What does the word knowledge mean

Coin showing the owl of Athena

Knowledge is a form of awareness or familiarity. It is often understood as awareness of facts or as practical skills, and may also mean familiarity with objects or situations. Knowledge of facts, also called propositional knowledge, is often defined as true belief that is distinct from opinion or guesswork by virtue of justification. While there is wide agreement among philosophers that propositional knowledge is a form of true belief, many controversies in philosophy focus on justification: whether it is needed at all, how to understand it, and whether something else besides it is needed. These controversies intensified due to a series of thought experiments by Edmund Gettier and have provoked various alternative definitions. Some of them deny that justification is necessary and suggest alternative criteria while others accept that justification is an essential aspect and formulate additional requirements.

Knowledge can be produced in many different ways. The most important source of empirical knowledge is perception, which is the usage of the senses. Many theorists also include introspection as a source of knowledge, not of external physical objects, but of one’s own mental states. Other sources often discussed include memory, rational intuition, inference, and testimony. According to foundationalism, some of these sources are basic in the sense that they can justify beliefs without depending on other mental states. This claim is rejected by coherentists, who contend that a sufficient degree of coherence among all the mental states of the believer is necessary for knowledge. According to infinitism, an infinite chain of beliefs is needed.

Many different aspects of knowledge are investigated, and it plays a role in various disciplines. It is the primary subject of the field of epistemology, which studies what someone knows, how they come to know it, and what it means to know something. The problem of the value of knowledge concerns the question of why knowledge is more valuable than mere true belief. Philosophical skepticism is the thesis that humans lack any form of knowledge or that knowledge is impossible. Formal epistemology studies, among other things, the rules governing how knowledge and related states behave and in what relations they stand to each other. Science tries to acquire knowledge using the scientific method, which is based on repeatable experimentation, observation, and measurement. Many religions hold that humans should seek knowledge and that God or the divine is the source of knowledge.

Definitions

Numerous definitions of knowledge have been suggested.[1][2][3] Most definitions of knowledge in analytic philosophy recognize three fundamental types. «Knowledge-that», also called propositional knowledge, can be expressed using that-clauses as in «I know that Dave is at home».[4][5][6] «Knowledge-how» (know-how) expresses practical competence, as in «she knows how to swim». Finally, «knowledge by acquaintance» refers to a familiarity with the known object based on previous direct experience.[5][7][8] Analytical philosophers usually aim to identify the essential features of propositional knowledge in their definitions.[9] There is wide, though not universal, agreement among philosophers that knowledge involves a cognitive success or an epistemic contact with reality, like making a discovery, and that propositional knowledge is a form of true belief.[10][11]

Despite the agreement about these general characteristics of knowledge, many deep disagreements remain regarding its exact definition. These disagreements relate to the goals and methods within epistemology and other fields, or to differences concerning the standards of knowledge that people intend to uphold, for example, what degree of certainty is required. One approach is to focus on knowledge’s most salient features in order to give a practically useful definition.[12][5] Another is to try to provide a theoretically precise definition by listing the conditions that are individually necessary and jointly sufficient. The term «analysis of knowledge» (or equivalently, «conception of knowledge» or «theory of knowledge») is often used for this approach.[1][13][14] It can be understood in analogy to how chemists analyze a sample by seeking a list of all the chemical elements composing it.[1][15][16] An example of this approach is characterizing knowledge as justified true belief (JTB), which is seen by many philosophers as the standard definition.[4][17] Others seek a common core among diverse forms of knowledge, for example, that they all involve some kind of awareness or that they all belong to a special type of successful performance.[11][18][19][20]

Methodological differences concern whether researchers base their inquiry on abstract and general intuitions or on concrete and specific cases, referred to as methodism and particularism, respectively.[21][22][23] Another source of disagreement is the role of ordinary language in one’s inquiry: the weight given to how the term «knowledge» is used in everyday discourse.[6][14] According to Ludwig Wittgenstein, for example, there is no clear-cut definition of knowledge since it is just a cluster of concepts related through family resemblance.[24][25] Different conceptions of the standards of knowledge are also responsible for various disagreements. Some epistemologists, like René Descartes, hold that knowledge demands very high requirements, like certainty, and is therefore quite rare. Others see knowledge as a rather common phenomenon, prevalent in many everyday situations, without excessively high standards.[1][5][26]

In analytic philosophy, knowledge is usually understood as a mental state possessed by an individual person, but the term is sometimes used to refer to a characteristic of a group of people as group knowledge, social knowledge, or collective knowledge.[27][28] In a slightly different sense, it can also mean knowledge stored in documents, as in «knowledge housed in the library»[29][30] or the knowledge base of an expert system.[31][32] The English word knowledge is a broad term. It includes various meanings that some other languages distinguish using several words. For example, Latin uses the words cognitio and scientia for «knowledge» while Spanish uses the words conocer and saber for «to know».[11] In ancient Greek, four important terms for knowledge were used: epistēmē (unchanging theoretical knowledge), technē (expert technical knowledge), mētis (strategic knowledge), and gnōsis (personal intellectual knowledge).[20] Knowledge is often contrasted with ignorance, which is associated with a lack of understanding, education, and true beliefs.[33][34][35] Epistemology, also referred to as the theory of knowledge, is the philosophical discipline studying knowledge. It investigates topics like the nature of knowledge and justification, how knowledge arises, and what value it has. Further issues include the different types of knowledge and the extent to which the beliefs of most people amount to knowledge as well as the limits of what can be known.[36][37][11]

Justified true belief

Venn diagram of justified true belief

Knowledge is often defined as justified true belief.

Many philosophers define knowledge as justified true belief (JTB). This definition characterizes knowledge through three essential features: as (1) a belief that is (2) true and (3) justified.[4][17] In the dialogue Theaetetus by the ancient Greek philosopher Plato, Socrates pondered the distinction between knowledge and true belief but rejected the JTB definition of knowledge.[38][39] The most widely accepted feature is truth: one can believe something false but one cannot know something false.[5][6] A few ordinary language philosophers have raised doubts that knowledge is a form of belief based on everyday expressions like «I do not believe that; I know it».[4][5][40] Most theorists reject this distinction and explain such expressions through ambiguities of natural language.[4][5]

The main controversy surrounding the JTB definition concerns its third feature: justification.[1][4][41] This component is often included because of the impression that some true beliefs are not forms of knowledge. Specifically, this covers cases of superstition, lucky guesses, or erroneous reasoning. The corresponding beliefs may even be true but it seems there is more to knowledge than just being right about something.[4][5][14] The JTB definition solves this problem by identifying proper justification as the additional component needed, which is absent in the above-mentioned cases. Many philosophers have understood justification internalistically (internalism): a belief is justified if it is supported by another mental state of the person, such as a perceptual experience, a memory, or a second belief. This mental state has to constitute a sufficiently strong evidence or reason for the believed proposition. Some modern versions modify the JTB definition by using an externalist conception of justification instead. This means that justification depends not just on factors internal to the subject but also on external factors. According to reliabilist theories of justification, justified beliefs are produced by a reliable process. According to causal theories of justification, justification requires that the believed fact causes the belief. This is the case, for example, when a bird sits on a tree and a person forms a belief about this fact because they see the bird.[1][4][5]

Gettier problem and alternatives

Venn diagram of justified true belief that does not amount to knowledge

The Gettier problem is motivated by the idea that some justified true beliefs do not amount to knowledge.

The JTB definition came under severe criticism in the 20th century, when Edmund Gettier gave a series of counterexamples.[42] They purport to present concrete cases of justified true beliefs that fail to constitute knowledge. The reason for their failure is usually a form of epistemic luck: the justification is not relevant to the truth.[4][5][41] In a well-known example, there is a country road with many barn facades and only one real barn. The person driving is not aware of this, stops in front of the real barn by a lucky coincidence, and forms the belief that he is in front of a barn. It has been argued that this justified true belief does not constitute knowledge since the person would not have been able to tell the difference without the fortuitous accident.[43][44][45] So even though the belief is justified, it is a lucky coincidence that it is also true.[1]

The responses to these counterexamples have been diverse. According to some, they show that the JTB definition of knowledge is deeply flawed and that a radical reconceptualization of knowledge is necessary, often by denying justification a role.[1] This can happen, for example, by replacing justification with reliability or by understanding knowledge as the manifestation of cognitive virtues. Another approach is to define it in regard to the cognitive role it plays. For example, one role of knowledge is to provide reasons for thinking something or for doing something.[11] Various theorists are diametrically opposed to the radical reconceptualization and either deny that Gettier cases pose problems or they try to solve them by making smaller modifications to how justification is defined. Such approaches result in a minimal modification of the JTB definition.[1]

Between these two extremes, some philosophers have suggested various moderate departures. They agree that the JTB definition includes some correct claims: justified true belief is a necessary condition of knowledge. However, they disagree that it is a sufficient condition. They hold instead that an additional criterion, some feature X, is necessary for knowledge. For this reason, they are often referred to as JTB+X definitions of knowledge.[1][46] A closely related approach speaks not of justification but of warrant and defines warrant as justification together with whatever else is necessary to arrive at knowledge.[4][47]

Many candidates for the fourth feature have been suggested. In this regard, knowledge may be defined as justified true belief that does not depend on any false beliefs, that there are no defeaters[a] present, or that the person would not have the belief if it was false.[14][45] Such and similar definitions are successful at avoiding many of the original Gettier cases. However, they are often undermined by newly conceived counterexamples.[49] To avoid all possible cases, it may be necessary to find a criterion that excludes all forms of epistemic luck. It has been argued that such a criterion would set the required standards of knowledge very high: the belief has to be infallible to succeed in all cases.[5][50] This would mean that very few of our beliefs amount to knowledge, if any.[5][51][52] For example, Richard Kirkham suggests that our definition of knowledge requires that the evidence for the belief necessitates its truth.[53] There is still very little consensus in the academic discourse as to which of the proposed modifications or reconceptualizations is correct.[1][54][11]

Types

A common distinction among types of knowledge is between propositional knowledge, or knowledge-that, and non-propositional knowledge in the form of practical skills or acquaintance.[5][55][56] The distinctions between these major types are usually drawn based on the linguistic formulations used to express them.[1]

Propositional knowledge

Propositional knowledge, also referred to as descriptive knowledge, is a form of theoretical knowledge about facts, like knowing that «2 + 2 = 4». It is the paradigmatic type of knowledge in analytic philosophy.[4][5][6] Propositional knowledge is propositional in the sense that it involves a relation to a proposition. Since propositions are often expressed through that-clauses, it is also referred to as knowledge-that, as in «Akari knows that kangaroos hop».[5][6][8] In this case, Akari stands in the relation of knowing to the proposition «kangaroos hop». Closely related types of knowledge are know-wh, for example, knowing who is coming to dinner and knowing why they are coming.[5] These expressions are normally understood as types of propositional knowledge since they usually can be paraphrased using a that-clause.[5][6] It is usually held that the capacity for propositional knowledge is exclusive to relatively sophisticated creatures, such as humans. This is based on the claim that advanced intellectual capacities are required to believe a proposition that expresses what the world is like.[57]

Propositional knowledge is either occurrent or dispositional. Occurrent knowledge is knowledge that is active, for example, because a person is currently thinking about it. Dispositional knowledge, on the other hand, is stored in the back of a person’s mind without being involved in cognitive processes at the moment. In this regard, it refers to the mere ability to access the relevant information. For example, a person may know for most of their life that cats have whiskers. This knowledge is dispositional most of the time. It becomes occurrent when the person actively thinks about the whiskers of cats. A similar classification is often discussed in relation to beliefs as the difference between occurrent and dispositional beliefs.[6][58][59]

Non-propositional knowledge

Photograph of someone riding a bicycle

Knowing how to ride a bicycle is one form of non-propositional knowledge.

Non-propositional knowledge is knowledge in which no essential relation to a proposition is involved. The two most well-known forms are knowledge-how (know-how or procedural knowledge) and knowledge by acquaintance.[5][6][7] The term «know-how» refers to some form of practical ability or skill. It can be defined as having the corresponding competence.[5][57] Examples include knowing how to ride a bicycle or knowing how to swim. Some of the abilities responsible for know-how may also involve certain forms of knowledge-that, as in knowing how to prove a mathematical theorem, but this is not generally the case.[11] Some forms of practical knowledge do not require a highly developed mind, in contrast to propositional knowledge. In this regard, practical knowledge is more common in the animal kingdom. For example, an ant knows how to walk even though it presumably lacks a mind sufficiently developed enough to stand in a relation to the corresponding proposition by representing it.[57] Knowledge-how is closely related to tacit knowledge. Tacit knowledge is knowledge that cannot be fully articulated or explained, in contrast to explicit knowledge.[60][61]

Knowledge by acquaintance is familiarity with an individual that results from direct experiential contact with this individual.[5][6][8] This individual can a person or a regular object. On the linguistic level, it does not require a that-clause and can be expressed using a direct object. So when someone claims that they know Wladimir Klitschko personally, they are expressing that they had a certain kind of contact with him and not that they know a certain fact about him. This is usually understood to mean that it constitutes a relation to a concrete individual and not to a proposition. Knowledge by acquaintance plays a central role in Bertrand Russell’s epistemology. He contrasts it with knowledge by description, which is a form of propositional knowledge not based on direct perceptual experience.[62][63][5] However, there is some controversy about whether it is possible to acquire knowledge by acquaintance in its pure non-propositional form. In this regard, some theorists, like Peter D. Klein, have suggested that it can be understood as one type of propositional knowledge that is only expressed in a grammatically different way.[4]

Other distinctions

A priori and a posteriori

The distinction between a priori and a posteriori knowledge came to prominence in Immanuel Kant’s philosophy and is often discussed in the academic literature. To which category a knowledge attitude belongs depends on the role of experience in its formation and justification.[6][64][65] To know something a posteriori means to know it on the basis of experience.[66][67] For example, to know that it is currently raining or that the baby is crying belongs to a posteriori knowledge since it is based on some form of experience, like visual or auditory experience.[64] A priori knowledge, however, is possible without any experience to justify or support the known proposition.[65][68] Mathematical knowledge, such as that 2 + 2 = 4, is a paradigmatic case of a priori knowledge since no empirical investigation is necessary to confirm this fact.[67][68] The distinction between a posteriori and a priori knowledge is usually equated with the distinction between empirical and non-empirical knowledge.[67] This distinction pertains primarily to knowledge but it can also be applied to propositions or arguments. For example, an a priori proposition is a proposition that can be known independently of experience.[64]

The relevant experience in question is primarily identified with sensory experience. However, some non-sensory experiences, like memory and introspection, are often included as well. But certain conscious phenomena are excluded in this context. For example, the conscious phenomenon of a rational insight into the solution of a mathematical problem does not make the resulting knowledge a posteriori.[64][65] It is sometimes argued that, in a trivial sense, some form of experience is required even for a priori knowledge, the experience needed to learn the language in which the claim is expressed. For a priori knowledge, this is the only form of experience required. For this reason, knowing that «all bachelors are unmarried» is considered a form of a priori knowledge since, given an understanding of the terms «bachelor» and «unmarried», no further experience is necessary to know that it is true.[64][65]

One difficulty for a priori knowledge is to explain how it is possible. It is usually seen as unproblematic that one can come to know things through experience but it is not clear how knowledge is possible without experience. One of the earliest solutions to this problem is due to Plato, who argues that, in the context of geometry, the soul already possesses the knowledge and just needs to recollect or remember it to access it again.[68][69] A similar explanation is given by René Descartes, who holds that a priori knowledge exists as innate knowledge present in the mind of each human.[68] A different approach is to posit a special mental faculty responsible for this type of knowledge, often referred to as rational insight or rational intuition.[64]

Self-knowledge

In philosophy, «self-knowledge» usually refers to a person’s knowledge of their own sensations, thoughts, beliefs, and other mental states. Many philosophers hold that it is a special type of knowledge since it is more direct than knowledge of the external world, which is mediated through the senses. Traditionally, it was often claimed that self-knowledge is indubitable. For example, when someone is in pain, they cannot be wrong about this fact. However, various contemporary theorists reject this position. A closely related issue is to explain how self-knowledge works. Some philosophers, like Russell, understand it as a form of knowledge by acquaintance while others, like John Locke, claim that there is an inner sense that works in analogy to how the external five senses work. According to a different perspective, self-knowledge is indirect in the sense that a person has to interpret their internal and external behavior in order to learn about their mental states, similar to how one can learn about the mental states of other people by interpreting their external behavior.[70][71][72]

In a slightly different sense, the term self-knowledge can also refer to the knowledge of the self as a persisting entity that has certain personality traits, preferences, physical attributes, relationships, goals, and social identities. This meaning is of particular interest to psychology and refers to a person’s awareness of their own characteristics.[73][74][75] Self-knowledge is closely related to self-concept, the difference being that the self-concept also includes unrealistic aspects of how a person sees themselves. In this regard, self-knowledge is often measured by comparing a person’s self-assessment of their character traits with how other people assess this person’s traits.[74]

Situated knowledge

«Situated knowledges» redirects here. For the Donna Haraway essay, see Situated Knowledges.

Situated knowledge is knowledge specific to a particular situation.[76][77] It is closely related to practical or tacit knowledge, which is learned and applied in specific circumstances. This especially concerns certain forms of acquiring knowledge, such as trial and error or learning from experience.[78] In this regard, situated knowledge usually lacks a more explicit structure and is not articulated in terms of universal ideas.[77] The term is often used in feminism and postmodernism to argue that many forms of knowledge are not absolute but depend on the concrete historical, cultural, and linguistic context.[76][77] Understood in this way, it is frequently used to argue against absolute or universal knowledge claims stated in the scientific discourse. Donna Haraway is a prominent defender of this position.[78][79] One of her arguments is based on the idea that perception is embodied and is not a universal «gaze from nowhere».[78]

Higher and lower knowledge

Many forms of eastern spirituality and religion distinguish between higher and lower knowledge. They are also referred to as para vidya and apara vidya in Hinduism or the two truths doctrine in Buddhism. Lower knowledge is based on the senses and the intellect. In this regard, all forms of empirical and objective knowledge belong to this category.[80][81] Most of the knowledge needed in one’s everyday functioning is lower knowledge. It is about mundane or conventional things that are in tune with common sense. It includes the body of knowledge belonging to the empirical sciences.[80][82][83]

Higher knowledge, on the other hand, is understood as knowledge of God, the absolute, the true self, or the ultimate reality. It belongs neither to the external world of physical objects nor to the internal world of the experience of emotions and concepts. Many spiritual teachings emphasize the increased importance, or sometimes even exclusive importance, of higher knowledge in comparison to lower knowledge. This is usually based on the idea that achieving higher knowledge is one of the central steps on the spiritual path. In this regard, higher knowledge is seen as what frees the individual from ignorance, helps them realize God, or liberates them from the cycle of rebirth.[81][82] This is often combined with the view that lower knowledge is in some way based on a delusion: it belongs to the realm of mere appearances or Maya, while higher knowledge manages to view the reality underlying these appearances.[83] In the Buddhist tradition, the attainment of higher knowledge or ultimate truth is often associated with seeing the world from the perspective of sunyata, i.e. as a form of emptiness lacking inherent existence or intrinsic nature.[80][84][85]

Sources of knowledge

Picture of the five senses

Perception using one of the five senses is an important source of knowledge.

Sources of knowledge are ways how people come to know things. According to Andrea Kern, they can be understood as rational capacities that are exercised when a person acquires new knowledge.[86] Various sources of knowledge are discussed in the academic literature, often in terms of the mental faculties responsible. They include perception, introspection, memory, inference, and testimony. However, not everyone agrees that all of them actually lead to knowledge. Usually, perception or observation, i.e. using one of the senses, is identified as the most important source of empirical knowledge.[5][6][87] So knowing that the baby is sleeping constitutes observational knowledge if it was caused by a perception of the snoring baby. But this would not be the case if one learned about this fact through a telephone conversation with one’s spouse. Direct realists explain observational knowledge by holding that perception constitutes a direct contact with the perceived object. Indirect realists, on the other hand, contend that this contact happens indirectly: people can only directly perceive sense data, which are then interpreted as representing external objects. This distinction affects whether the knowledge of external objects is direct or indirect and may thus have an impact on how certain perceptual knowledge is.[11]

Introspection is often seen in analogy to perception as a source of knowledge, not of external physical objects, but of internal mental states. Traditionally, various theorists have ascribed a special epistemic status to introspection by claiming that it is infallible or that there is no introspective difference between appearance and reality. However, this claim has been contested in the contemporary discourse. Critics argue that it may be possible, for example, to mistake an unpleasant itch for a pain or to confuse the experience of a slight ellipse for the experience of a circle.[11] Perceptual and introspective knowledge often act as a form of fundamental or basic knowledge. According to some empiricists, perceptual knowledge is the only source of basic knowledge and provides the foundation for all other knowledge.[5][6]

Memory is usually identified as another source of knowledge. It differs from perception and introspection in that it is not as independent or fundamental as they are since it depends on other previous experiences.[11][88] The faculty of memory retains knowledge acquired in the past and makes it accessible in the present, as when remembering a past event or a friend’s phone number.[89][90] It is generally considered a reliable source of knowledge, but it can be deceptive at times nonetheless, either because the original experience was unreliable or because the memory degraded and does not accurately represent the original experience anymore.[11]

Knowledge based on perception, introspection, or memory may also give rise to inferential knowledge, which comes about when reasoning is applied to draw inferences from another known fact.[5][6][11] In this regard, the perceptual knowledge of a Czech stamp on a postcard may give rise to the inferential knowledge that one’s friend is visiting the Czech Republic. According to rationalists, some forms of knowledge are completely independent of observation and introspection. They are needed to explain how certain a priori beliefs, like the mathematical belief that 2 + 2 = 4, constitute knowledge. Some theorists, like Robert Audi, hold that the faculty of pure reason or rational intuition is responsible in these cases since there seem to be no sensory perceptions that could justify such general and abstract knowledge.[88][91] However, difficulties in providing a clear account of pure reason or rational intuition have led various empirically minded epistemologists to doubt that they constitute independent sources of knowledge.[5][6][11] A closely related approach is to hold that this type of knowledge is innate. According to Plato’s theory of recollection, for example, it is accessed through a special form of remembering.[5][6]

Photograph of a person giving testimony at a trial

Testimony is an important source of knowledge for many everyday purposes. The testimony given at a trial is one special case.

Testimony is often included as an additional source of knowledge. Unlike the other sources, it is not tied to one specific cognitive faculty. Instead, it is based on the idea that one person can come to know a fact because another person talks about this fact. Testimony can happen in numerous ways, like regular speech, a letter, the newspaper, or an online blog. The problem of testimony consists in clarifying under what circumstances and why it constitutes a source of knowledge. A popular response is that it depends on the reliability of the person pronouncing the testimony: only testimony from reliable sources can lead to knowledge.[11][92][93]

Structure of knowledge

The structure of knowledge is the way in which the mental states of a person need to be related to each other for knowledge to arise.[94][95] Most theorists hold that, among other things, an agent has to have good reasons for holding a belief if this belief is to amount to knowledge. So when challenged, the agent may justify their belief by referring to their reason for holding it. In many cases, this reason is itself a belief that may as well be challenged. So when the agent believes that Ford cars are cheaper than BMWs because they believe to have heard this from a reliable source, they may be challenged to justify why they believe that their source is reliable. Whatever support they present may also be challenged.[4][11][14] This threatens to lead to an infinite regress since the epistemic status at each step depends on the epistemic status of the previous step.[96][97] Theories of the structure of knowledge offer responses for how to solve this problem.[4][11][14]

Diagram showing the differences between foundationalism, coherentism, and infinitism

Foundationalism, coherentism, and infinitism are theories of the structure of knowledge. The black arrows symbolize how one belief supports another belief.

The three most common theories are foundationalism, coherentism, and infinitism. Foundationalists and coherentists deny the existence of this infinite regress, in contrast to infinitists.[4][11][14] According to foundationalists, some basic reasons have their epistemic status independent of other reasons and thereby constitute the endpoint of the regress. Against this view, it has been argued that the concept of «basic reason» is contradictory: there should be a reason for why some reasons are basic and others are non-basic, in which case the basic reasons would depend on another reason after all and would therefore not be basic. An additional problem consists in finding plausible candidates for basic reasons.[4][11][14]

Coherentists and infinitists avoid these problems by denying the distinction between basic and non-basic reasons. Coherentists argue that there is only a finite number of reasons, which mutually support each other and thereby ensure each other’s epistemic status.[4][11] Their critics contend that this constitutes the fallacy of circular reasoning.[98][99] For example, if belief b1 supports belief b2 and belief b2 supports belief b1, the agent has a reason for accepting one belief if they already have the other. However, their mutual support alone is not a good reason for newly accepting both beliefs at once. A closely related issue is that there can be various distinct sets of coherent beliefs and coherentists face the problem of explaining why someone should accept one coherent set rather than another.[4][11] For infinitists, in contrast to foundationalists and coherentists, there is an infinite number of reasons. This position faces the problem of explaining how human knowledge is possible at all, as it seems that the human mind is limited and cannot possess an infinite number of reasons.[4] In their traditional forms, both foundationalists and coherentists face the Gettier problem, i.e. that having a reason or justification for a true belief is not sufficient for knowledge in cases where cognitive luck is responsible for the success.[4][100]

Value of knowledge

Sculpture showing a torch being passed form one person to another

Knowledge may be valuable either because it is useful or because it is good in itself. Knowledge can be useful by helping a person achieve their goals. An example of this form of instrumental value is knowledge of a disease, which can be beneficial because it enables a person to identify and treat the disease. Or to reach an important job interview, knowledge of where and when it takes place helps the person arrive there on time.[101][102][103] However, this does not imply that knowledge is always useful. In this regard, many true beliefs about trivial matters have neither positive nor negative value. This concerns, for example, knowing how many grains of sand are on a specific beach or memorizing phone numbers one never intends to call. In a few cases, knowledge may even have a negative value. For example, if a person’s life depends on gathering the courage to jump over a ravine, then having a true belief about the involved dangers may hinder the person to do so.[102]

Besides having instrumental value, knowledge may also have intrinsic value. This means that certain forms of knowledge are good in themselves even if they do not provide any practical benefits. According to Duncan Pritchard, this applies to certain forms of knowledge associated with wisdom.[102][101] The value of knowledge is relevant to the field of education, specifically to the issue of choosing which knowledge should be passed on to the student.[101]

A more specific issue in epistemology concerns the question of whether or why knowledge is more valuable than mere true belief.[104][103] There is wide agreement that knowledge is good in some sense but the thesis that knowledge is better than true belief is controversial. An early discussion of this problem is found in Plato’s Meno in relation to the claim that both knowledge and true belief can successfully guide action and, therefore, have apparently the same value. For example, it seems that mere true belief is as effective as knowledge when trying to find the way to Larissa.[103][104][105] According to Plato, knowledge is better because it is more stable.[103] A different approach is to hold that knowledge gets its additional value from justification. However, if the value in question is understood primarily as an instrumental value, it is not clear in what sense knowledge is better than mere true belief since they are usually equally useful.[104]

The problem of the value of knowledge is often discussed in relation to reliabilism and virtue epistemology.[104][103][106] Reliabilism can be defined as the thesis that knowledge is reliably-formed true belief. On this view, it is difficult to explain how a reliable belief-forming process adds additional value.[104] According to an analogy by Linda Zagzebski, a cup of coffee made by a reliable coffee machine has the same value as an equally good cup of coffee made by an unreliable coffee machine.[107] This difficulty in solving the value problem is sometimes used as an argument against reliabilism. Virtue epistemologists see knowledge as the manifestation of cognitive virtues and can thus argue that knowledge has additional value due to its association with virtue. However, not everyone agrees that knowledge actually has additional value over true belief. A similar view is defended by Jonathan Kvanvig, who argues that the main epistemic value resides not in knowledge but in understanding, which implies grasping how one’s beliefs cohere with each other.[104][103][108]

Philosophical skepticism

Bust of Pyrrho of Elis

Philosophical skepticism in its strongest form, also referred to as global skepticism, is the thesis that humans lack any form of knowledge or that knowledge is impossible. Very few philosophers have explicitly defended this position. However, it has been influential nonetheless, usually in a negative sense: many researchers see it as a serious challenge to any epistemological theory and often try to show how their preferred theory overcomes it.[4][5][11] For example, it is commonly accepted that perceptual experience constitutes a source of knowledge. However, according to the dream argument, this is not the case since dreaming provides unreliable information and since the agent could be dreaming without knowing it. Because of this inability to discriminate between dream and perception, it is argued that there is no perceptual knowledge.[4][5][6] A similar often cited thought experiment assumes that the agent is actually a brain in a vat that is just fed electrical stimuli. Such a brain would have the false impression of having a body and interacting with the external world. The basic argument is the same: since the agent is unable to tell the difference, they do not know that they have a body responsible for reliable perceptions.[11]

One issue revealed through these thought experiments is the problem of underdetermination: that the evidence available is not sufficient to make a rational decision between competing theories. And if two contrary hypotheses explain the appearances equally well, then the agent is not justified in believing one of those hypotheses rather than the other. Based on this premise, the general skeptic has to argue that this is true for all our knowledge, that there is always an alternative and very different explanation.[11] Another skeptic argument is based on the idea that human cognition is fallible and therefore lacks absolute certainty. More specific arguments target particular theories of knowledge, such as foundationalism or coherentism, and try to show that their concept of knowledge is deeply flawed.[4][11] An important argument against global skepticism is that it seems to contradict itself: the claim that there is no knowledge appears to constitute a knowledge-claim itself.[6] Other responses come from common sense philosophy and reject global skepticism based on the fact that it contradicts many plausible ordinary beliefs. It is then argued against skepticism by seeing common sense as more reliable than the abstract reasoning cited in favor of skepticism.[11][109]

Certain less radical forms of skepticism deny that knowledge exists within a specific area or discipline, sometimes referred to as local or selective skepticism.[5][6][11] It is often motivated by the idea that certain phenomena do not accurately represent their subject matter. They may thus lead to false impressions concerning its nature. External world skeptics hold that one can only know about one’s own sensory impressions and experiences but not about the external world. This is based on the idea that beliefs about the external world are mediated through the senses. The senses are faulty at times and may thus show things that are not really there. This problem is avoided on the level of sensory impressions, which are given to the experiencer directly without an intermediary. In this sense, the person may be wrong about seeing a red Ferrari in the street (it might have been a Maserati or a mere light reflection) but they cannot be wrong about having a sensory impression of the color red.[5][6][11]

The inverse path is taken by some materialists, who accept the existence of the external physical world but deny the existence of the internal realm of mind and consciousness based on the difficulty of explaining how the two realms can exist together.[14] Other forms of local skepticism accept scientific knowledge but deny the possibility of moral knowledge, for example, because there is no reliable way to empirically measure whether a moral claim is true or false.[5]

The issue of the definition and standards of knowledge is central to the question of whether skepticism in its different forms is true. If very high standards are used, for example, that knowledge implies infallibility, then skepticism becomes more plausible. In this case, the skeptic only has to show that no belief is absolutely certain; that while the actual belief is true, it could have been false. However, the more these standards are weakened to how the term is used in everyday language, the less plausible skepticism becomes.[6][110][11] For example, such a position is defended in the pragmatist epistemology, which sees all beliefs and theories as fallible hypotheses and holds that they may need to be revised as new evidence is acquired.[111][112][113]

In various disciplines

Formal epistemology

Formal epistemology studies knowledge using formal tools, such as mathematics and logic.[114] An important issue in this field concerns the epistemic principles of knowledge. These are rules governing how knowledge and related states behave and in what relations they stand to each other. The transparency principle, also referred to as the luminosity of knowledge, is an often discussed principle. It states that knowing something implies the second-order knowledge that one knows it. This principle implies that if Heike knows that today is Monday, then she also knows that she knows that today is Monday.[11][115][116] Other commonly discussed principles are the conjunction principle, the closure principle, and the evidence transfer principle. For example, the conjunction principle states that having two justified beliefs in two separate propositions implies that the agent is also justified in believing the conjunction of these two propositions. In this regard, if Bob knows that dogs are animals and he also knows that cats are animals, then he knows the conjunction of these two propositions, i.e. he knows that dogs and cats are animals.[4]

Science

The scientific approach is usually regarded as an exemplary process for how to gain knowledge about empirical facts.[117][118] Scientific knowledge includes mundane knowledge about easily observable facts, for example, chemical knowledge that certain reactants become hot when mixed together. But it also encompasses knowledge of less tangible issues, like claims about the behavior of genes, neutrinos, and black holes.[119]

A key aspect of most forms of science is that they seek natural laws that explain empirical observations.[117][118] Scientific knowledge is discovered and tested using the scientific method. This method aims to arrive at reliable knowledge by formulating the problem in a clear manner and by ensuring that the evidence used to support or refute a specific theory is public, reliable, and replicable. This way, other researchers can repeat the experiments and observations in the initial study to confirm or disconfirm it.[120] The scientific method is often analyzed as a series of steps. According to some formulations, it begins with regular observation and data collection. Based on these insights, the scientists then try to find a hypothesis that explains the observations. The hypothesis is then tested using a controlled experiment to compare whether predictions based on the hypothesis match the actual results. As a last step, the results are interpreted and a conclusion is reached whether and to what degree the findings confirm or disconfirm the hypothesis.[121][122][123]

The progress of scientific knowledge is traditionally seen as a gradual and continuous process in which the existing body of knowledge is increased in each step. However, this view has been challenged by various philosophers of science, such as Thomas Kuhn, who holds that between phases of incremental progress, there are so-called scientific revolutions in which a paradigm shift occurs. According to this view, various fundamental assumptions are changed due to the paradigm shift, resulting in a radically new perspective on the body of scientific knowledge that is incommensurable with the previous outlook.[124][125]

Religion

Knowledge plays a central role in many religions. Knowledge claims about the existence of God or religious doctrines about how each one should live their lives are found in almost every culture.[126] However, such knowledge claims are often controversial and are commonly rejected by religious skeptics and atheists.[127] The epistemology of religion is the field of inquiry that investigates whether belief in God and in other religious doctrines is rational and amounts to knowledge.[126][128] One important view in this field is evidentialism. It states that belief in religious doctrines is justified if it is supported by sufficient evidence. Suggested examples of evidence for religious doctrines include religious experiences such as direct contact with the divine or inner testimony as when hearing God’s voice.[126][128][129] However, evidentialists often reject that belief in religious doctrines amount to knowledge based on the claim that there is not sufficient evidence.[126][128] A famous saying in this regard is due to Bertrand Russell. When asked how he would justify his lack of belief in God when facing his judgment after death, he replied «Not enough evidence, God! Not enough evidence.»[126]

However, religious teachings about the existence and nature of God are not always understood as knowledge claims by their defenders and some explicitly state that the proper attitude towards such doctrines is not knowledge but faith. This is often combined with the assumption that these doctrines are true but cannot be fully understood by reason or verified through rational inquiry. For this reason, it is claimed that one should accept them even though they do not amount to knowledge.[127] Such a view is reflected in a famous saying by Immanuel Kant where he claims that he «had to deny knowledge in order to make room for faith.»[130]

Distinct religions often differ from each other concerning the doctrines they proclaim as well as their understanding of the role of knowledge in religious practice.[131][132] In both the Jewish and the Christian tradition, knowledge plays a role in the fall of man in which Adam and Eve were expelled from the Garden of Eden. Responsible for this fall was that they ignored God’s command and ate from the tree of knowledge, which gave them the knowledge of good and evil. This is understood as a rebellion against God since this knowledge belongs to God and it is not for humans to decide what is right or wrong.[133][134][135] In the Christian literature, knowledge is seen as one of the seven gifts of the Holy Spirit.[136] In Islam, «the Knowing» (al-ʿAlīm) is one of the 99 names reflecting distinct attributes of God. The Qur’an asserts that knowledge comes from God and the acquisition of knowledge is encouraged in the teachings of Muhammad.[137][138]

Oil painting showing Saraswati

Saraswati is the goddess of knowledge and the arts in Hinduism.

In Buddhism, knowledge that leads to liberation is called vijjā. It contrasts with avijjā or ignorance, which is understood as the root of all suffering. This is often explained in relation to the claim that humans suffer because they crave things that are impermanent. The ignorance of the impermanent nature of things is seen as the factor responsible for this craving.[139][140][141] The central goal of Buddhist practice is to stop suffering. This aim is to be achieved by understanding and practicing the teaching known as the Four Noble Truths and thereby overcoming ignorance.[140][141] Knowledge plays a key role in the classical path of Hinduism known as jñāna yoga or «path of knowledge». Its aim is to achieve oneness with the divine by fostering an understanding of the self and its relation to Brahman or ultimate reality.[142][143]

Anthropology

The anthropology of knowledge is a multi-disciplinary field of inquiry.[144][145] It studies how knowledge is acquired, stored, retrieved, and communicated.[146] Special interest is given to how knowledge is reproduced and undergoes changes in relation to social and cultural circumstances.[144] In this context, the term knowledge is used in a very broad sense, roughly equivalent to terms like understanding and culture.[144][147] This means that the forms and reproduction of understanding are studied irrespective of their truth value. In epistemology, on the other hand, knowledge is usually restricted to forms of true belief. The main focus in anthropology is on empirical observations of how people ascribe truth values to meaning contents, like when affirming an assertion, even if these contents are false.[144] But it also includes practical components: knowledge is what is employed when interpreting and acting on the world and involves diverse phenomena, such as feelings, embodied skills, information, and concepts. It is used to understand and anticipate events in order to prepare and react accordingly.[147]

The reproduction of knowledge and its changes often happen through some form of communication.[144][146] This includes face-to-face discussions and online communications as well as seminars and rituals. An important role in this context falls to institutions, like university departments or scientific journals in the academic context.[144] A tradition or traditional knowledge may be defined as knowledge that has been reproduced within a society or geographic region over several generations. However, societies also respond to various external influences, such as other societies, whose understanding is often interpreted and incorporated in a modified form.[144][147][148]

Individuals belonging to the same social group usually understand things and organize knowledge in similar ways to one another. In this regard, social identities play a significant role: individuals who associate themselves with similar identities, like age-influenced, professional, religious, and ethnic identities, tend to embody similar forms of knowledge. Such identities concern both how an individual sees themselves, for example, in terms of the ideals they pursue, as well as how other people see them, such as the expectations they have toward the individual.[144][149]

Sociology

The sociology of knowledge is closely related to the anthropology of knowledge.[150][147][151] It is the subfield of sociology that investigates how thought and society are related to each other. In it, the term «knowledge» is understood in a very wide sense that encompasses many types of mental products. It includes philosophical and political ideas as well as religious and ideological doctrines and can also be applied to folklore, law, and technology. In this regard, knowledge is sometimes treated as a synonym for culture. The sociology of knowledge studies in what sociohistorical circumstances knowledge arises and on what existential conditions it depends. The investigated conditions can include physical, demographic, economic, and sociocultural factors. The sociology of knowledge differs from most forms of epistemology since its main focus is on the question of how ideas originate and what consequences they have rather than asking whether these ideas are coherent or correct. An example of a theory in this field is due to Karl Marx, who claims that the dominant ideology in a society is a product of and changes with the underlying socioeconomic conditions.[152][153][154] A related perspective is found in certain forms of decolonial scholarship that claim that colonial powers are responsible for the hegemony of western knowledge systems and seek a decolonization of knowledge to undermine this hegemony.[155][156]

See also

  • Common knowledge
  • Domain knowledge
  • Epistemic modal logic
  • General knowledge
  • Inductive inference
  • Inductive probability
  • Intelligence
  • Knowledge falsification
  • Knowledge transfer
  • Metaknowledge
  • Omniscience
  • Outline of human intelligence
  • Outline of knowledge

References

Notes

  1. ^ A defeater of a belief is evidence that this belief is false.[48]

Citations

  1. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l Ichikawa, Jonathan Jenkins; Steup, Matthias (2018). «The Analysis of Knowledge». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 2 May 2022. Retrieved 24 May 2022.
  2. ^ Bolisani, Ettore; Bratianu, Constantin (2018). «The Elusive Definition of Knowledge». Emergent Knowledge Strategies: Strategic Thinking in Knowledge Management. Springer International Publishing. pp. 1–22. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-60657-6_1. ISBN 978-3-319-60657-6. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  3. ^ «knowledge». Oxford dictionary (American English). Archived from the original on 14 July 2010.
  4. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x Klein, Peter D. (1998). «Knowledge, concept of». In Craig, Edward (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London; New York: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-P031-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. OCLC 38096851. Archived from the original on 13 June 2022. Retrieved 13 June 2022.
  5. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z aa ab ac ad ae Hetherington, Stephen. «Knowledge». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 18 May 2022.
  6. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t Stroll, Avrum. «epistemology». www.britannica.com. Archived from the original on 10 July 2019. Retrieved 20 May 2022.
  7. ^ a b Stanley, Jason; Willlamson, Timothy (2001). «Knowing How». Journal of Philosophy. 98 (8): 411–444. doi:10.2307/2678403. JSTOR 2678403. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  8. ^ a b c Zagzebski 1999, p. 92.
  9. ^ Zagzebski 1999, p. 92, 96-7.
  10. ^ Zagzebski 1999, p. 109.
  11. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z aa ab ac Steup, Matthias; Neta, Ram (2020). «Epistemology». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 21 July 2020. Retrieved 22 May 2022.
  12. ^ Zagzebski 1999, p. 99.
  13. ^ Hannon, Michael (2021). «Knowledge, concept of». Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London; New York: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-P031-2. ISBN 978-0-415-07310-3. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  14. ^ a b c d e f g h i Lehrer, Keith (15 October 2015). «1. The Analysis of Knowledge». Theory of Knowledge. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-19609-7. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  15. ^ Zagzebski 1999, p. 96.
  16. ^ Gupta, Anil (2021). «Definitions: 1.1 Real and nominal definitions». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 1 May 2022. Retrieved 28 May 2022.
  17. ^ a b Zagzebski 1999, p. 99–100.
  18. ^ Silva, Paul Jr. (September 2019). «Beliefless knowing». Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. 100 (3): 723–746. doi:10.1111/papq.12273. S2CID 240808741.
  19. ^ Crumley, Jack S. (2016). «What do you know? Look at the artifacts». Introducing Philosophy: Knowledge and Reality. Peterborough, Ontario, Canada: Broadview Press. pp. 51–52. ISBN 978-1-55481-129-8. OCLC 950057343. Archived from the original on 13 June 2022. Retrieved 13 June 2022.
  20. ^ a b Allen, Barry (2005). «Knowledge». In Horowitz, Maryanne Cline (ed.). New Dictionary of the History of Ideas. Vol. 3. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons. pp. 1199–1204. ISBN 978-0-684-31377-1. OCLC 55800981. Archived from the original on 22 August 2017.
  21. ^ Pritchard, Duncan (1 October 2013). «3 Defining knowledge». What is this thing called Knowledge?. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-57367-7. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  22. ^ McCain, Kevin. «Problem of the Criterion». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 28 May 2022.
  23. ^ Fumerton, Richard (25 September 2008). «The Problem of the Criterion». The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism. pp. 34–52. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195183214.003.0003. ISBN 978-0-19-518321-4. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  24. ^ García-Arnaldos, María Dolores (23 October 2020). «An Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge, written by O’Brien, D.» History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis. 23 (2): 508. doi:10.30965/26664275-20210003. ISSN 2666-4275. S2CID 228985437.
  25. ^ O’Brien, Dan (16 December 2016). «Part I Chapter 7: Family resemblance». An Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-5095-1240-9.
  26. ^ Black, Tim (1 April 2002). «Relevant alternatives and the shifting standards of knowledge». Southwest Philosophy Review. 18 (1): 23–32. doi:10.5840/swphilreview20021813. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  27. ^ Klausen, Søren Harnow (March 2015). «Group knowledge: a real-world approach». Synthese. 192 (3): 813–839. doi:10.1007/s11229-014-0589-9. S2CID 207246817.
  28. ^ Lackey, Jennifer (February 2021). The Epistemology of Groups. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-965660-8.
  29. ^ «knowledge». The American Heritage Dictionary. HarperCollins. Retrieved 25 October 2022.
  30. ^ Magee, Bryan; Popper, Karl R. (1971). «Conversation with Karl Popper». In Magee, Bryan (ed.). Modern British philosophy. New York: St. Martin’s Press. pp. 74–75. ISBN 978-0-19-283047-0. OCLC 314039. Popper: Putting our ideas into words, or better, writing them down, makes an important difference. … It is what I call ‘knowledge in the objective sense’. Scientific knowledge belongs to it. It is this knowledge which is stored in our libraries rather than our heads. Magee: And you regard the knowledge stored in our libraries as more important than the knowledge stored in our heads. Popper: Much more important, from every point of view
  31. ^ «knowledge base». The American Heritage Dictionary. HarperCollins. Retrieved 25 October 2022.
  32. ^ Walton, Douglas N. (January 2005). «Pragmatic and idealized models of knowledge and ignorance». American Philosophical Quarterly. 42 (1): 59–69 (59, 64). JSTOR 20010182. It is a pervasive assumption in recent analytical philosophy that knowledge can be defined as a modality representing a rational agent’s true and consistent beliefs. Such views are based on rationality assumptions. One is that knowledge can only consist of true propositions. This way of speaking is sharply at odds with the way we speak about knowledge, for example, in computing, where a so-called knowledge base can be a database, that is, a set of data that has been collected and is thought to consist of true propositions, even though, realistically speaking, many of them might later be shown to be false or untenable. … The pragmatic account of knowledge starts with a knowledge system, meaning a working system with an agent having a database. … The notion of a search can be a social one, in many instances. A group of agents can be engaged in the search, and some of them can know things that others do not know.
  33. ^ Crotty, Kevin (8 November 2022). Ignorance, Irony, and Knowledge in Plato. Rowman & Littlefield. p. 16. ISBN 978-1-6669-2712-2.
  34. ^ Peels, Rik; Blaauw, Martijn (22 December 2016). The Epistemic Dimensions of Ignorance. Cambridge University Press. p. 25. ISBN 978-1-107-17560-0.
  35. ^ Publishers, HarperCollins. «The American Heritage Dictionary entry: ignorance». www.ahdictionary.com. Retrieved 7 March 2023.
  36. ^ Truncellito, David A. «Epistemology». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 8 March 2023.
  37. ^ Moser, Paul K. (27 October 2005). The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology. Oxford University Press. p. 3. ISBN 978-0-19-020818-9.
  38. ^ Parikh, Rohit; Renero, Adriana (2017). «Justified True Belief: Plato, Gettier, and Turing». Philosophical Explorations of the Legacy of Alan Turing: Turing 100. Springer International Publishing. pp. 93–102. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-53280-6_4. ISBN 978-3-319-53280-6. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  39. ^ Chappell, Sophie-Grace (2019). «Plato on Knowledge in the Theaetetus«. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 10 July 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  40. ^ Zagzebski 1999, p. 93.
  41. ^ a b Zagzebski 1999, p. 100.
  42. ^ Hetherington, Stephen. «Gettier Problems». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 19 February 2009. Retrieved 28 May 2022.
  43. ^ Rodríguez, Ángel García (2018). «Fake barns and our epistemological theorizing». Crítica: Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía. 50 (148): 29–54. doi:10.22201/iifs.18704905e.2018.02. ISSN 0011-1503. JSTOR 26767766. S2CID 171635198.
  44. ^ Goldman, Alvin I. (18 November 1976). «Discrimination and Perceptual Knowledge». The Journal of Philosophy. 73 (20): 771–791. doi:10.2307/2025679. JSTOR 2025679.
  45. ^ a b Sudduth, Michael. «Defeaters in Epistemology: 2b Defeasibility Analyses and Propositional Defeaters». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 17 May 2022.
  46. ^ Durán, Juan M.; Formanek, Nico (1 December 2018). «Grounds for Trust: Essential Epistemic Opacity and Computational Reliabilism». Minds and Machines. 28 (4): 645–666. doi:10.1007/s11023-018-9481-6. ISSN 1572-8641. S2CID 53102940.
  47. ^ Comesaña, Juan (2005). «Justified vs. Warranted Perceptual Belief: Resisting Disjunctivism». Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 71 (2): 367–383. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2005.tb00453.x. ISSN 0031-8205. JSTOR 40040862. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  48. ^ McCain, Kevin; Stapleford, Scott; Steup, Matthias (21 October 2021). Epistemic Dilemmas: New Arguments, New Angles. Routledge. p. 111. ISBN 978-1-000-46851-9.
  49. ^ Zagzebski 1999, p. 101.
  50. ^ Kraft, Tim (2012). «Scepticism, Infallibilism, Fallibilism». Discipline Filosofiche. 22 (2): 49–70. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  51. ^ Zagzebski 1999, p. 103–4.
  52. ^ Sidelle, Alan (2001). «An Argument That Internalism Requires Infallibility». Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 63 (1): 163–179. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2001.tb00096.x. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  53. ^ Kirkham, Richard L. (October 1984). «Does the Gettier Problem Rest on a Mistake?». Mind. New Series. 93 (372): 501–513. doi:10.1093/mind/XCIII.372.501. JSTOR 2254258.
  54. ^ Zagzebski 1999, p. 93–4, 104–5.
  55. ^ Ronald, Barnett (1 May 1990). The Idea Of Higher Education. McGraw-Hill Education (UK). p. 40. ISBN 978-0-335-09420-2.
  56. ^ Lilley, Simon; Lightfoot, Geoffrey; Amaral, Paulo (2004). Representing Organization: Knowledge, Management, and the Information Age. Oxford University Press. pp. 162–3. ISBN 978-0-19-877541-6.
  57. ^ a b c Pritchard, Duncan (1 October 2013). «1 Some preliminaries». What is this thing called Knowledge?. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-57367-7. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  58. ^ Bartlett, Gary (2018). «Occurrent States». Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 48 (1): 1–17. doi:10.1080/00455091.2017.1323531. S2CID 220316213. Archived from the original on 4 May 2021. Retrieved 3 April 2021.
  59. ^ Schwitzgebel, Eric (2021). «Belief: 2.1 Occurrent Versus Dispositional Belief». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 15 November 2019. Retrieved 8 June 2022.
  60. ^ Gascoigne, Neil; Thornton, Tim (3 September 2014). Tacit Knowledge. Routledge. p. 8, 37, 81, 108. ISBN 978-1-317-54726-6.
  61. ^ Hill, Sonya D., ed. (2009). «Knowledge–Based View Of The Firm». Encyclopedia of Management. Gale. ISBN 978-1-4144-0691-6.
  62. ^ Hasan, Ali; Fumerton, Richard (2020). «Knowledge by Acquaintance vs. Description: 1. The Distinction». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 31 May 2022. Retrieved 28 May 2022.
  63. ^ DePoe, John M. «Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 28 May 2022.
  64. ^ a b c d e f Baehr, Jason S. «A Priori and A Posteriori». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 September 2022.
  65. ^ a b c d Russell, Bruce (2020). «A Priori Justification and Knowledge». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 September 2022.
  66. ^ «a posteriori knowledge». www.britannica.com. Retrieved 17 September 2022.
  67. ^ a b c Moser, Paul K. «A posteriori». Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. Retrieved 18 September 2022.
  68. ^ a b c d «a priori knowledge». www.britannica.com. Retrieved 17 September 2022.
  69. ^ Woolf, Raphael (1 January 2013). «Plato and the Norms of Thought». Mind. 122 (485): 171–216. doi:10.1093/mind/fzt012. ISSN 0026-4423.
  70. ^ Gertler, Brie (2021). «Self-Knowledge». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 October 2022.
  71. ^ Gertler, Brie (25 November 2010). «1. Introduction». Self-Knowledge. Routledge. p. 1. ISBN 978-1-136-85811-6.
  72. ^ McGeer, V. (2001). «Self-knowledge: Philosophical Aspects». International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences: 13837–13841. doi:10.1016/B0-08-043076-7/01073-1. ISBN 978-0-08-043076-8.
  73. ^ Gertler, Brie. «Self-Knowledge > Knowledge of the Self». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 22 October 2022.
  74. ^ a b Morin, Alain; Racy, Famira (1 January 2021). «15. Dynamic self-processes — Self-knowledge». The Handbook of Personality Dynamics and Processes. Academic Press. pp. 373–4. ISBN 978-0-12-813995-0.
  75. ^ Kernis, Michael H. (15 April 2013). Self-Esteem Issues and Answers: A Sourcebook of Current Perspectives. Psychology Press. p. 209. ISBN 978-1-134-95270-0.
  76. ^ a b «situated knowledge». APA Dictionary of Psychology. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. n.d. Retrieved 18 September 2022.
  77. ^ a b c Hunter, Lynette (2009). «Situated Knowledge». Mapping Landscapes for Performance as Research: Scholarly Acts and Creative Cartographies. Palgrave Macmillan UK. pp. 151–153. doi:10.1057/9780230244481_23. ISBN 978-0-230-24448-1.
  78. ^ a b c Haraway, Donna (1988). «Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective». Feminist Studies. 14 (3): 575–599. doi:10.2307/3178066. JSTOR 3178066. S2CID 39794636.
  79. ^ Thompson, C. M. (1 January 2001). «Situated Knowledge: Feminist and Science and Technology Studies Perspectives». International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences. Pergamon. pp. 14129–14133. ISBN 978-0-08-043076-8.
  80. ^ a b c Thakchoe, Sonam (2022). «The Theory of Two Truths in India». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 16 May 2022. Retrieved 6 June 2022.
  81. ^ a b «Para and Apara Vidya». The Hindu. 18 September 2018. Archived from the original on 31 May 2022. Retrieved 6 June 2022.
  82. ^ a b Mishra, T. K. (4 August 2021). The Power of Ethics: Some lessons from the Bhagavad-Gita. K.K. Publications. p. 52. ISBN 978-81-7844-127-6. Archived from the original on 30 July 2022. Retrieved 21 June 2022.
  83. ^ a b Ghose, Aurobindo (September 1998). «Political Writings and Speeches. 1890–1908: The Glory of God in Man». Bande Mataram II. ISBN 978-81-7058-416-2.
  84. ^ Paul Williams (2008). Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations. Routledge. pp. 68–69. ISBN 978-1-134-25056-1. Archived from the original on 21 November 2016. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  85. ^ Christopher W. Gowans (2014). Buddhist Moral Philosophy: An Introduction. Routledge. pp. 69–70. ISBN 978-1-317-65934-1. Archived from the original on 12 November 2021. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  86. ^ Kern, Andrea (2 January 2017). Sources of Knowledge: On the Concept of a Rational Capacity for Knowledge. Harvard University Press. pp. 8–10, 133. ISBN 978-0-674-41611-6.
  87. ^ O’Brien, Daniel. «The Epistemology of Perception». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 25 October 2022.
  88. ^ a b Audi, Robert (2002). «The Sources of Knowledge». The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology. Oxford University Press. pp. 71–94. ISBN 978-0-19-513005-8. Archived from the original on 12 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  89. ^ Gardiner, J. M. (29 September 2001). «Episodic memory and autonoetic consciousness: a first-person approach». Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences. 356 (1413): 1351–1361. doi:10.1098/rstb.2001.0955. ISSN 0962-8436. PMC 1088519. PMID 11571027.
  90. ^ Michaelian, Kourken; Sutton, John (2017). «Memory: 3. Episodicity». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 5 October 2021. Retrieved 2 October 2021.
  91. ^ Markie, Peter; Folescu, M. (2021). «Rationalism vs. Empiricism». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 9 August 2019. Retrieved 8 June 2022.
  92. ^ Leonard, Nick (2021). «Epistemological Problems of Testimony». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 10 July 2022. Retrieved 8 June 2022.
  93. ^ Green, Christopher R. «Epistemology of Testimony». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 7 March 2022. Retrieved 8 June 2022.
  94. ^ Hasan, Ali; Fumerton, Richard (2018). «Foundationalist Theories of Epistemic Justification». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 6 June 2022.
  95. ^ Fumerton, Richard (2022). Foundationalism. doi:10.1017/9781009028868. ISBN 978-1-009-02886-8. Archived from the original on 12 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  96. ^ Cameron, Ross (2018). «Infinite Regress Arguments». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 2 January 2020. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  97. ^ Clark, Romane (1988). «Vicious Infinite Regress Arguments». Philosophical Perspectives. 2: 369–380. doi:10.2307/2214081. JSTOR 2214081. Archived from the original on 26 March 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  98. ^ Murphy, Peter. «Coherentism in Epistemology». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 12 June 2022. Retrieved 8 June 2022.
  99. ^ Lammenranta, Markus. «Epistemic Circularity». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 27 January 2021. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  100. ^ Schafer, Karl (September 2014). «Knowledge and Two Forms of Non-Accidental Truth». Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 89 (2): 375. doi:10.1111/phpr.12062. What the Gettier cases show is that this condition is insufficient to capture all the ways in which accidental truth is incompatible with knowledge.
  101. ^ a b c Degenhardt, M. A. B. (13 August 2019). Education and the Value of Knowledge. Routledge. p. 1-6. ISBN 978-1-000-62799-2.
  102. ^ a b c Pritchard, Duncan (1 October 2013). «2 The value of knowledge». What is this thing called Knowledge?. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-57367-7. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  103. ^ a b c d e f Olsson, Erik J (December 2011). «The Value of Knowledge: The Value of Knowledge». Philosophy Compass. 6 (12): 874–883. doi:10.1111/j.1747-9991.2011.00425.x. S2CID 143034920.
  104. ^ a b c d e f Pritchard, Duncan; Turri, John; Carter, J. Adam (2022). «The Value of Knowledge». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 19 September 2022.
  105. ^ Plato (2002). Five Dialogues. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Pub. Co. pp. 89–90, 97b–98a. ISBN 978-0-87220-633-5.
  106. ^ Pritchard, Duncan (April 2007). «Recent Work on Epistemic Value». American Philosophical Quarterly. 44 (2): 85–110. JSTOR 20464361.
  107. ^ Turri, John; Alfano, Mark; Greco, John (2021). «Virtue Epistemology: 6. Epistemic Value». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 20 September 2022.
  108. ^ Kvanvig, Jonathan L. (2003). The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding. Cambridge University Press. p. 200. ISBN 978-1-139-44228-2. Archived from the original on 23 July 2020. Retrieved 16 July 2020.
  109. ^ Lycan, William G. (24 January 2019). «2. Moore against the New Skeptics». On Evidence in Philosophy. Oxford University Press. pp. 21–36. ISBN 978-0-19-256526-6.
  110. ^ Zagzebski 1999, p. 97–8.
  111. ^ McDermid, Douglas. «Pragmatism: 2b. Anti-Cartesianism». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  112. ^ Misak, Cheryl (7 February 2002). Truth, Politics, Morality: Pragmatism and Deliberation. Routledge. p. 53. ISBN 978-1-134-82618-6.
  113. ^ Hamner, M. Gail (2003). American Pragmatism: A Religious Genealogy. Oxford University Press. p. 87. ISBN 978-0-19-515547-1.
  114. ^ Weisberg, Jonathan (2021). «Formal Epistemology». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 14 March 2015. Retrieved 5 June 2022.
  115. ^ Das, Nilanjan; Salow, Bernhard (2018). «Transparency and the KK Principle». Noûs. 52 (1): 3–23. doi:10.1111/nous.12158. Archived from the original on 12 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  116. ^ Dokic, Jérôme; Égré, Paul (2009). «Margin for Error and the Transparency of Knowledge». Synthese. 166 (1): 1–20. doi:10.1007/s11229-007-9245-y. S2CID 14221986. Archived from the original on 12 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  117. ^ a b Pritchard, Duncan (1 October 2013). «11 Scientific knowledge». What is this thing called Knowledge?. Routledge. pp. 115–8. ISBN 978-1-134-57367-7. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  118. ^ a b Moser, Paul K. (27 October 2005). «13. Scientific Knowledge». The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology. Oxford University Press. p. 385. ISBN 978-0-19-020818-9.
  119. ^ Moser, Paul K. (27 October 2005). «13. Scientific Knowledge». The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology. Oxford University Press. p. 386. ISBN 978-0-19-020818-9.
  120. ^ Moser, Paul K. (27 October 2005). «13. Scientific Knowledge». The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology. Oxford University Press. p. 390. ISBN 978-0-19-020818-9.Hatfield, Gary (1996). «Scientific method». In Craig, Edward (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge.«scientific method». www.britannica.com. Retrieved 17 July 2022.Hepburn, Brian; Andersen, Hanne (2021). «Scientific Method». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 23 July 2022.

  121. ^ «scientific method». www.britannica.com. Retrieved 17 July 2022.
  122. ^ Hatfield, Gary (1996). «Scientific method». In Craig, Edward (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge.
  123. ^ Hepburn, Brian; Andersen, Hanne (2021). «Scientific Method». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 23 July 2022.
  124. ^ Pritchard, Duncan (1 October 2013). «11 Scientific knowledge». What is this thing called Knowledge?. Routledge. pp. 123–5. ISBN 978-1-134-57367-7. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  125. ^ Niiniluoto, Ilkka (2019). «Scientific Progress». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 8 March 2023.
  126. ^ a b c d e Clark, Kelly James. «Religious Epistemology». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 21 September 2022.
  127. ^ a b Penelhum, Terence (1971). «1. Faith, Scepticism and Philosophy». Problems of Religious Knowledge. Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-333-10633-4.
  128. ^ a b c Forrest, Peter (2021). «The Epistemology of Religion». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 21 September 2022.
  129. ^ Dougherty, Trent (12 June 2014). «Faith, Trust, and Testimony». Religious Faith and Intellectual Virtue: 97–123. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199672158.003.0005. ISBN 978-0-19-967215-8.
  130. ^ Stevenson, Leslie (March 2003). «Opinion, Belief or Faith, and Knowledge». Kantian Review. 7: 72–101. doi:10.1017/S1369415400001746. ISSN 2044-2394. S2CID 143965507.
  131. ^ Paden, William E. (2009). «Comparative religion». The Routledge Companion to the Study of Religion. pp. 239–256. doi:10.4324/9780203868768-19. ISBN 978-0-203-86876-8.
  132. ^ Bouquet, Alan Coates (1962). Comparative Religion: A Short Outline. CUP Archive. p. 1.
  133. ^ Carson, Thomas; Cerrito, Joann, eds. (2003). New Catholic encyclopedia Vol. 14: Thi–Zwi (2nd ed.). Detroit: Thomson/Gale. p. 164. ISBN 978-0-7876-4018-7.
  134. ^ Delahunty, Andrew; Dignen, Sheila (13 September 2012). «Tree of knowledge». Oxford Dictionary of Reference and Allusion. OUP Oxford. p. 365. ISBN 978-0-19-956746-1.
  135. ^ Blayney, Benjamin, ed. (1769). «Genesis». The King James Bible. Oxford University Press.
  136. ^ Vost, Kevin (15 December 2016). Seven Gifts of the Holy Spirit. Sophia Institute Press. pp. 75–6. ISBN 978-1-62282-412-0.
  137. ^ Campo, Juan Eduardo (2009). Encyclopedia of Islam. Infobase Publishing. p. 515. ISBN 978-1-4381-2696-8.
  138. ^ Swartley, Keith E. (2 November 2005). Encountering the World of Islam. InterVarsity Press. p. 63. ISBN 978-0-8308-5644-2.
  139. ^ Burton, David (2002). «Knowledge and Liberation: Philosophical Ruminations on a Buddhist Conundrum». Philosophy East and West. 52 (3): 326–345. doi:10.1353/pew.2002.0011. ISSN 0031-8221. JSTOR 1400322. S2CID 145257341.
  140. ^ a b Chaudhary, Angraj (2017). «Avijjā)». In Sarao, K.T.S.; Long, Jeffery D. (eds.). Buddhism and Jainism. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer Nature. pp. 202–3. ISBN 978-94-024-0851-5.
  141. ^ a b Chaudhary, Angraj (2017). «Wisdom (Buddhism)». In Sarao, K.T.S.; Long, Jeffery D. (eds.). Buddhism and Jainism. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer Nature. pp. 1373–4. ISBN 978-94-024-0851-5.
  142. ^ Jones, Constance; Ryan, James D. (2006). «jnana». Encyclopedia of Hinduism. Infobase Publishing. ISBN 978-0-8160-7564-5.
  143. ^ Jones, Constance; Ryan, James D. (2006). «Bhagavad Gita». Encyclopedia of Hinduism. Infobase Publishing. ISBN 978-0-8160-7564-5.
  144. ^ a b c d e f g h Allwood, Carl Martin (17 October 2013). «Anthropology of Knowledge». The Encyclopedia of Cross-Cultural Psychology. John Wiley & Sons, Inc. pp. 69–72. doi:10.1002/9781118339893.wbeccp025. ISBN 978-1-118-33989-3.
  145. ^ Boyer, Dominic (2007). «1. Of Dialectical Germans and Dialectical Ethnographers: Notes from an Engagement with Philosophy». In Harris, Mark (ed.). Ways of Knowing: Anthropological Approaches to Crafting Experience and Knowledge. Berghahn Books. ISBN 978-1-84545-364-0.
  146. ^ a b Cohen, Emma (2010). «Anthropology of knowledge». The Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute. 16: S193–S202. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9655.2010.01617.x. hdl:11858/00-001M-0000-0012-9B72-7. JSTOR 40606072.
  147. ^ a b c d Barth, Fredrik (February 2002). «An Anthropology of Knowledge». Current Anthropology. 43 (1): 1–18. doi:10.1086/324131. hdl:1956/4191. ISSN 0011-3204.
  148. ^ Kuruk, Paul (28 March 2020). Traditional Knowledge, Genetic Resources, Customary Law and Intellectual Property: A Global Primer. Edward Elgar Publishing. p. 25. ISBN 978-1-78536-848-6.
  149. ^ Hansen, Judith Friedman (1982). «From Background to Foreground: Toward an Anthropology of Learning». Anthropology & Education Quarterly. 13 (2): 193. doi:10.1525/aeq.1982.13.2.05x1833m. ISSN 0161-7761. JSTOR 3216630.
  150. ^ Boyer, Dominic (December 2005). Spirit and System: Media, Intellectuals, and the Dialectic in Modern German Culture. University of Chicago Press. p. 34. ISBN 978-0-226-06891-6.
  151. ^ Aspen, Harald (2001). Amhara Traditions of Knowledge: Spirit Mediums and Their Clients. Otto Harrassowitz Verlag. p. 5. ISBN 978-3-447-04410-3.
  152. ^ Coser, Lewis A. (1968). «Knowledge, Sociology of». International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences. Gale. ISBN 978-0-02-928751-4.
  153. ^ Tufari, P. (2003). «Knowledge, Sociology of». New Catholic Encyclopedia. Thomson/Gale. ISBN 978-0-7876-4008-8.
  154. ^ Scheler, Max; Stikkers, Kenneth W. (16 July 2012). Problems of a Sociology of Knowledge (Routledge Revivals). Routledge. p. 23. ISBN 978-0-415-62334-6.
  155. ^ Lee, Jerry Won (22 September 2017). The Politics of Translingualism: After Englishes. Routledge. p. 67. ISBN 978-1-315-31051-0.
  156. ^ Dreyer, Jaco S. (21 April 2017). «Practical theology and the call for the decolonisation of higher education in South Africa: Reflections and proposals». HTS Teologiese Studies / Theological Studies. 73 (4): 1–7. doi:10.4102/hts.v73i4.4805.

Bibliography

  • Zagzebski, Linda (1999). «What Is Knowledge?». In Greco, John; Sosa, Ernest (eds.). The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology. Malden, MA: Blackwell. pp. 92–116. doi:10.1002/9781405164863.ch3. ISBN 978-0-631-20290-5. OCLC 39269507. S2CID 158886670. Archived from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.

External links

  • Knowledge at PhilPapers
  • «Knowledge». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). «The Value of Knowledge». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). «The Analysis of Knowledge». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). «Knowledge by Acquaintance vs. Description». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Knowledge at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project

Last Update: Jan 03, 2023

This is a question our experts keep getting from time to time. Now, we have got the complete detailed explanation and answer for everyone, who is interested!


Asked by: Glennie Jacobs

Score: 4.3/5
(61 votes)

Knowledge is a familiarity, awareness, or understanding of someone or something, such as facts, skills, or objects. By most accounts, knowledge can be acquired in many different ways and from many sources, including but not limited to perception, reason, memory, testimony, scientific inquiry, education, and practice.

What is the real meaning of knowledge?

Knowledge is a familiarity, awareness, or understanding of someone or something, such as facts (descriptive knowledge), skills (procedural knowledge), or objects (acquaintance knowledge). … The term «knowledge» can refer to a theoretical or practical understanding of a subject.

What is the best definition of knowledge?

1a(1) : the fact or condition of knowing something with familiarity gained through experience or association. (2) : acquaintance with or understanding of a science, art, or technique. b(1) : the fact or condition of being aware of something.

What is an example of knowledge?

Knowledge is defined as what is learned, understood or aware of. An example of knowledge is learning the alphabet. … The state or fact of knowing.

What is knowledge easy language?

Knowledge means the things which are true, as opposed to opinion. Information which is correct is knowledge. Knowledge can always be supported by evidence. … In philosophy, the study of knowledge is called epistemology. The philosopher Plato defined knowledge as «justified true belief».

40 related questions found

What are the 4 types of knowledge?

Cognitive theorists have researched at length about the progression and refinement of knowledge and experience over time as individuals develop expertise within a given structure (Schuell, 1990). During this progression, four types of knowledge are developed: declarative, procedural, contextual, and somatic.

What are the 5 sources of knowledge?

The sources of new knowledge are authority, intuition, scientific empiricisim, and an educated guess. Authority, intuition, and an educated guess are all sources of hypotheses, but scientific empiricism is the only source of new knowledge.

What is difference knowledge and skills?

Knowledge — “facts, information, and skills acquired by a person through experience or education; the theoretical or practical understanding of a subject”, or, “awareness or familiarity gained by experience of a fact or situation”. Skills – “the ability to do something well; expertise”, or, “a particular ability”.

How do you describe knowledge?

Adjectives often used with “knowledge”: extensive, deep, superficial, theoretical, practical, useful, working, encyclopedic, public, private, scientific, tacit, explicit, general, specialized, special, broad, declarative, procedural, innate, etc.

How do you acquire knowledge?

Apart from some specific industry-relevant methods, try these general ways to gain more knowledge:

  1. Be Curious.
  2. Reading.
  3. Research.
  4. Listening.
  5. Writing.
  6. Teach Others.
  7. Practice.
  8. Be Thirsty and Willing.

What is knowledge and its importance?

Knowledge does much more than just help students hone their thinking skills: It actually makes learning easier. Knowledge is not only cumulative, it grows exponentially. Those with a rich base of factual knowledge find it easier to learn more — the rich get richer.

What is knowledge and its types?

There are three core types of knowledge: explicit (documented information), implicit (applied information), and tacit (understood information). These different types of knowledge work together to form the spectrum of how we pass information to each other, learn, and grow.

Does knowledge have to be true?

Belief is necessary but not sufficient for knowledge. We are all sometimes mistaken in what we believe; in other words, while some of our beliefs are true, others are false. … However, we can say that truth is a condition of knowledge; that is, if a belief is not true, it cannot constitute knowledge.

Why is knowledge important in life?

Knowledge is important for personal growth and development. … * Knowledge solves problems– problems in life which can be solved with the power of knowledge. Knowledge sharpens our skills like reasoning and problem-solving. A strong base of knowledge helps brains function more smoothly and effectively.

Is knowledge the key to success?

Knowledge is the key to success, to power, to respect in high societies, moreover, the key to one’s personality. Based on knowledge, one gets a job, earns a living and gains respect among fellow people.

What is the purpose of knowledge?

Knowledge is like glue that sticks information as well as learning together. When we have prior knowledge about a topic, we understand it better. It plays an important role in students’ life especially in the school. If they don’t have related knowledge, they face difficulties in understanding the text.

How do we use knowledge?

Usually, knowledge is paired with the preposition of. Example: He has first-hand knowledge of what happened. Example: I have limited knowledge of European history. Example: She’s never lived out of state to my knowledge.

What is a synonym for good knowledge?

Adjective. Profoundly wise. sage. wise.

What is the root word of knowledge?

Knowledge comes from the Greek word, Gnosis, signifying knowing through observation or experience.

How do you use knowledge and skills?

There are many ways you can apply classroom knowledge on the job.

  1. Reflect on Your Academic Knowledge.
  2. Seek Opportunities for Continued Practice.
  3. Teach it To Others.
  4. Set Goals for Implementation.
  5. Group Work.
  6. Change Your Routine to Include New Knowledge.
  7. Don’t Try to Implement Everything at Once.

What comes first knowledge or skills?

To make it simple, knowledge is theoretical and skills are practical. … The same applies to a job: One can know a lot about a subject matter, but might not have the skills required to apply that knowledge to specific tasks, since knowledge does not provide skills.

How do you develop knowledge and skills?

8 Ways to Keep Your Knowledge and Skills Current

  1. Take Professional Development Courses. …
  2. Use Online Resources. …
  3. Attend Professional Events. …
  4. Network Online. …
  5. Invest in Continuing Education and Certifications. …
  6. Follow Thought Leaders on Social Media. …
  7. Read White Papers and Case Studies. …
  8. Determine Hard and Soft Skills to Develop.

What are the six sources of knowledge?

What are the sources of our knowledge in education? It seems to me that the traditional six ways of knowing, identified by philosophers-appeal to authority, intuition, formal logic, empiricism, pragmatism, and scepticism—should all be applied to our endeavours to know more about what is happening in education.

What are four methods of acquiring knowledge?

Four sub-processes of attaining knowledge are observation, explanation, prediction and control.

What is the most important source of knowledge?

Direct Empirical Experience as the Source of Knowledge

The most fundamental source of information is what a person comes to know by direct personal experience. This would include learning to ride a bike, that something is round, or that one thing is bigger than another.

That is why Anscombe calls practical knowledge ˜knowledge without observation,™ meaning to exclude not only observation in the narrow sense but knowledge by inference (Anscombe 1963, p. 50). ❋ Setiya, Kieran (2009)

According to this, Harpo does not acquire any new factual knowledge, only ˜knowledge how™, in the form of the ability to respond directly to sounds, which he could not do before. ❋ Robinson, Howard (2007)

“The best grounds for accepting contextualism concerning knowledge attributions come from how knowledge-attributing (and knowledge-denying) sentences are used in ordinary, non-philosophical talk: What ordinary speakers will count as ˜knowledge™ in some non-philosophical contexts they will deny is such in others” ❋ Rysiew, Patrick (2007)

This proposal that the concept of knowledge may have changed over time so that what we now call ˜knowledge™ may sometimes perform a different function to the one that our original concept of knowledge was supposed to track is clearly of central importance to debates about the value of knowledge, as Craig’s account of objectification indicates. ❋ Pritchard, Duncan (2007)

Brahmans, that of the Aupanishadas, which has laid down for its first doctrine that _works are for the sake of understanding_, that the practice of ritual is of value only as a help to the mystic knowledge of the All. But here they have not halted; they have gone a further step, and declared that _knowledge once attained, works become needless_. ❋ Lionel D. Barnett (N/A)

Besides when the statute speaks of «knowledge,» aside from the expression «wilfully» it means _knowledge_ as a _fact_ — not any _forced presumption of knowledge_ against the clear facts of the case. ❋ Anonymous (N/A)

And the Master’s answer would come in that clear, quiet voice of His, «yes, tarry: you have knowledge enough, but _knowledge is not enough_, there must be power.» ❋ S.D. Gordon (N/A)

_For a knowledge of liberal sciences, but a controlled and exact knowledge_, forms men who will love the truth …. ❋ Louis Bertrand (1903)

That is the point that the student ought to grasp; this knowledge of God, not the belief in Him, not the faith in Him, not only vague idea concerning Him, but the _knowledge_ of Him, is possible to man. ❋ Annie Wood Besant (1890)

_Sound knowledge_, a _sound head_, _strong faith_, and _great grace_ — all these combined — may indeed preserve one whom the necessity of his position may lead into un-Catholic schools; but no one will deny that this anti-Catholic literature must exercise a most baneful influence over all those who, without sufficient preparation from nature or grace, plunge into it, in the pursuit of amusement or knowledge. ❋ Michael M��ller (1862)

He thinks that you were drowned — as, indeed, so did I— the time that you were thrown overboard without my knowledge — mind that, _without my knowledge_ — and your father in his madness thinks he is commissioned by God to avenge your death. ❋ Arthur Twidle (1859)

Hence a knowledge of Physics, particularly the physics which Democritus taught, was needful to deliver men from false hopes and false fears. [784] (ii.) _Ignorance of the nature of man, of his faculties, powers, and the sources and limits of his knowledge_, from whence arise illusions, prejudices, and errors. ❋ Unknown (1852)

But let us turn to that knowledge which God has given, and which therefore does not admit of improvement by lapse of time, this is _religious knowledge_. ❋ John Henry Newman (1845)

It is plain that the temptation under which man fell in paradise was this, an ambitious curiosity after knowledge which was not allowed him: next came the desire of the eyes and the flesh, but the forbidden tree was called the tree of _knowledge_; the Tempter _promised_ knowledge; and after the fall Almighty God pronounced, as in the text, that man had gained it. ❋ John Henry Newman (1845)

‘_Generally_,’ he says, ‘_let this be a rule_, that all partitions of knowledge be accepted rather for LINES and VEINS, than for _sections_ and _separations_, and that _the continuance and entireness of knowledge_ be preserved. ❋ Delia Bacon (1835)

The reason why parents are to be consulted is, because they deliberate from judgement, knowledge, and love; from _judgement_, because they are in an advanced age, which excels in judgement, and discerns what is suitable and unsuitable: from _knowledge_, in respect to both the suitor and their daughter; in respect to the suitor they procure information, and in respect to their daughter they already know; wherefore they conclude respecting both with united discernment: from ❋ Emanuel Swedenborg (1730)

«The worst enemy of knowledge is not ignorance but the illusion of knowledge» ❋ Unknown (2009)

_inference_, or _the derivation of new knowledge from old knowledge_. ❋ Ralph Barton Perry (1916)

If the imagery of logic or passion ever comes to convey _knowledge_, it does so by virtue of a concomitant physical adjustment to external things; for the nerve of real or transcendent knowledge is the notice which one part of the world may take of another part; and it is this momentous cognisance, no matter what intangible feelings may supply terms for its prosody, that enlarges the mind to some practical purpose and informs it about the world. ❋ George Santayana (1907)

[Knowledge] is something aqcquired by [everything] we [experience] ❋ Justincn618 (2017)

«Hey did you hear that Johnny is pretty knowledgable? Yeah I’d like to get some of his knowledge.» «How much knowledge did [the teacher] [squeeze] [in you] today?» ❋ Ptom (2008)

‘did you see that car? it was totally knowledge!’
‘oh my [gosh] did you see [that ugly] [chick]? no knowledge ❋ Brittney(Y) (2008)

[Sorry I] can’t be at [your funeral], I was [eating ass] knowledge! ❋ Profressour Dewy (2023)

Knowledge of [heat]’s [potential] pain prevents (most) people from [sticking] their hand into fire. ❋ Ieo (2019)

[Robby]: What’s up, [dun]?
Gary: [Knowledge Knowledge], boy (with accompanying hand gesture.) ❋ Hott Nickelz (2009)

[Your mate] doesn’t [stand] a chance to [pass] the Knowledge no matter how hard he tries! ❋ Joesmith (2006)

[Knowledged]
You [just] [got] [knowledged] ❋ Aoster1 (2010)

[Lil bored] calls [KSI] [knowledge]. ❋ S/he’s Just A Friend (2020)

I am gaining knowledge so that I am prepared to debate [prehistoric] [Inuit] [burial] rituals at the office. ❋ DreadPirateRoberts (2015)

1

a(1)

: the fact or condition of knowing something with familiarity gained through experience or association

(2)

: acquaintance with or understanding of a science, art, or technique

b(1)

: the fact or condition of being aware of something

(2)

: the range of one’s information or understanding

answered to the best of my knowledge

d

: the fact or condition of having information or of being learned

a person of unusual knowledge

2

a

: the sum of what is known : the body of truth, information, and principles acquired by humankind

b

archaic

: a branch of learning

Synonyms

Choose the Right Synonym for knowledge



rich in the knowledge of human nature

learning applies to knowledge acquired especially through formal, often advanced, schooling.



a book that demonstrates vast learning

erudition strongly implies the acquiring of profound, recondite, or bookish learning.



an erudition unusual even in a scholar

scholarship implies the possession of learning characteristic of the advanced scholar in a specialized field of study or investigation.



a work of first-rate literary scholarship

Example Sentences

At that time the word science had not been narrowed down to one kind of knowledge; it meant whatever was known, and men of learning were still able to possess most of it.


Jacques Barzun, From Dawn to Decadence, 2000


With their aid, he should be able to adapt himself selectively to his culture, rejecting its evils, stupidities and irrelevances, gratefully accepting all its treasures of accumulated knowledge … and practical wisdom.


Aldous Huxley, «Culture and the … ,»

in Artificial Paradises, Mike Jay editor1999


The knowledge of the godawful way people act (their greed, their vicarious or direct violence), and of the youth and helplessness of those who died, leads to shame …


Harold Brodkey, New Yorker, 30 Jan. 1995



She has little knowledge of fashion.



He has devoted himself to the pursuit of knowledge.



She gained a thorough knowledge of local customs.



Did you have any knowledge of her intentions?

See More

Recent Examples on the Web

Following Alexander the Great’s conquest of Egypt in 330 B.C.E., the two cultures traded their knowledge of the stars, with the Greeks introducing the concept of zodiac signs and the Egyptians discussing the seasonal movement of the sun and the patterns that make up constellations.


Christopher Parker, Smithsonian Magazine, 4 Apr. 2023





That knowledge helped him up his skills and grow his audience.


Curtis Bunn, NBC News, 3 Apr. 2023





One former public school teacher issued a warning to parents nationwide on how educators are indoctrinating children on controversial issues like transgenderism — all without their knowledge and consent.


Bailee Hill, Fox News, 2 Apr. 2023





Understanding how water is stored on the moon is useful: That knowledge could point future lunar astronauts toward potential resources that might one day be converted to drinking water or even rocket fuel.


Katie Hunt, CNN, 1 Apr. 2023





The residents at Brookdale Senior Living have a wealth of wisdom, but there are some gaps in that knowledge.


Steve Hartman, CBS News, 31 Mar. 2023





This is a sovereign and solemn requirement of all states to inform their own people of what is going on in their country, to the best of their knowledge.


Beth Mole, Ars Technica, 30 Mar. 2023





Learning from other industry professionals and gaining their knowledge and experience can be invaluable.


Sonia Singh, Rolling Stone, 30 Mar. 2023





And paleontology plays an important part in producing that knowledge.


Sam Walters, Discover Magazine, 30 Mar. 2023



See More

These examples are programmatically compiled from various online sources to illustrate current usage of the word ‘knowledge.’ Any opinions expressed in the examples do not represent those of Merriam-Webster or its editors. Send us feedback about these examples.

Word History

Etymology

Middle English knowlege, from knowlechen to acknowledge, irregular from knowen

First Known Use

14th century, in the meaning defined at sense 4

Time Traveler

The first known use of knowledge was
in the 14th century

Dictionary Entries Near knowledge

Cite this Entry

“Knowledge.” Merriam-Webster.com Dictionary, Merriam-Webster, https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/knowledge. Accessed 14 Apr. 2023.

Share

More from Merriam-Webster on knowledge

Last Updated:
7 Apr 2023
— Updated example sentences

Subscribe to America’s largest dictionary and get thousands more definitions and advanced search—ad free!

Merriam-Webster unabridged


Asked by: Glennie Jacobs

Score: 4.3/5
(61 votes)

Knowledge is a familiarity, awareness, or understanding of someone or something, such as facts, skills, or objects. By most accounts, knowledge can be acquired in many different ways and from many sources, including but not limited to perception, reason, memory, testimony, scientific inquiry, education, and practice.

What is the real meaning of knowledge?

Knowledge is a familiarity, awareness, or understanding of someone or something, such as facts (descriptive knowledge), skills (procedural knowledge), or objects (acquaintance knowledge). … The term «knowledge» can refer to a theoretical or practical understanding of a subject.

What is the best definition of knowledge?

1a(1) : the fact or condition of knowing something with familiarity gained through experience or association. (2) : acquaintance with or understanding of a science, art, or technique. b(1) : the fact or condition of being aware of something.

What is an example of knowledge?

Knowledge is defined as what is learned, understood or aware of. An example of knowledge is learning the alphabet. … The state or fact of knowing.

What is knowledge easy language?

Knowledge means the things which are true, as opposed to opinion. Information which is correct is knowledge. Knowledge can always be supported by evidence. … In philosophy, the study of knowledge is called epistemology. The philosopher Plato defined knowledge as «justified true belief».

40 related questions found

What are the 4 types of knowledge?

Cognitive theorists have researched at length about the progression and refinement of knowledge and experience over time as individuals develop expertise within a given structure (Schuell, 1990). During this progression, four types of knowledge are developed: declarative, procedural, contextual, and somatic.

What are the 5 sources of knowledge?

The sources of new knowledge are authority, intuition, scientific empiricisim, and an educated guess. Authority, intuition, and an educated guess are all sources of hypotheses, but scientific empiricism is the only source of new knowledge.

What is difference knowledge and skills?

Knowledge — “facts, information, and skills acquired by a person through experience or education; the theoretical or practical understanding of a subject”, or, “awareness or familiarity gained by experience of a fact or situation”. Skills – “the ability to do something well; expertise”, or, “a particular ability”.

How do you describe knowledge?

Adjectives often used with “knowledge”: extensive, deep, superficial, theoretical, practical, useful, working, encyclopedic, public, private, scientific, tacit, explicit, general, specialized, special, broad, declarative, procedural, innate, etc.

How do you acquire knowledge?

Apart from some specific industry-relevant methods, try these general ways to gain more knowledge:

  1. Be Curious.
  2. Reading.
  3. Research.
  4. Listening.
  5. Writing.
  6. Teach Others.
  7. Practice.
  8. Be Thirsty and Willing.

What is knowledge and its importance?

Knowledge does much more than just help students hone their thinking skills: It actually makes learning easier. Knowledge is not only cumulative, it grows exponentially. Those with a rich base of factual knowledge find it easier to learn more — the rich get richer.

What is knowledge and its types?

There are three core types of knowledge: explicit (documented information), implicit (applied information), and tacit (understood information). These different types of knowledge work together to form the spectrum of how we pass information to each other, learn, and grow.

Does knowledge have to be true?

Belief is necessary but not sufficient for knowledge. We are all sometimes mistaken in what we believe; in other words, while some of our beliefs are true, others are false. … However, we can say that truth is a condition of knowledge; that is, if a belief is not true, it cannot constitute knowledge.

Why is knowledge important in life?

Knowledge is important for personal growth and development. … * Knowledge solves problems– problems in life which can be solved with the power of knowledge. Knowledge sharpens our skills like reasoning and problem-solving. A strong base of knowledge helps brains function more smoothly and effectively.

Is knowledge the key to success?

Knowledge is the key to success, to power, to respect in high societies, moreover, the key to one’s personality. Based on knowledge, one gets a job, earns a living and gains respect among fellow people.

What is the purpose of knowledge?

Knowledge is like glue that sticks information as well as learning together. When we have prior knowledge about a topic, we understand it better. It plays an important role in students’ life especially in the school. If they don’t have related knowledge, they face difficulties in understanding the text.

How do we use knowledge?

Usually, knowledge is paired with the preposition of. Example: He has first-hand knowledge of what happened. Example: I have limited knowledge of European history. Example: She’s never lived out of state to my knowledge.

What is a synonym for good knowledge?

Adjective. Profoundly wise. sage. wise.

What is the root word of knowledge?

Knowledge comes from the Greek word, Gnosis, signifying knowing through observation or experience.

How do you use knowledge and skills?

There are many ways you can apply classroom knowledge on the job.

  1. Reflect on Your Academic Knowledge.
  2. Seek Opportunities for Continued Practice.
  3. Teach it To Others.
  4. Set Goals for Implementation.
  5. Group Work.
  6. Change Your Routine to Include New Knowledge.
  7. Don’t Try to Implement Everything at Once.

What comes first knowledge or skills?

To make it simple, knowledge is theoretical and skills are practical. … The same applies to a job: One can know a lot about a subject matter, but might not have the skills required to apply that knowledge to specific tasks, since knowledge does not provide skills.

How do you develop knowledge and skills?

8 Ways to Keep Your Knowledge and Skills Current

  1. Take Professional Development Courses. …
  2. Use Online Resources. …
  3. Attend Professional Events. …
  4. Network Online. …
  5. Invest in Continuing Education and Certifications. …
  6. Follow Thought Leaders on Social Media. …
  7. Read White Papers and Case Studies. …
  8. Determine Hard and Soft Skills to Develop.

What are the six sources of knowledge?

What are the sources of our knowledge in education? It seems to me that the traditional six ways of knowing, identified by philosophers-appeal to authority, intuition, formal logic, empiricism, pragmatism, and scepticism—should all be applied to our endeavours to know more about what is happening in education.

What are four methods of acquiring knowledge?

Four sub-processes of attaining knowledge are observation, explanation, prediction and control.

What is the most important source of knowledge?

Direct Empirical Experience as the Source of Knowledge

The most fundamental source of information is what a person comes to know by direct personal experience. This would include learning to ride a bike, that something is round, or that one thing is bigger than another.

Like this post? Please share to your friends:
  • What does the word john means
  • What does the word issue means
  • What does the word island
  • What does the word is out mean
  • What does the word introduction