza (es) f
- Sudovian: grozis m
- Swahili: urembo (sw), uzuri (sw), jamala (sw)
- Swedish: skönhet (sv) c, fägring (sv) c (poetic)
- Tagalog: ganda, kagandahan
- Tajik: зебоӣ (tg) (zeboyī)
- Tamil: அழகு (ta) (aḻaku), எழில் (ta) (eḻil), சௌந்தரியம் (ta) (cauntariyam)
- Telugu: అందము (te) (andamu), చక్కదనము (te) (cakkadanamu)
- Thai: ความสวย (th) (kwaam-sǔai), ความสวยงาม (th) (kwaam-sǔai-ngaam)
- Tibetan: please add this translation if you can
- Turkish: güzellik (tr)
- Tuvan: чаражы (çarajı)
- Ukrainian: краса́ f (krasá), вро́да f (vróda)
- Urdu: خوبصورتی f (xūbsūrtī)
- Venetian: bełézsa f
- Volapük: jön (vo)
- Votic: ilozuz
- Welsh: harddwch m, prydferthwch m
- Yiddish: שיינקײַט f (sheynkayt)
1
: the quality or aggregate of qualities in a person or thing that gives pleasure to the senses or pleasurably exalts the mind or spirit : loveliness
a woman of great physical beauty
exploring the natural beauty of the island
A thing of beauty is a joy forever …—John Keats
2
: a beautiful person or thing
His new car’s a real beauty.
especially
: a beautiful woman
She was a great beauty in her day.
3
: a particularly graceful, ornamental, or excellent quality
Well, at any rate, he had two great beauties—the pale flat white of his skin and his great shaggy mass of dark hair.—Dorothy C. Fisher
4
: a brilliant, extreme, or egregious example or instance
caught a couple of beauties on our last fishing trip
that mistake was a beauty
Synonyms
Example Sentences
We explored the natural beauty of the island.
I’m learning to appreciate the beauty of poetry.
We explored the natural beauties of the island.
She was one of the great beauties of her time.
Recent Examples on the Web
Ali Kessler is a native New Yorker residing in the Sunshine State with expertise in hospitality, travel, the beauty industry, and electronics.
—Jessica Hartshorn, goodhousekeeping.com, 4 Apr. 2023
To celebrate the news, Smith took to their social media to share a compilation video of the song’s success, showing off behind-the-scenes clips from the shoot of the music video, as well as viral dance challenges, beauty tutorials and covers of the track from TikTok.
—Stephen Daw, Billboard, 4 Apr. 2023
Alana quickly became known for her sassy one-liners and her no-nonsense approach to the world of beauty pageants.
—Emma Kershaw, Peoplemag, 4 Apr. 2023
L’Oréal is freshening up its collection by buying Aesop, an Australian beauty brand, for an enterprise value of $2.5 billion.
—Dave Sebastian, WSJ, 4 Apr. 2023
The Depuffer is available for $38 on pillowtalkderm.com. play iconThe triangle icon that indicates to play Brian Underwood Brian Underwood is the beauty director at Women’s Health.
—Brian Underwood, Women’s Health, 4 Apr. 2023
Hours of scrolling the internet led me to this beauty.
—ELLE, 31 Mar. 2023
The harsh beauty of all of it was being able to put it all in front of that lens and leave it there.
—Helena Andrews-dyer, Washington Post, 31 Mar. 2023
The natural beauty is breathtaking and the wonder of sunsets (among other things) has not worn off.
—Ryan Fonseca, Los Angeles Times, 31 Mar. 2023
See More
These examples are programmatically compiled from various online sources to illustrate current usage of the word ‘beauty.’ Any opinions expressed in the examples do not represent those of Merriam-Webster or its editors. Send us feedback about these examples.
Word History
Etymology
Middle English beaute, bealte, borrowed from Anglo-French, from bel, beau «beautiful, good-looking» (going back to Latin bellus) + -te -ty — more at beau
First Known Use
14th century, in the meaning defined at sense 1
Time Traveler
The first known use of beauty was
in the 14th century
Dictionary Entries Near beauty
Cite this Entry
“Beauty.” Merriam-Webster.com Dictionary, Merriam-Webster, https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/beauty. Accessed 14 Apr. 2023.
Share
More from Merriam-Webster on beauty
Last Updated:
6 Apr 2023
— Updated example sentences
Subscribe to America’s largest dictionary and get thousands more definitions and advanced search—ad free!
Merriam-Webster unabridged
красота, красавица, прелесть, краса
существительное ↓
- красота; прекрасное
beauty of form [voice, melody, verse, feeling] — красота формы [голоса, мелодии, стиха, чувств]
spiritual beauty — духовная красота
beauty preparations — косметика; средства ухода за кожей и т. п.
beauty doctor — косметолог; косметичка
beauty culture — косметика, массаж, парикмахерское дело и т. п.
to be in the flower of one’s beauty — быть в расцвете красоты; блистать красотой
- часто pl привлекательная или красивая черта; украшение
beauties of nature — красоты природы
her smile was one of her beauties — улыбка была одним из её украшений
the poem contains a thousand beauties — в поэме тысячи прекрасных мест
- ирон. прелесть
that’s the beauty of it — в этом-то вся прелесть
I can’t say that I see the beauty of it — я не вижу в этом ничего смешного или интересного
his black eye was a beauty — синяк у него был — просто прелесть
you are a beauty, I must say — хорош же ты, нечего сказать
- красавица
faded beauties — увядшие /перезрелые/ красотки
- красотка, красавец (в обращении, преим. к лошадям и собакам)
- собир. библ., поэт. краса, цвет (народа и т. п.)
- разг. преимущество, достоинство
beauty is but skin-deep — ≅ нельзя судить о человеке по внешнему виду
Мои примеры
Словосочетания
the timeless beauty of the sea — вечная красота моря
the sublime beauty of the night — возвышенная красота ночи
celestial beauty — божественная красота
beauty contest — конкурс красоты
dreamlike beauty — призрачная красота
the pearl of beauty — эталон красоты
beauty shop — салон красоты
classic beauty — классическая красота
classical beauty — классическая красота
she has an ethereal beauty — она обладает неземной красотой
a beauty of a girl — красавица
an ideal of beauty — идеал красоты
Примеры с переводом
She was a beauty in her day.
В своё время она была красавицей.
She’s a creature of rare beauty.
Она — создание редкой красоты.
Beauty is only skin deep.
Красота обманчива. / С лица воду не пить. / Красота не глубже кожи.
Beauty inheres in art.
Искусству присуща красота.
Sleeping Beauty was enchanted
Спящая Красавица была заколдована
She is a ravishing beauty.
Она — очаровательная красавица.
You should have seen the boat — a real beauty.
Вы бы видели эту лодку — настоящая красавица.
ещё 23 примера свернуть
Примеры, ожидающие перевода
…a horse of unequaled beauty…
He was bowled over by her beauty.
“Beauty” and “truth” are abstractions.
Для того чтобы добавить вариант перевода, кликните по иконке ☰, напротив примера.
Возможные однокоренные слова
beautify — украшать, украшаться
beaut — красота, красавица, нечто примечательное, чудесный, выдающийся
Формы слова
noun
ед. ч.(singular): beauty
мн. ч.(plural): beauties
- Top Definitions
- Synonyms
- Quiz
- Related Content
- Examples
- British
- Idioms And Phrases
This shows grade level based on the word’s complexity.
This shows grade level based on the word’s complexity.
noun, plural beau·ties.
the quality present in a thing or person that gives intense pleasure or deep satisfaction to the mind, whether arising from sensory manifestations (as shape, color, sound, etc.), a meaningful design or pattern, or something else (as a personality in which high spiritual qualities are manifest).
a beautiful person, especially a woman.
treatments and products that enhance a person’s physical attractiveness, or the industry associated with this: She left her career in business administration to pursue her passion in beauty and wellness.
a beautiful thing, as a work of art or a building.
Often beauties. a beautiful feature or trait in nature or in some natural or artificial environment: the rugged beauties of our seashore and mountains.
an individually pleasing or beautiful quality; grace; charm: a vivid blue area that is the one real beauty of the painting.
Informal. a particular advantage: One of the beauties of this medicine is the freedom from aftereffects.
(often used ironically) someone or something that is extraordinary, remarkable, or amazing; a beaut: That sunburn is a real beauty!
something excellent of its kind: My old car, now she was a beauty.
adjective
relating to or being something intended to enhance a person’s physical attractiveness: They have a wonderful handcrafted line of natural beauty products, including soaps, lip balm, scented oils, and moisturizer.Make time for yourself and book a relaxing beauty treatment in our first-class spa.
QUIZ
CAN YOU ANSWER THESE COMMON GRAMMAR DEBATES?
There are grammar debates that never die; and the ones highlighted in the questions in this quiz are sure to rile everyone up once again. Do you know how to answer the questions that cause some of the greatest grammar debates?
Which sentence is correct?
Origin of beauty
First recorded in 1225–75; Middle English be(a)ute, from Old French beaute; replacing Middle English bealte, from Old French beltet, from unattested Vulgar Latin bellitāt- (stem of unattested bellitās ), equivalent to Latin bell(us) “fine” + -itāt- noun suffix; see -ity
historical usage of beauty
English beauty comes from Middle English beaute, beaulte, from Anglo-French bealte, ultimately from an unrecorded Vulgar Latin noun bellitās (stem bellitāt-), a derivative of the Latin adjective bellus “pretty, handsome, charming, fine, pleasant, nice,” which is related to Latin bonus “good, virtuous.”
The progression of the various senses is: “(especially of a woman) physical attractiveness, grace, charm” (early 14th century); “(general) moral or intellectual excellence” (late 14th century); “(of a physical object) pleasing to the sight” and “a pleasing or beautiful quality” (both from the 15th century).
The colloquial, sometimes ironic sense, especially in the shortened noun beaut, “someone or something extraordinary, remarkable, or amazing,” was originally an Americanism dating to the first half of the 19th century.
OTHER WORDS FROM beauty
non·beau·ty, noun, plural non·beau·ties.
Words nearby beauty
beautician, beautiful, beautifully, beautiful people, beautify, beauty, “Beauty and the Beast”, beautyberry, beauty-bush, beauty contest, Beauty is only skin deep
Dictionary.com Unabridged
Based on the Random House Unabridged Dictionary, © Random House, Inc. 2023
Words related to beauty
allure, artistry, charm, delicacy, elegance, good looks, grace, refinement, style, vision, feature, importance, value, adorableness, allurement, attraction, comeliness, exquisiteness, fairness, glamor
How to use beauty in a sentence
-
There’s a clear trend away from gendered anything these days—clothes, beauty products, pronouns.
-
On the surface, this seems reasonable — swapping out Black pain for Black beauty.
-
A disappointment became an opportunity to enjoy the natural beauty of a place we could access through general aviation.
-
This modestly upscale dermaplaning wand is designed for people who want the quality of a salon device but are seeking beauty upgrades on a budget.
-
That’s the beauty of why we’ve presented it the way we have.
-
If you read the reactions, she was billed as ‘Beauty and Brains.’
-
Her Miss America win transcended mere superficial beauty standards.
-
Also, she was tall and thin, too, further adding to the ways she met the physical beauty conventions.
-
There was so much beauty, talent, potential, and most importantly, honesty in your work.
-
There was something beautiful about this, and I still see that beauty.
-
A flash of surprise and pleasure lit the fine eyes of the haughty beauty perched up there on the palace wall.
-
Let the thought of self pass in, and the beauty of great action is gone, like the bloom from a soiled flower.
-
The beauty, the mystery,—this fierce sunshine or something—stir——’ She hesitated for a fraction of a second.
-
Thy eye desireth favour and beauty, but more than these green sown fields.
-
Sir Cadge was about the same age as the famous beauty, and rose quite two inches above her lofty head.
British Dictionary definitions for beauty
noun plural -ties
the combination of all the qualities of a person or thing that delight the senses and please the mind
a very attractive and well-formed girl or woman
informal an outstanding example of its kindthe horse is a beauty
informal an advantageous featureone beauty of the job is the short hours
informal, old-fashioned a light-hearted and affectionate term of addresshello, my old beauty!
interjection
(NZ ˈbjuːdɪ) an expression of approval or agreementAlso (Scot, Austral, and NZ): you beauty
Word Origin for beauty
C13: from Old French biauté, from biau beautiful; see beau
Collins English Dictionary — Complete & Unabridged 2012 Digital Edition
© William Collins Sons & Co. Ltd. 1979, 1986 © HarperCollins
Publishers 1998, 2000, 2003, 2005, 2006, 2007, 2009, 2012
Other Idioms and Phrases with beauty
In addition to the idiom beginning with beauty
- beauty is only skin deep
also see:
- that’s the beauty of
The American Heritage® Idioms Dictionary
Copyright © 2002, 2001, 1995 by Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing Company. Published by Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing Company.
Consider what the concept and meaning of the word means beauty (информация предоставлена intellect.icu).
n. (pl. -ies) 1 combination of shape, colour, sound, etc., that pleases the senses. 2 colloq. a excellent specimen (what a beauty!). b attractive feature; advantage (that’s the beauty of it!). 3 beautiful woman. [Latin bellus pretty]
Цифровое произношение
Beauty имеет soundex-B300, metaphone-«», double-metaphone PT.
See also
… The main problems of aesthetics , its ideas are illuminated in. the treatise Oh , the soothing beauty -. Its essence — the teaching of beauty as a spiritual realm . Beauty is considered achievable only … … is a certain intangible essence (eidos ) — an idea that. is in the mind (nus ) and is the generating principle .of perfect beauty Eidos — forming what is the beginning , unites scattered . parts , reducing them to unity , and not mechanical … (Aesthetics)
… to truth as a way to freedom Freedom as a characteristic of a decent life Beauty in a person ‘s life Beauty that helps to love life Beauty of nature The beauty of things and objects The … … The beauty of man The beauty of a human face («portraits of beauty «). The beauty of human movements Beauty as a characteristic of human actions Beauty as a product of human activity … (Theory of education. Organization and methods of educational work)
… man is a.microcosm , I will put a macrocosmaanthropocentric , aja people — a cec microcosm ., a yak macrocosm Beauty in the aesthetics of M Ficino is defined through . the concept of harmony , having its own differentiation … … philosopher expressed this dialectical idea almost in aphoristic form .: Love — the last goal of beauty : beauty craves for love And we have to worry about the beauty of sensual … (Aesthetics)
… contemplating . on him soothes desire Thomas puts forward the idea of .a disinterested experience of beauty , because the fine associated feeling , a. large degree of cognitive , vision and hearing their philosopher … … , while beauty of matter . (physical ) arises as an incidental He also divides the incidental beauty into spiritual (sciences , virtues . as the essence of the beauty of the soul ) and.forest , defining it with reference to Augustine … (Aesthetics)
… the opinion of J Locke , calls feelings Quality Op In the Object of perception ., personifying the beauty of order , harmony , he proposes to consider .the sphere , comprehends inner feelings , and the ability … … and admiration — Stressing the importance . of knowing the objective properties of things and phenomena for.understanding the essence of beauty , And Shaftesbury unfolds understood aesthetic taste . in and true truth — and discovers what his … (Aesthetics)
… the Great pays special attention to the role of. visual images during the perception and experience of beauty , as.well as to the mechanism of influence of the beautiful on. the person The beautiful is comprehended not only in connection … … of. sin , therefore it causes a negative attitude towards oneself On the other hand , beauty in the material world and. in art is highly valued as evidence of manifestations of.absolute divine beauty … (Aesthetics)
beauty — перевод на русский
/ˈbjuːti/
And laugh, like youth and beauty do when life still promises joy and happiness.
» смейс€, пока есть молодость и красота, пока обещает жизнь радость и счастье.
And when it overflows, your beauty will be preserved forever.
И когда она заполнится, твоя красота станет бессмертна.
Famed is thy beauty, Majesty.
Красота твоя несравненна, моя королева!
Oh, there’s beauty. — But it’s not alive.
– Вот это красота.
Beauty and wit and intelligence, and all the things that are so important in a woman.
Красота, вкус, острый ум. Все те качества, которые так важно для всех.
Показать ещё примеры для «красота»…
you’ve got another beauty.
что у Вас еще одна красавица.
A beauty …
Красавица…
Pretend there’s a 5-pound beauty in yonder pool… just behind the jutting boulder.
Представьте, что к вам плывет пятифунтовая красавица пока она вот за тем выступающим валуном.
Stay here, my beauty. You might get hurt outside.
Входи, красавица, там могут подстрелить.
Показать ещё примеры для «красавица»…
— You mean that a woman of your culture and beauty and money and wealth and money would marry that impostor?
— Вы имеете ввиду, что культурная женщина красивая, с деньгами и богатством выйдет замуж за этого самозванца?
A beauty, eh?
Красивая, э?
This here is more than an object of beauty.
Это не просто красивая безделушка…
If hearsay does not lie, you have a ward of surpassing beauty, milord.
Если люди не врут, то у вас живет очень красивая принцесса.
She’s a beauty.
Она красивая.
Показать ещё примеры для «красивая»…
— She’s a true beauty.
Она— настоящая красотка
She used to be a beauty.
Она была красотка.
I had a bathing beauty or something like that right over there.
У меня здесь висела купающаяся красотка, или что-то вроде этого. Ну, я пытался сделать так, что бы здесь всё выглядело… более по-домашнему.
Tan in peace, my beauty.
Загорай спокойно, красотка.
A real beauty!
Настоящая красотка!
Показать ещё примеры для «красотка»…
Isn’t it a beauty?
Разве это не прелесть?
You, my beauty? And in such a state.
Ах вы, моя прелесть, я рад вам помочь.
The chief beauty of this work lies not so much in its style, or in the extent and usefulness of the information it conveys, as in its simple truthfulness.
ƒжером: ќсновна€ прелесть этого творени€ — не столько в его стиле, объеме и пользе от содержащейс€ в нем информации, сколько в его простой правдивости.
his heart, too, was a prey to violent emotion, but neither the tears of the poor girl, nor the wonderful charm of her beauty could produce any impression upon his hardened soul.
сердце его также терзалось, но ни слезы бедной девушки, ни удивительная прелесть её горести не тревожили суровой души его.
The beauty of this deal is the overfunded pension.
Прелесть этой сделки в пенсионных резервах.
Показать ещё примеры для «прелесть»…
Oh, it’s a beauty!
О, прекрасно!
Beauty, Charlie.
Прекрасно, Чарли.
Yeah, ain’t that a beauty?
Да, разве это не прекрасно?
You would have been treated like gods and lived forever in beauty.
К вам бы относились, как к богам и вы бы вечно прекрасно жили.
It was a thing of beauty.
Это было прекрасно.
Показать ещё примеры для «прекрасно»…
— Beauty queen Lemon?
— Мисс Лемон!
Thank you, Beauty queen Lemon.
Спасибо, мисс Лемон.
Beauty queen Lemon dreams with the perfect system of filing, what it will leave backwards all the other systems.
Мисс Лемон мечтает создать свою собственную систему классификации дел которая затмит все ныне существующие.
Beauty queen Lemon, we are going to be out up to tomorrow.
Мисс Лемон, мы с капитаном Гастингсом уезжаем на один день.
— As well as Beauty queen Collins.
И мисс Коллинз.
Показать ещё примеры для «мисс»…
I’m working at a beauty parlor.
Я работаю в салоне красоты
I told you I was working at a beauty parlor.
Я говорила тебе, что я работаю в салоне красоты.
Me, I worked in a beauty parlor.
А я работаю в салоне красоты.
At the beauty salon, Madame.
В салоне красоты, мадам.
At a beauty parlor.
В салоне красоты.
Показать ещё примеры для «в салоне красоты»…
— You ain’t no beauty.
-Да уж, ты не красавец.
I am no beauty.
Я не красавец.
I grant you, I am no beauty… but under this exterior… you’ll find a very flower of man.
Признаю, я не красавец… но под этой оболочкой… скрывается настоящий мужской цветок.
Boy, what a beauty.
Какой красавец!
Isn’t she a beauty?
Ну разве не красавец?
Показать ещё примеры для «красавец»…
Well… my sleeping beauty.
Ну ты моя спящая красавица.
Our «Sleeping Beauty»!
Не парень, а спящая красавица.
SLEEPING BEAUTY
«СПЯЩАЯ КРАСАВИЦА»
Sleeping on and on Like sleeping beauty
Вудете все время спать и не сможете проснуться, как спящая красавица.
And get on your feet, that man, whad’ya think you are… the sleeping bloody beauty!
А ты чего разлегся? Вставай давай, гребаная спящая красавица!
Показать ещё примеры для «спящая красавица»…
Отправить комментарий
Other forms: beauties
Ah, beauty. Anything that has it pleases the senses, like a delicious scent, a perfect piece of pie, or a gorgeous person walking by.
A noun describing an incredibly pleasing or harmonious quality or feature, beauty is hard to describe. Sure, super models and classical paintings exhibit beauty. But so do well designed sports cars and perfectly executed soccer goals. Belle found beauty in the Beast, astrologers find beauty in the stars, and arachnologists find beauty in giant hairy spiders. So that’s why many people say that «beauty is in the eye of the beholder.»
Definitions of beauty
-
noun
the qualities that give pleasure to the senses
see moresee less-
Antonyms:
-
ugliness
qualities of appearance that do not give pleasure to the senses
-
types:
- show 18 types…
- hide 18 types…
-
raw beauty
beauty that is stark and powerfully impressive
-
glory, resplendence, resplendency
brilliant, radiant beauty
-
exquisiteness
extreme beauty of a delicate sort
-
picturesqueness
visually vivid and pleasing
-
pleasingness
an agreeable beauty that gives pleasure or enjoyment
-
pulchritude
physical beauty (especially of a woman)
-
glamor, glamour
alluring beauty or charm (often with sex-appeal)
-
beauteousness, comeliness, fairness, loveliness
the quality of being good looking and attractive
-
cuteness, prettiness
the quality of being appealing in a delicate or graceful way (of a girl or young woman)
-
good looks, handsomeness
the quality of having regular well-defined features (especially of a man)
-
attractiveness
sexual allure
-
adorability, adorableness
extreme attractiveness
-
animal magnetism, beguilement, bewitchery
magnetic personal charm
-
charisma, personal appeal, personal magnetism
a personal attractiveness or interestingness that enables you to influence others
-
curvaceousness, shapeliness, voluptuousness
the quality of having a well-rounded body
-
desirability, desirableness, oomph, sex appeal
attractiveness to the opposite sex
-
appeal, appealingness, charm
attractiveness that interests or pleases or stimulates
-
spiff
attractiveness in appearance or dress or manner
-
type of:
-
appearance, visual aspect
outward or visible aspect of a person or thing
-
ugliness
-
noun
an outstanding example of its kind
“his roses were
beauties”-
synonyms:
beaut
-
noun
a very attractive or seductive looking woman
DISCLAIMER: These example sentences appear in various news sources and books to reflect the usage of the word ‘beauty’.
Views expressed in the examples do not represent the opinion of Vocabulary.com or its editors.
Send us feedback
EDITOR’S CHOICE
Look up beauty for the last time
Close your vocabulary gaps with personalized learning that focuses on teaching the
words you need to know.
Sign up now (it’s free!)
Whether you’re a teacher or a learner, Vocabulary.com can put you or your class on the path to systematic vocabulary improvement.
Get started