Desires are states of mind that are expressed by terms like «wanting», «wishing», «longing» or «craving». A great variety of features is commonly associated with desires. They are seen as propositional attitudes towards conceivable states of affairs. They aim to change the world by representing how the world should be, unlike beliefs, which aim to represent how the world actually is. Desires are closely related to agency: they motivate the agent to realize them. For this to be possible, a desire has to be combined with a belief about which action would realize it. Desires present their objects in a favorable light, as something that appears to be good. Their fulfillment is normally experienced as pleasurable in contrast to the negative experience of failing to do so. Conscious desires are usually accompanied by some form of emotional response. While many researchers roughly agree on these general features, there is significant disagreement about how to define desires, i.e. which of these features are essential and which ones are merely accidental. Action-based theories define desires as structures that incline us toward actions. Pleasure-based theories focus on the tendency of desires to cause pleasure when fulfilled. Value-based theories identify desires with attitudes toward values, like judging or having an appearance that something is good.
Desires can be grouped into various types according to a few basic distinctions. Intrinsic desires concern what the subject wants for its own sake while instrumental desires are about what the subject wants for the sake of something else. Occurrent desires are either conscious or otherwise causally active, in contrast to standing desires, which exist somewhere in the back of one’s mind. Propositional desires are directed at possible states of affairs while object-desires are directly about objects. Various authors distinguish between higher desires associated with spiritual or religious goals and lower desires, which are concerned with bodily or sensory pleasures. Desires play a role in many different fields. There is disagreement whether desires should be understood as practical reasons or whether we can have practical reasons without having a desire to follow them. According to fitting-attitude theories of value, an object is valuable if it is fitting to desire this object or if we ought to desire it. Desire-satisfaction theories of well-being state that a person’s well-being is determined by whether that person’s desires are satisfied.
Marketing and advertising companies have used psychological research on how desire is stimulated to find more effective ways to induce consumers into buying a given product or service. Techniques include creating a sense of lack in the viewer or associating the product with desirable attributes. Desire plays a key role in art. The theme of desire is at the core of romance novels, which often create drama by showing cases where human desire is impeded by social conventions, class, or cultural barriers. Melodrama films use plots that appeal to the heightened emotions of the audience by showing «crises of human emotion, failed romance or friendship», in which desire is thwarted or unrequited.
Theories[edit]
Theories of desire aim to define desires in terms of their essential features.[1] A great variety of features are ascribed to desires, like that they are propositional attitudes, that they lead to actions, that their fulfillment tends to bring pleasure, etc.[2][3] Across the different theories of desires, there is a broad agreement about what these features are. Their disagreement concerns which of these features belong to the essence of desires and which ones are merely accidental or contingent.[1] Traditionally, the two most important theories define desires in terms of dispositions to cause actions or concerning their tendency to bring pleasure upon being fulfilled. An important alternative of more recent origin holds that desiring something means seeing the object of desire as valuable.[3]
General features[edit]
A great variety of features is ascribed to desires. They are usually seen as attitudes toward conceivable states of affairs, often referred to as propositional attitudes.[4] They differ from beliefs, which are also commonly seen as propositional attitudes, by their direction of fit.[4] Both beliefs and desires are representations of the world. But while beliefs aim at truth, i.e. to represent how the world actually is, desires aim to change the world by representing how the world should be. These two modes of representation have been termed mind-to-world and world-to-mind direction of fit respectively.[4][1] Desires can be either positive, in the sense that the subject wants a desirable state to be the case, or negative, in the sense that the subject wants an undesirable state not to be the case.[5] It is usually held that desires come in varying strengths: some things are desired more strongly than other things.[6] We desire things in regard to some features they have but usually not in regard to all of their features.[7]
Desires are also closely related to agency: we normally try to realize our desires when acting.[4] It is usually held that desires by themselves are not sufficient for actions: they have to be combined with beliefs. The desire to own a new mobile phone, for example, can only result in the action of ordering one online if paired with the belief that ordering it would contribute to the desire being fulfilled.[1] The fulfillment of desires is normally experienced as pleasurable in contrast to the negative experience of failing to do so.[3] But independently of whether the desire is fulfilled or not, there is a sense in which the desire presents its object in a favorable light, as something that appears to be good.[8] Besides causing actions and pleasures, desires also have various effects on the mental life. One of these effects is to frequently move the subject’s attention to the object of desire, specifically to its positive features.[3] Another effect of special interest to psychology is the tendency of desires to promote reward-based learning, for example, in the form of operant conditioning.[1]
Action-based theories[edit]
Action-based or motivational theories have traditionally been dominant.[3] They can take different forms but they all have in common that they define desires as structures that incline us toward actions.[1][7] This is especially relevant when ascribing desires, not from a first-person perspective, but from a third-person perspective. Action-based theories usually include some reference to beliefs in their definition, for example, that «to desire that P is to be disposed to bring it about that P, assuming one’s beliefs are true».[1] Despite their popularity and their usefulness for empirical investigations, action-based theories face various criticisms. These criticisms can roughly be divided into two groups. On the one hand, there are inclinations to act that are not based on desires.[1][3] Evaluative beliefs about what we should do, for example, incline us toward doing it, even if we do not want to do it.[4] There are also mental disorders that have a similar effect, like the tics associated with Tourette syndrome. On the other hand, there are desires that do not incline us toward action.[1][3] These include desires for things we cannot change, for example, a mathematician’s desire that the number Pi be a rational number. In some extreme cases, such desires may be very common, for example, a totally paralyzed person may have all kinds of regular desires but lacks any disposition to act due to the paralysis.[1]
Pleasure-based theories[edit]
It is one important feature of desires that their fulfillment is pleasurable. Pleasure-based or hedonic theories use this feature as part of their definition of desires.[2] According to one version, «to desire p is … to be disposed to take pleasure in it seeming that p and displeasure in it seeming that not-p».[1] Hedonic theories avoid many of the problems faced by action-based theories: they allow that other things besides desires incline us to actions and they have no problems explaining how a paralyzed person can still have desires.[3] But they also come with new problems of their own. One is that it is usually assumed that there is a causal relation between desires and pleasure: the satisfaction of desires is seen as the cause of the resulting pleasure. But this is only possible if cause and effect are two distinct things, not if they are identical.[3] Apart from this, there may also be bad or misleading desires whose fulfillment does not bring the pleasure they originally seemed to promise.[9]
Value-based theories[edit]
Value-based theories are of more recent origin than action-based theories and hedonic theories. They identify desires with attitudes toward values. Cognitivist versions, sometimes referred to as desire-as-belief theses, equate desires with beliefs that something is good, thereby categorizing desires as one type of belief.[1][4][10] But such versions face the difficulty of explaining how we can have beliefs about what we should do despite not wanting to do it. A more promising approach identifies desires not with value-beliefs but with value-seemings.[8] On this view, to desire to have one more drink is the same as it seeming good to the subject to have one more drink. But such a seeming is compatible with the subject having the opposite belief that having one more drink would be a bad idea.[1] A closely related theory is due to T. M. Scanlon, who holds that desires are judgments of what we have reasons to do.[1] Critics have pointed out that value-based theories have difficulties explaining how animals, like cats or dogs, can have desires, since they arguably cannot represent things as being good in the relevant sense.[3]
Others[edit]
A great variety of other theories of desires have been proposed. Attention-based theories take the tendency of attention to keep returning to the desired object as the defining feature of desires.[3] Learning-based theories define desires in terms of their tendency to promote reward-based learning, for example, in the form of operant conditioning.[3] Functionalist theories define desires in terms of the causal roles played by internal states while interpretationist theories ascribe desires to persons or animals based on what would best explain their behavior.[1] Holistic theories combine various of the aforementioned features in their definition of desires.[1]
Types[edit]
Desires can be grouped into various types according to a few basic distinctions. Something is desired intrinsically if the subject desires it for its own sake. Otherwise, the desire is instrumental or extrinsic.[2] Occurrent desires are causally active while standing desires exist somewhere in the back of one’s mind.[11] Propositional desires are directed at possible states of affairs, in contrast to object-desires, which are directly about objects.[12]
Intrinsic and instrumental[edit]
The distinction between intrinsic and instrumental or extrinsic desires is central to many issues concerning desires.[2][3] Something is desired intrinsically if the subject desires it for its own sake.[1][9] Pleasure is a common object of intrinsic desires. According to psychological hedonism, it is the only thing desired intrinsically.[2] Intrinsic desires have a special status in that they do not depend on other desires. They contrast with instrumental desires, in which something is desired for the sake of something else.[1][9][3] For example, Haruto enjoys movies, which is why he has an intrinsic desire to watch them. But in order to watch them, he has to step into his car, navigate through the traffic to the nearby cinema, wait in line, pay for the ticket, etc. He desires to do all these things as well, but only in an instrumental manner. He would not do all these things were it not for his intrinsic desire to watch the movie. It is possible to desire the same thing both intrinsically and instrumentally at the same time.[1] So if Haruto was a driving enthusiast, he might have both an intrinsic and an instrumental desire to drive to the cinema. Instrumental desires are usually about causal means to bring the object of another desire about.[1][3] Driving to the cinema, for example, is one of the causal requirements for watching the movie there. But there are also constitutive means besides causal means.[13] Constitutive means are not causes but ways of doing something. Watching the movie while sitting in seat 13F, for example, is one way of watching the movie, but not an antecedent cause. Desires corresponding to constitutive means are sometimes termed «realizer desires».[1][3]
Occurrent and standing[edit]
Occurrent desires are desires that are currently active.[11] They are either conscious or at least have unconscious effects, for example, on the subject’s reasoning or behavior.[14] Desires we engage in and try to realize are occurrent.[1] But we have many desires that are not relevant to our present situation and do not influence us currently. Such desires are called standing or dispositional.[11][14] They exist somewhere in the back of our minds and are different from not desiring at all despite lacking causal effects at the moment.[1] If Dhanvi is busy convincing her friend to go hiking this weekend, for example, then her desire to go hiking is occurrent. But many of her other desires, like to sell her old car or to talk with her boss about a promotion, are merely standing during this conversation. Standing desires remain part of the mind even while the subject is sound asleep.[11] It has been questioned whether standing desires should be considered desires at all in a strict sense. One motivation for raising this doubt is that desires are attitudes toward contents but a disposition to have a certain attitude is not automatically an attitude itself.[15] Desires can be occurrent even if they do not influence our behavior. This is the case, for example, if the agent has a conscious desire to do something but successfully resists it. This desire is occurrent because it plays some role in the agents mental life, even if it is not action-guiding.[1]
Propositional desires and object-desires[edit]
The dominant view is that all desires are to be understood as propositional attitudes.[4] But a contrasting view allows that at least some desires are directed not at propositions or possible states of affairs but directly at objects.[1][12] This difference is also reflected on a linguistic level. Object-desires can be expressed through a direct object, for example, Louis desires an omelet.[1] Propositional desires, on the other hand, are usually expressed through a that-clause, for example, Arielle desires that she has an omelet for breakfast.[16] Propositionalist theories hold that direct-object-expressions are just a short form for that-clause-expressions while object-desire-theorists contend that they correspond to a different form of desire.[1] One argument in favor of the latter position is that talk of object-desire is very common and natural in everyday language. But one important objection to this view is that object-desires lack proper conditions of satisfaction necessary for desires.[1][12] Conditions of satisfaction determine under which situations a desire is satisfied.[17] Arielle’s desire is satisfied if the that-clause expressing her desire has been realized, i.e. she is having an omelet for breakfast. But Louis’s desire is not satisfied by the mere existence of omelets nor by his coming into possession of an omelet at some indeterminate point in his life. So it seems that, when pressed for the details, object-desire-theorists have to resort to propositional expressions to articulate what exactly these desires entail. This threatens to collapse object-desires into propositional desires.[1][12]
Higher and lower[edit]
In religion and philosophy, a distinction is sometimes made between higher and lower desires. Higher desires are commonly associated with spiritual or religious goals in contrast to lower desires, sometimes termed passions, which are concerned with bodily or sensory pleasures. This difference is closely related to John Stuart Mill’s distinction between the higher pleasures of the mind and the lower pleasures of the body.[18] In some religions, all desires are outright rejected as a negative influence on our well-being. The second Noble Truth in Buddhism, for example, states that desiring is the cause of all suffering.[19] A related doctrine is also found in the Hindu tradition of karma yoga, which recommends that we act without a desire for the fruits of our actions, referred to as «Nishkam Karma».[20][21] But other strands in Hinduism explicitly distinguish lower or bad desires for worldly things from higher or good desires for closeness or oneness with God. This distinction is found, for example, in the Bhagavad Gita or in the tradition of bhakti yoga.[20][22] A similar line of thought is present in the teachings of Christianity. In the doctrine of the seven deadly sins, for example, various vices are listed, which have been defined as perverse or corrupt versions of love. Explicit reference to bad forms of desiring is found, for example, in the sins of lust, gluttony and greed.[5][23] The seven sins are contrasted with the seven virtues, which include the corresponding positive counterparts.[24] A desire for God is explicitly encouraged in various doctrines.[25] Existentialists sometimes distinguish between authentic and inauthentic desires. Authentic desires express what the agent truly wants from deep within. An agent wants something inauthentically, on the other hand, if the agent is not fully identified with this desire, despite having it.[26]
Roles[edit]
Desire is a quite fundamental concept. As such, it is relevant for many different fields. Various definitions and theories of other concepts have been expressed in terms of desires. Actions depend on desires and moral praiseworthiness is sometimes defined in terms of being motivated by the right desire.[1] A popular contemporary approach defines value as that which it is fitting to desire.[27] Desire-satisfaction theories of well-being state that a person’s well-being is determined by whether that person’s desires are satisfied.[28] It has been suggested that to prefer one thing to another is just to have a stronger desire for the former thing.[29] An influential theory of personhood holds that only entities with higher-order desires can be persons.[30]
Action, practical reasons and morality[edit]
Desires play a central role in actions as what motivates them. It is usually held that a desire by itself is not sufficient: it has to be combined with a belief that the action in question would contribute to the fulfillment of the desire.[31] The notion of practical reasons is closely related to motivation and desire. Some philosophers, often from a Humean tradition, simply identify an agent’s desires with the practical reasons he has. A closely related view holds that desires are not reasons themselves but present reasons to the agent.[1] A strength of these positions is that they can give a straightforward explanation of how practical reasons can act as motivation. But an important objection is that we may have reasons to do things without a desire to do them.[1] This is especially relevant in the field of morality. Peter Singer, for example, suggests that most people living in developed countries have a moral obligation to donate a significant portion of their income to charities.[32][33] Such an obligation would constitute a practical reason to act accordingly even for people who feel no desire to do so.
A closely related issue in morality asks not what reasons we have but for what reasons we act. This idea goes back to Immanuel Kant, who holds that doing the right thing is not sufficient from the moral perspective. Instead, we have to do the right thing for the right reason.[34] He refers to this distinction as the difference between legality (Legalität), i.e. acting in accordance with outer norms, and morality (Moralität), i.e. being motivated by the right inward attitude.[35][36] On this view, donating a significant portion of one’s income to charities is not a moral action if the motivating desire is to improve one’s reputation by convincing other people of one’s wealth and generosity. Instead, from a Kantian perspective, it should be performed out of a desire to do one’s duty. These issues are often discussed in contemporary philosophy under the terms of moral praiseworthiness and blameworthiness. One important position in this field is that the praiseworthiness of an action depends on the desire motivating this action.[1][37]
Value and well-being[edit]
It is common in axiology to define value in relation to desire. Such approaches fall under the category of fitting-attitude theories. According to them, an object is valuable if it is fitting to desire this object or if we ought to desire it.[27][38] This is sometimes expressed by saying that the object is desirable, appropriately desired or worthy of desire. Two important aspects of this type of position are that it reduces values to deontic notions, or what we ought to feel, and that it makes values dependent on human responses and attitudes.[27][38][39] Despite their popularity, fitting-attitude theories of value face various theoretical objections. An often-cited one is the wrong kind of reason problem, which is based on the consideration that facts independent of the value of an object may affect whether this object ought to be desired.[27][38] In one thought experiment, an evil demon threatens the agent to kill her family unless she desires him. In such a situation, it is fitting for the agent to desire the demon in order to save her family, despite the fact that the demon does not possess positive value.[27][38]
Well-being is usually considered a special type of value: the well-being of a person is what is ultimately good for this person.[40] Desire-satisfaction theories are among the major theories of well-being. They state that a person’s well-being is determined by whether that person’s desires are satisfied: the higher the number of satisfied desires, the higher the well-being.[28] One problem for some versions of desire theory is that not all desires are good: some desires may even have terrible consequences for the agent. Desire theorists have tried to avoid this objection by holding that what matters are not actual desires but the desires the agent would have if she was fully informed.[28][41]
Preferences[edit]
Desires and preferences are two closely related notions: they are both conative states that determine our behavior.[29] The difference between the two is that desires are directed at one object while preferences concern a comparison between two alternatives, of which one is preferred to the other.[4][29] The focus on preferences instead of desires is very common in the field of decision theory. It has been argued that desire is the more fundamental notion and that preferences are to be defined in terms of desires.[1][4][29] For this to work, desire has to be understood as involving a degree or intensity. Given this assumption, a preference can be defined as a comparison of two desires.[1] That Nadia prefers tea over coffee, for example, just means that her desire for tea is stronger than her desire for coffee. One argument for this approach is due to considerations of parsimony: a great number of preferences can be derived from a very small number of desires.[1][29] One objection to this theory is that our introspective access is much more immediate in cases of preferences than in cases of desires. So it is usually much easier for us to know which of two options we prefer than to know the degree with which we desire a particular object. This consideration has been used to suggest that maybe preference, and not desire, is the more fundamental notion.[1]
Persons, personhood and higher-order desires[edit]
Personhood is what persons have. There are various theories about what constitutes personhood. Most agree that being a person has to do with having certain mental abilities and is connected to having a certain moral and legal status.[42][43][44] An influential theory of persons is due to Harry Frankfurt. He defines persons in terms of higher-order desires.[30][45][46] Many of the desires we have, like the desire to have ice cream or to take a vacation, are first-order desires. Higher-order desires, on the other hand, are desires about other desires. They are most prominent in cases where a person has a desire he does not want to have.[30][45][46] A recovering addict, for example, may have both a first-order desire to take drugs and a second-order desire of not following this first-order desire.[30][45] Or a religious ascetic may still have sexual desires while at the same time wanting to be free of these desires. According to Frankfurt, having second-order volitions, i.e. second-order desires about which first-order desires are followed, is the mark of personhood. It is a form of caring about oneself, of being concerned with who one is and what one does. Not all entities with a mind have higher-order volitions. Frankfurt terms them «wantons» in contrast to «persons». On his view, animals and maybe also some human beings are wantons.[30][45][46]
Formation[edit]
Both psychology and philosophy are interested in where desires come from or how they form. An important distinction for this investigation is between intrinsic desires, i.e. what the subject wants for its own sake, and instrumental desires, i.e. what the subject wants for the sake of something else.[2][3] Instrumental desires depend for their formation and existence on other desires.[9] For example, Aisha has a desire to find a charging station at the airport. This desire is instrumental because it is based on another desire: to keep her mobile phone from dying. Without the latter desire, the former would not have come into existence.[1] As an additional requirement, a possibly unconscious belief or judgment is necessary to the effect that the fulfillment of the instrumental desire would somehow contribute to the fulfillment of the desire it is based on.[9] Instrumental desires usually pass away after the desires they are based on cease to exist.[1] But defective cases are possible where, often due to absentmindedness, the instrumental desire remains. Such cases are sometimes termed «motivational inertia».[9] Something like this might be the case when the agent finds himself with a desire to go to the kitchen, only to realize upon arriving that he does not know what he wants there.[9]
Intrinsic desires, on the other hand, do not depend on other desires.[9] Some authors hold that all or at least some intrinsic desires are inborn or innate, for example, desires for pleasure or for nutrition.[1] But other authors suggest that even these relatively basic desires may depend to some extent on experience: before we can desire a pleasurable object, we have to learn, through a hedonic experience of this object for example, that it is pleasurable.[47] But it is also conceivable that reason by itself generates intrinsic desires. On this view, reasoning to the conclusion that it would be rational to have a certain intrinsic desire causes the subject to have this desire.[1][4] It has also been proposed that instrumental desires may be transformed into intrinsic desires under the right conditions. This could be possible through processes of reward-based learning.[3] The idea is that whatever reliably predicts the fulfillment of intrinsic desires may itself become the object of an intrinsic desire. So a baby may initially only instrumentally desire its mother because of the warmth, hugs and milk she provides. But over time, this instrumental desire may become an intrinsic desire.[3]
The death-of-desire thesis holds that desires cannot continue to exist once their object is realized.[8] This would mean that an agent cannot desire to have something if he believes that he already has it.[48] One objection to the death-of-desire thesis comes from the fact that our preferences usually do not change upon desire-satisfaction.[8] So if Samuel prefers to wear dry clothes rather than wet clothes, he would continue to hold this preference even after having come home from a rainy day and having changed his clothes. This would indicate against the death-of-desire thesis that no change on the level of the agent’s conative states takes place.[8]
Philosophy[edit]
In philosophy, desire has been identified as a philosophical problem since Antiquity. In The Republic, Plato argues that individual desires must be postponed in the name of the higher ideal. In De Anima, Aristotle claims that desire is implicated in animal interactions and the propensity of animals to motion; at the same time, he acknowledges that reasoning also interacts with desire.
Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679) proposed the concept of psychological hedonism, which asserts that the «fundamental motivation of all human action is the desire for pleasure.» Baruch Spinoza (1632–1677) had a view which contrasted with Hobbes, in that «he saw natural desires as a form of bondage» that are not chosen by a person of their own free will. David Hume (1711–1776) claimed that desires and passions are non-cognitive, automatic bodily responses, and he argued that reasoning is «capable only of devising means to ends set by [bodily] desire».[49]
Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) called any action based on desires a hypothetical imperative, which means they are a command of reason, applying only if one desires the goal in question.[50] Kant also established a relation between the beautiful and pleasure in Critique of Judgment. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel claimed that «self-consciousness is desire».
Because desire can cause humans to become obsessed and embittered, it has been called one of the causes of woe for mankind.[51]
Religion[edit]
Buddhism[edit]
In Buddhism, craving (see taṇhā) is thought to be the cause of all suffering that one experiences in human existence. The eradication of craving leads one to ultimate happiness, or Nirvana. However, desire for wholesome things is seen as liberating and enhancing.[52] While the stream of desire for sense-pleasures must be cut eventually, a practitioner on the path to liberation is encouraged by the Buddha to «generate desire» for the fostering of skillful qualities and the abandoning of unskillful ones.[53]
For an individual to effect his or her liberation, the flow of sense-desire must be cut completely; however, while training, he or she must work with motivational processes based on skillfully applied desire.[54] According to the early Buddhist scriptures, the Buddha stated that monks should «generate desire» for the sake of fostering skillful qualities and abandoning unskillful ones.[53]
Christianity[edit]
Within Christianity, desire is seen as something that can either lead a person towards God or away from him. Desire is not considered to be a bad thing in and of itself; rather, it is a powerful force within the human that, once submitted to the Lordship of Christ, can become a tool for good, for advancement, and for abundant living.
Hinduism[edit]
In Hinduism, the Rig Veda’s creation myth Nasadiya Sukta states regarding the one (ekam) spirit: «In the beginning there was Desire (kama) that was first seed of mind. Poets found the bond of being in non-being in their heart’s thought».
Psychology[edit]
Neuropsychology[edit]
While desires are often classified as emotions by laypersons, psychologists often describe desires as ur-emotions, or feelings that do not quite fit the category of basic emotions.[55] For psychologists, desires arise from bodily structures and functions (e.g., the stomach needing food and the blood needing oxygen). On the other hand, emotions arise from a person’s mental state. A 2008 study by the University of Michigan indicated that, while humans experience desire and fear as psychological opposites, they share the same brain circuit.[56] A 2008 study entitled «The Neural Correlates of Desire» showed that the human brain categorizes stimuli according to its desirability by activating three different brain areas: the superior orbitofrontal cortex, the mid-cingulate cortex, and the anterior cingulate cortex.[57][non-primary source needed]
In affective neuroscience, «desire» and «wanting» are operationally defined as motivational salience;[58][59] the form of «desire» or «wanting» associated with a rewarding stimulus (i.e., a stimulus which acts as a positive reinforcer, such as palatable food, an attractive mate, or an addictive drug) is called «incentive salience» and research has demonstrated that incentive salience, the sensation of pleasure, and positive reinforcement are all derived from neuronal activity within the reward system.[58][60][61] Studies have shown that dopamine signaling in the nucleus accumbens shell and endogenous opioid signaling in the ventral pallidum are at least partially responsible for mediating an individual’s desire (i.e., incentive salience) for a rewarding stimulus and the subjective perception of pleasure derived from experiencing or «consuming» a rewarding stimulus (e.g., pleasure derived from eating palatable food, sexual pleasure from intercourse with an attractive mate, or euphoria from using an addictive drug).[59][60][61][62][63][64] Research also shows that the orbitofrontal cortex has connections to both the opioid and dopamine systems, and stimulating this cortex is associated with subjective reports of pleasure.[65]
Psychoanalysis[edit]
Austrian psychiatrist Sigmund Freud, who is best known for his theories of the unconscious mind and the defense mechanism of repression and for creating the clinical practice of psychoanalysis, proposed the notion of the Oedipus complex, which argues that desire for the mother creates neuroses in their sons. Freud used the Greek myth of Oedipus to argue that people desire incest and must repress that desire. He claimed that children pass through several stages, including a stage in which they fixate on the mother as a sexual object.
That this «complex» is universal has long since been disputed. Even if it were true, that would not explain those neuroses in daughters, but only in sons. While it is true that sexual confusion can be aberrative in a few cases, there is no credible evidence to suggest that it is a universal scenario. While Freud was correct in labeling the various symptoms behind most compulsions, phobias and disorders, he was largely incorrect in his theories regarding the etiology of what he identified.[66]
French psychoanalyst and psychiatrist Jacques Lacan (1901–1981) argues that desire first occurs during a «mirror phase» of a baby’s development, when the baby sees an image of wholeness in a mirror which gives them a desire for that being. As a person matures, Lacan claims that they still feel separated from themselves by language, which is incomplete, and so a person continually strives to become whole. He uses the term «jouissance» to refer to the lost object or feeling of absence (see manque) which a person believes to be unobtainable.[67] Gilles Deleuze rejects the idea, defended by Lacan and other psychoanalysts, that desire is a form of lack related to incompleteness or a lost object. Instead, he holds that it should be understood as a positive reality in the form of an affirmative vital force.[68][69]
Marketing[edit]
In the field of marketing, desire is the human appetite for a given object of attention. Desire for a product is stimulated by advertising, which attempts to give buyers a sense of lack or wanting. In store retailing, merchants attempt to increase the desire of the buyer by showcasing the product attractively, in the case of clothes or jewellery, or, for food stores, by offering samples. With print, TV, and radio advertising, desire is created by giving the potential buyer a sense of lacking («Are you still driving that old car?») or by associating the product with desirable attributes, either by showing a celebrity using or wearing the product, or by giving the product a «halo effect» by showing attractive models with the product. Nike’s «Just Do It» ads for sports shoes are appealing to consumers’ desires for self-betterment.
In some cases, the potential buyer already has the desire for the product before they enter the store, as in the case of a decorating buff entering their favorite furniture store. The role of the salespeople in these cases is simply to guide the customer towards making a choice; they do not have to try to «sell» the general idea of making a purchase, because the customer already wants the products. In other cases, the potential buyer does not have a desire for the product or service, and so the company has to create the sense of desire. An example of this situation is for life insurance. Most young adults are not thinking about dying, so they are not naturally thinking about how they need to have accidental death insurance. Life insurance companies, though, are attempting to create a desire for life insurance with advertising that shows pictures of children and asks «If anything happens to you, who will pay for the children’s upkeep?».[citation needed]
Marketing theorists call desire the third stage in the hierarchy of effects, which occurs when the buyer develops a sense that if they felt the need for the type of product in question, the advertised product is what would quench their desire.[70]
Artworks[edit]
Texts[edit]
The theme of desire is at the core of the written fictions, especially romance novels. Novels which are based around the theme of desire, which can range from a long aching feeling to an unstoppable torrent, include Madame Bovary by Gustave Flaubert; Love in the Time of Cholera by Gabriel Garcia Marquez; Lolita by Vladimir Nabokov; Jane Eyre by Charlotte Brontë, and Dracula by Bram Stoker. Brontë’s characterization of Jane Eyre depicts her as torn by an inner conflict between reason and desire, because «customs» and «conventionalities» stand in the way of her romantic desires.[71] E.M. Forster’s novels use homoerotic codes to describe same-sex desire and longing. Close male friendships with subtle homoerotic undercurrents occur in every novel, which subverts the conventional, heterosexual plot of the novels.[72] In the Gothic-themed Dracula, Stoker depicts the theme of desire which is coupled with fear. When the character Lucy is seduced by Dracula, she describes her sensations in the graveyard as a mixture of fear and blissful emotion.
Poet W.B. Yeats depicts the positive and negative aspects of desire in his poems such as «The Rose for the World», «Adam’s Curse», «No Second Troy», «All Things can Tempt me», and «Meditations in Time of Civil War». Some poems depict desire as a poison for the soul; Yeats worked through his desire for his beloved, Maud Gonne, and realized that «Our longing, our craving, our thirsting for something other than Reality is what dissatisfies us». In «The Rose for the World», he admires her beauty, but feels pain because he cannot be with her. In the poem «No Second Troy», Yeats overflows with anger and bitterness because of their unrequited love.[73] Poet T. S. Eliot dealt with the themes of desire and homoeroticism in his poetry, prose and drama.[74] Other poems on the theme of desire include John Donne’s poem «To His Mistress Going to Bed», Carol Ann Duffy’s longings in «Warming Her Pearls»; Ted Hughes’ «Lovesong» about the savage intensity of desire; and Wendy Cope’s humorous poem «Song».
Philippe Borgeaud’s novels analyse how emotions such as erotic desire and seduction are connected to fear and wrath by examining cases where people are worried about issues of impurity, sin, and shame.
Films[edit]
Just as desire is central to the written fiction genre of romance, it is the central theme of melodrama films, which are a subgenre of the drama film. Like drama, a melodrama depends mostly on in-depth character development, interaction, and highly emotional themes. Melodramatic films tend to use plots that appeal to the heightened emotions of the audience. Melodramatic plots often deal with «crises of human emotion, failed romance or friendship, strained familial situations, tragedy, illness, neuroses, or emotional and physical hardship.» Film critics sometimes use the term «pejoratively to connote an unrealistic, bathos-filled, campy tale of romance or domestic situations with stereotypical characters (often including a central female character) that would directly appeal to feminine audiences.»[75] Also called «women’s movies», «weepies», tearjerkers, or «chick flicks».
«Melodrama… is Hollywood’s fairly consistent way of treating desire and subject identity», as can be seen in well-known films such as Gone with the Wind, in which «desire is the driving force for both Scarlett and the hero, Rhett». Scarlett desires love, money, the attention of men, and the vision of being a virtuous «true lady». Rhett Butler desires to be with Scarlett, which builds to a burning longing that is ultimately his undoing, because Scarlett keeps refusing his advances; when she finally confesses her secret desire, Rhett is worn out and his longing is spent.
In Cathy Cupitt’s article on «Desire and Vision in Blade Runner», she argues that film, as a «visual narrative form, plays with the voyeuristic desires of its audience». Focusing on the dystopian 1980s science fiction film Blade Runner, she calls the film an «Object of Visual Desire», in which it plays to an «expectation of an audience’s delight in visual texture, with the ‘retro-fitted’ spectacle of the post-modern city to ogle» and with the use of the «motif of the ‘eye'». In the film, «desire is a key motivating influence on the narrative of the film, both in the ‘real world’, and within the text.»[76]
See also[edit]
- Affect
- Feeling
- Impulse (psychology)
- Motivation
- Saudade
- Taṇhā
- Trishna (Vedic thought)
- Valence (psychology)
References[edit]
- ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z aa ab ac ad ae af ag ah ai aj ak al am an ao Schroeder, Tim (2020). «Desire». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 3 May 2021.
- ^ a b c d e f Honderich, Ted (2005). «desire». The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
- ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s Schroeder, Timothy (2010). «Desire: philosophical issues». WIREs Cognitive Science. 1 (3): 363–370. doi:10.1002/wcs.3. ISSN 1939-5086. PMID 26271376.
- ^ a b c d e f g h i j Pettit, Philip. «Desire — Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy». www.rep.routledge.com. Retrieved 4 May 2021.
- ^ a b Sandkühler, Hans Jörg (2010). «Begehren/Begierde». Enzyklopädie Philosophie. Meiner. Archived from the original on 2021-03-11. Retrieved 2021-05-04.
- ^ Mele, Alfred R. (2003). «7. Motivational Strength». Motivation and Agency. Oxford University Press.
- ^ a b Swinburne, Richard (1985). «Desire». Philosophy. 60 (234): 429–445. doi:10.1017/S0031819100042492. S2CID 239303542.
- ^ a b c d e Oddie, Graham. «Desire and the Good: In Search of the Right Fit». The Nature of Desire. Oxford University Press.
- ^ a b c d e f g h Audi, Robert (2001). «3. Action, Belief, and Desire». The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and Substance of Rationality. Oxford University Press.
- ^ Bradley, Richard; Stefansson, H. Orii (2016). «Desire, Expectation, and Invariance». Mind. 125 (499): 691–725. doi:10.1093/mind/fzv200.
- ^ a b c d Strandberg, Caj (2012). «Expressivism and Dispositional Desires: 2. a distinction in mind». American Philosophical Quarterly. 49 (1): 81–91.
- ^ a b c d Lycan, William G. (2012). «Desire Considered as a Propositional Attitude». Philosophical Perspectives. 26 (1): 201–215. doi:10.1111/phpe.12003.
- ^ Audi, Robert (2001). «4. The Sources of Practical Reasons». The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and Substance of Rationality. Oxford University Press.
- ^ a b Bartlett, Gary (2018). «Occurrent States». Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 48 (1): 1–17. doi:10.1080/00455091.2017.1323531. S2CID 220316213.
- ^ Mele, Alfred R. (2003). «1. Motivation and Desire». Motivation and Agency. Oxford University Press.
- ^ Nelson, Michael (2019). «Propositional Attitude Reports». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 4 May 2021.
- ^ Siewert, Charles (2017). «Consciousness and Intentionality: 2. The Interpretation of «Intentionality»«. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 4 May 2021.
- ^ Heydt, Colin. «John Stuart Mill: ii. Basic Argument». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 3 February 2021.
- ^ Shulman, Eviatar (2014). «1. The Structural Relationship between Philosophy and Meditation». Rethinking the Buddha: Early Buddhist Philosophy as Meditative Perception. Cambridge University Press.
- ^ a b Framarin, Christopher G. (2007). «Good and Bad Desires: Implications of the Dialogue Between Ka and Arjuna». International Journal of Hindu Studies. 11 (2): 147–170. doi:10.1007/s11407-007-9046-4. S2CID 145772857.
- ^ Sri Aurobindo (1948). «Self-Surrender in Works — The Way of the Gita». The Synthesis of Yoga. Madras, Sri Aurobindo Library.
- ^ Sri Aurobindo (1948). «The Motives of Devotion». The Synthesis of Yoga. Madras, Sri Aurobindo Library.
- ^ «Catechism of the Catholic Church: 1866, 1871». www.vatican.va. Retrieved 6 May 2021.
- ^ «Virtue in Christianity». Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 6 May 2021.
- ^ «Catechism of the Catholic Church: 27». www.vatican.va.
- ^ Varga, Somogy; Guignon, Charles (2020). «Authenticity». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
- ^ a b c d e Jacobson, Daniel (2011). «Fitting Attitude Theories of Value». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 5 May 2021.
- ^ a b c Crisp, Roger (2017). «Well-Being: 4.2 Desire Theories». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 5 May 2021.
- ^ a b c d e Schulz, Armin W. (2015). «Preferences Vs. Desires: Debating the Fundamental Structure of Conative States». Economics and Philosophy. 31 (2): 239–257. doi:10.1017/S0266267115000115. S2CID 155414997.
- ^ a b c d e Frankfurt, Harry G. (1971). «Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person» (PDF). Journal of Philosophy. 68 (1): 5–20. doi:10.2307/2024717. JSTOR 2024717.
- ^ Wilson, George; Shpall, Samuel (2016). «Action». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 5 May 2021.
- ^ Singer, Peter (2016). «The Most Good You Can Do: A Response to the Commentaries». Journal of Global Ethics. 12 (2): 161–169. doi:10.1080/17449626.2016.1191523. S2CID 151903760.
- ^ Kanygina, Yuliya (2011). «Introduction». The Demandingness Objection to Peter Singer’s Account of Our Obligations to the World’s Poor. Budapest, Hungary: Central European University.
- ^ Johnson, Robert; Cureton, Adam (2021). «Kant’s Moral Philosophy: 2. Good Will, Moral Worth and Duty». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 5 May 2021.
- ^ Weigelin, Ernst (1917). «Legalität und Moralität». Archiv für Rechts- und Wirtschaftsphilosophie. 10 (4): 367–376. ISSN 0177-1108. JSTOR 23683644.
- ^ Zaczyk, Rainer (2006). «Einheit des Grundes, Grund der Differenz von Moralität und Legalität». Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik. 14: 311–321. ISSN 0944-4610. JSTOR 43593317.
- ^ Talbert, Matthew (2019). «Moral Responsibility». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 5 May 2021.
- ^ a b c d Schroeder, Mark (2021). «Value Theory». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 5 May 2021.
- ^ Zimmerman, Michal J. (2015). «1. Value and Normativity». The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press USA.
- ^ Sumner, L. W. (2005). «Happiness». Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Macmillan Reference.
- ^ Heathwood, Chris (2005). Desire-Satisfaction Theories of Welfare (PhD Thesis). Scholarworks@Umass Amherst.
- ^ Craig, Edward (1996). «Persons». Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge.
- ^ Sandkühler, Hans Jörg (2010). «Person/Persönlichkeit». Enzyklopädie Philosophie. Meiner. Archived from the original on 2021-03-11. Retrieved 2021-05-04.
- ^ Borchert, Donald (2006). «Persons». Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan.
- ^ a b c d Vezér, Martin Alexander (2007). «On the Concept of Personhood: A Comparative Analysis of Three Accounts». LYCEUM. IX (1).
- ^ a b c Norris, Christopher (2010). «Frankfurt on Second-Order Desires and the Concept of a Person». Prolegomena. 9 (2): 199–242.
- ^ Audi, Robert (2011). Rationality and Religious Commitment. Oxford University Press. p. 20.
- ^ Lauria, Federico (2017). «The «Guise of the Ought to Be»: A Deontic View of the Intentionality of Desire». The Nature of Desire. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 352.
- ^ Ethics Chapter. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy CD-ROM, V. 1.0, London: Routledge Edward Craig (ed). «Morality and emotions». By Martha C. Nussbaum
- ^ «desire — behaviour». Encyclopædia Britannica.
- ^ Hagen, Steve. Buddhism Plain and Simple. New York: Broadway Books, 1997.
- ^ Charles S. Prebish, and Damien Keown, Buddhism — the EBook. Journal of Buddhist Ethics Online Books, 2005, page 83.
- ^ a b Thanissaro Bhikkhu, «The Wings to Awakening».
- ^ Steven Collins, Selfless Persons: Thought and Imagery in Theravada Buddhism. Cambridge University Press, 1982, page 251: «In the end, the flowing streams of sense-desire must be ‘cut’ or ‘crossed’ completely; nevertheless, for the duration of the Path, a monk must perforce work with motivational and perceptual processes as they ordinarily are, that is to say, based on desire … Thus, during mental training, the stream is not to be ‘cut’ immediately, but guided, like water along viaducts. The meditative steadying of the mind by counting in- and out-breaths (in the mindfulness of breathing) is compared to the steadying of a boat in ‘a fierce current’ by its rudder. The disturbance of the flow of a mountain stream by irrigation channels cut into its sides it used to illustrate the weakening of insight by the five ‘hindrances’.»
- ^ Berridge, Kent C. (2018). «Evolving Concepts of Emotion and Motivation». Frontiers in Psychology. 9: 1647. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2018.01647. ISSN 1664-1078. PMC 6137142. PMID 30245654.
- ^ «Changing stress levels can make brain flip from ‘desire’ to ‘dread‘«. Mar. 19, 2008
http://www.ns.umich.edu/htdocs/releases/story.php?id=6419 - ^ Kawabata H, Zeki S (2008). «The Neural Correlates of Desire». PLOS ONE. 3 (8): e3027. Bibcode:2008PLoSO…3.3027K. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.274.6152. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0003027. PMC 2518616. PMID 18728753. S2CID 3290147.
- ^ a b Schultz W (2015). «Neuronal reward and decision signals: from theories to data». Physiological Reviews. 95 (3): 853–951. doi:10.1152/physrev.00023.2014. PMC 4491543. PMID 26109341.
Rewards in operant conditioning are positive reinforcers. … Operant behavior gives a good definition for rewards. Anything that makes an individual come back for more is a positive reinforcer and therefore a reward. Although it provides a good definition, positive reinforcement is only one of several reward functions. … Rewards are attractive. They are motivating and make us exert an effort. … Rewards induce approach behavior, also called appetitive or preparatory behavior, and consummatory behavior. … Thus any stimulus, object, event, activity, or situation that has the potential to make us approach and consume it is by definition a reward. … Rewarding stimuli, objects, events, situations, and activities consist of several major components. First, rewards have basic sensory components (visual, auditory, somatosensory, gustatory, and olfactory) … Second, rewards are salient and thus elicit attention, which are manifested as orienting responses (FIGURE 1, middle). The salience of rewards derives from three principal factors, namely, their physical intensity and impact (physical salience), their novelty and surprise (novelty/surprise salience), and their general motivational impact shared with punishers (motivational salience). A separate form not included in this scheme, incentive salience, primarily addresses dopamine function in addiction and refers only to approach behavior (as opposed to learning) … These emotions are also called liking (for pleasure) and wanting (for desire) in addiction research (471) and strongly support the learning and approach generating functions of reward.
- ^ a b Malenka RC, Nestler EJ, Hyman SE (2009). Sydor A, Brown RY (eds.). Molecular Neuropharmacology: A Foundation for Clinical Neuroscience (2nd ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill Medical. pp. 147–148, 367, 376. ISBN 978-0-07-148127-4.
VTA DA neurons play a critical role in motivation, reward-related behavior (Chapter 15), attention, and multiple forms of memory. This organization of the DA system, wide projection from a limited number of cell bodies, permits coordinated responses to potent new rewards. Thus, acting in diverse terminal fields, dopamine confers motivational salience («wanting») on the reward itself or associated cues (nucleus accumbens shell region), updates the value placed on different goals in light of this new experience (orbital prefrontal cortex), helps consolidate multiple forms of memory (amygdala and hippocampus), and encodes new motor programs that will facilitate obtaining this reward in the future (nucleus accumbens core region and dorsal striatum). In this example, dopamine modulates the processing of sensorimotor information in diverse neural circuits to maximize the ability of the organism to obtain future rewards.
- ^ a b Malenka RC, Nestler EJ, Hyman SE (2009). «Chapter 15: Reinforcement and Addictive Disorders». In Sydor A, Brown RY (eds.). Molecular Neuropharmacology: A Foundation for Clinical Neuroscience (2nd ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill Medical. pp. 365–366, 376. ISBN 9780071481274.
The neural substrates that underlie the perception of reward and the phenomenon of positive reinforcement are a set of interconnected forebrain structures called brain reward pathways; these include the nucleus accumbens (NAc; the major component of the ventral striatum), the basal forebrain (components of which have been termed the extended amygdala, as discussed later in this chapter), hippocampus, hypothalamus, and frontal regions of cerebral cortex. These structures receive rich dopaminergic innervation from the ventral tegmental area (VTA) of the midbrain. Addictive drugs are rewarding and reinforcing because they act in brain reward pathways to enhance either dopamine release or the effects of dopamine in the NAc or related structures, or because they produce effects similar to dopamine. … A macrostructure postulated to integrate many of the functions of this circuit is described by some investigators as the extended amygdala. The extended amygdala is said to comprise several basal forebrain structures that share similar morphology, immunocytochemical features, and connectivity and that are well suited to mediating aspects of reward function; these include the bed nucleus of the stria terminalis, the central medial amygdala, the shell of the NAc, and the sublenticular substantia innominata.
- ^ a b Berridge KC, Kringelbach ML (May 2015). «Pleasure systems in the brain». Neuron. 86 (3): 646–664. doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2015.02.018. PMC 4425246. PMID 25950633.
In the prefrontal cortex, recent evidence indicates that the OFC and insula cortex may each contain their own additional hot spots (D.C. Castro et al., Soc. Neurosci., abstract). In specific subregions of each area, either opioid-stimulating or orexin-stimulating microinjections appear to enhance the number of liking reactions elicited by sweetness, similar to the NAc and VP hot spots. Successful confirmation of hedonic hot spots in the OFC or insula would be important and possibly relevant to the orbitofrontal mid-anterior site mentioned earlier that especially tracks the subjective pleasure of foods in humans (Georgiadis et al., 2012; Kringelbach, 2005; Kringelbach et al., 2003; Small et al., 2001; Veldhuizen et al., 2010). Finally, in the brainstem, a hindbrain site near the parabrachial nucleus of dorsal pons also appears able to contribute to hedonic gains of function (Söderpalm and Berridge, 2000). A brainstem mechanism for pleasure may seem more surprising than forebrain hot spots to anyone who views the brainstem as merely reflexive, but the pontine parabrachial nucleus contributes to taste, pain, and many visceral sensations from the body and has also been suggested to play an important role in motivation (Wu et al., 2012) and in human emotion (especially related to the somatic marker hypothesis) (Damasio, 2010).
- ^ Kringelbach ML, Berridge KC (2013). «The Joyful Mind». From Abuse to Recovery: Understanding Addiction. Macmillan. pp. 199–207. ISBN 9781466842557. Retrieved 8 April 2016.
So it makes sense that the real pleasure centers in the brain—those directly responsible for generating pleasurable sensations—turn out to lie within some of the structures previously identified as part of the reward circuit. One of these so-called hedonic hotspots lies in a subregion of the nucleus accumbens called the medial shell. A second is found within the ventral pallidum, a deep-seated structure near the base of the forebrain that receives most of its signals from the nucleus accumbens. … On the other hand, intense euphoria is harder to come by than everyday pleasures. The reason may be that strong enhancement of pleasure—like the chemically induced pleasure bump we produced in lab animals—seems to require activation of the entire network at once. Defection of any single component dampens the high.
- ^ Grall-Bronnec M, Sauvaget A (2014). «The use of repetitive transcranial magnetic stimulation for modulating craving and addictive behaviours: a critical literature review of efficacy, technical and methodological considerations». Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 47: 592–613. doi:10.1016/j.neubiorev.2014.10.013. PMID 25454360.
Studies have shown that cravings are underpinned by activation of the reward and motivation circuits (McBride et al., 2006, Wang et al., 2007, Wing et al., 2012, Goldman et al., 2013, Jansen et al., 2013 and Volkow et al., 2013). According to these authors, the main neural structures involved are: the nucleus accumbens, dorsal striatum, orbitofrontal cortex, anterior cingulate cortex, dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (DLPFC), amygdala, hippocampus and insula.
- ^ Koob GF, Volkow ND (August 2016). «Neurobiology of addiction: a neurocircuitry analysis». Lancet Psychiatry. 3 (8): 760–773. doi:10.1016/S2215-0366(16)00104-8. PMC 6135092. PMID 27475769.
Drug addiction represents a dramatic dysregulation of motivational circuits that is caused by a combination of exaggerated incentive salience and habit formation, reward deficits and stress surfeits, and compromised executive function in three stages. The rewarding effects of drugs of abuse, development of incentive salience, and development of drug-seeking habits in the binge/intoxication stage involve changes in dopamine and opioid peptides in the basal ganglia. The increases in negative emotional states and dysphoric and stress-like responses in the withdrawal/negative affect stage involve decreases in the function of the dopamine component of the reward system and recruitment of brain stress neurotransmitters, such as corticotropin-releasing factor and dynorphin, in the neurocircuitry of the extended amygdala. The craving and deficits in executive function in the so-called preoccupation/anticipation stage involve the dysregulation of key afferent projections from the prefrontal cortex and insula, including glutamate, to the basal ganglia and extended amygdala. Molecular genetic studies have identified transduction and transcription factors that act in neurocircuitry associated with the development and maintenance of addiction that might mediate initial vulnerability, maintenance, and relapse associated with addiction. … Substance-induced changes in transcription factors can also produce competing effects on reward function.141 For example, repeated substance use activates accumulating levels of ΔFosB, and animals with elevated ΔFosB exhibit exaggerated sensitivity to the rewarding eff ects of drugs of abuse, leading to the hypothesis that ΔFosB might be a sustained molecular trigger or switch that helps initiate and maintain a state of addiction.141,142
- ^ Kringelbach, Morten L. (May 2, 2006). «Searching the brain for happiness». BBC News. Archived from the original on October 19, 2006.
- ^ «Sigmund Freud (1856—1939)». The University of Tennessee, Martin. March 11, 2012. Retrieved January 16, 2018.
- ^ «A Systemic Perspective on Cognition and Mathematics». Lin Forrest Publishers. June 30, 2013. Retrieved January 16, 2018.
- ^ Gao, Jihai (August 2013). «Deleuze’s Conception of Desire». Deleuze Studies. 7 (3): 406–420. doi:10.3366/dls.2013.0120.
- ^ Smith, Daniel W. (2007). «Deleuze and the Question of Desire: Toward an Immanent Theory of Ethics». Parrhesia. 2: 66–78.
- ^ «Parked Domain». Archived from the original on 2008-09-14. Retrieved 2019-07-23.
{{cite web}}
: CS1 maint: bot: original URL status unknown (link) - ^ Desire, Class Position, and Gender in Jane Eyre and Pickwick Papers Benjamin Graves ’97 (English 73 Brown University, 1996)
- ^ Distant Desire: Homoerotic Codes and the Subversion of the English Novel in E.M. Forster’s Fiction (Sexuality and Literature) by Parminder Kaur Bakshi
- ^ «Sepulveda — Desire: Can’t Live With It, Can’t Live Without It».
- ^ Gender, Desire, and Sexuality in T. S. Eliot. Edited by Cassandra Laity. Drew University, New Jersey. Nancy K. Gish. University of Southern Maine (ISBN 978-0-521-80688-6 | ISBN 0-521-80688-7)
- ^ «Melodramas Films».
- ^ «Cathy Cupitt, Eyeballing the Simulacra Desire and Vision in Blade Runner«. Archived from the original on October 22, 1999. Retrieved 2017-03-29.
{{cite web}}
: CS1 maint: bot: original URL status unknown (link)
Further reading[edit]
- Marks, Joel. The Ways of Desire: New Essays in Philosophical Psychology on the Concept of Wanting. Transaction Publishers, 1986
- Jadranka Skorin-Kapov, The Aesthetics of Desire and Surprise: Phenomenology and Speculation. Lexington Books 2015
Wikiquote has quotations related to Desire.
But, for the most part, husbands and wives _can_ have children, if they so desire, _and they_ SHOULD _so desire_. ❋ Unknown (N/A)
B.C. See Vincent Smith, _Oxford History of India_, p. 52.] [Footnote 9: This is sometimes rendered simply by desire but _desire_ in ❋ Charles Eliot (1896)
How to bow to a muslim Kingwhose main desire is to destroy America. ❋ Unknown (2009)
Your main desire is to see America fail and blame this administration even tho they are left with the Bush mess. ❋ Unknown (2009)
So the fact of variability of desire is not on its own enough to cast doubt on the natural law universal goods thesis: as the good is not defined fundamentally by reference to desire, the fact of variation in desire is not enough to raise questions about universal goods. ❋ Unknown (2007)
The word desire has a wonderful derivation: It comes from the Latin de sidere, which means literally “from the stars.” ❋ John Assaraf (2008)
Further, between appetite and desire there is no difference, except that the term desire is generally applied to men, in so far as they are conscious of their appetite, and may accordingly be thus defined: Desire is appetite with consciousness thereof. ❋ Unknown (2007)
Single women abound — it’s a single available man’s paradise — so if your main desire is to meet a man for a serious relationship, this is probably not the best place. ❋ Unknown (2003)
He enters upon his job without any pretence of enthusiasm, and his main desire is not, as one might expect, to find a more interesting and useful job, but simply to be playing cricket. ❋ Unknown (1945)
I think the desire is there – the ESOL/Skills for Life agenda is based on the notion of preparing learners (mostly migrant worker population) to be functional in society. ❋ Unknown (2010)
Just as the vampire’s giving multilingual tongue to his desire is a speech from beyond life’s natural bounds, so he must be bested by a death-defying lifelessness of inscription. ❋ Unknown (2008)
I hereby ask that Bicici bank CI West Africa should please take this issue very serious to ensure that our desire is achieved. ❋ Unknown (2008)
This likely indicates the desire is there to hurt. ❋ Unknown (2007)
While I focus mainly on wine, the object of his desire is another fermented adult beverage — beer. ❋ Unknown (2007)
Michael Chabon has said that his desire is the «annihilation of literary categories.» ❋ Unknown (2007)
Indeed, this desire is already part of an aesthetic understanding whose programmatic unfolding includes its own negation, whose purpose is assured by the negation through which it becomes merely aesthetic and through which it reasserts itself as the effect of its own critique. ❋ Unknown (2005)
They showed the desire is there by pushing their payroll higher than expected to sign free agents. ❋ Unknown (2005)
My desire to [touch] his [body] is [overwhelming]. ❋ Alicia Beezzy (2007)
Under no [circumstances] should one [fuse] desire and [expectation], as that leads to hope, which prolongs suffering. ❋ Killing Kittens (2005)
[What does] [your heart] desire? ❋ Nikolai21 (2005)
‘Joe, you’re my desire!’ ❋ Deita (2005)
1: yo [tim], let’s grab something to eat.
2: [hell no], i got no desire, therefore i don’t desire food.
1: but if you don’t desire food, then obviously you’re desiring death, [and that’s] another desire.
2: …. ❋ Chaos.Envoy (2009)
desire makes me *do* things
it makes me act like [boarding] a plane
or writing an invitation
I wonder what you do
when [desire‘s] got you
what do you *do* for someone you desire?
Just [asking for a friend]. ❋ Dia Spora (2019)
You desire for [everything] ❋ ViolentTravis (2010)
[Gianna] [owns] desire because Gianna can. ❋ Gianna (2005)
»Did You see [Desire] today she looked very beautiful today!»
«[I don’t like] [desire] she only wants attention»
«Desire is always negative. She [doubts] her self all the time. But i believe in her» ❋ Therealqueen1000 (2014)
«Damn Desire so hot»
«Heard she’s got [Jacob] [tho]»
«[Hell] I wanted her» ❋ RicketyScoop (2022)
What is the origin of the word desire?
“Desire”, the word, comes from latin. … “Sidus”, in latin, means “star”. So, its literal meaning is “to feel a lack of stars”.
What’s another word for desire?
Synonyms & Antonyms of desire
- appetency,
- appetite,
- craving,
- drive,
- hankering,
- hunger,
- itch,
- jones.
What is the full meaning of desire?
Desire, craving, longing, yearning suggest feelings that impel one to the attainment or possession of something. Desire is a strong feeling, worthy or unworthy, that impels to the attainment or possession of something that is (in reality or imagination) within reach: a desire for success.
Why do we desire?
Desire is intimately connected to pleasure and pain. We feel pleasure at the things that, in the course of evolution, have tended to promote the survival and reproduction of our species, and pain at those that have not. Things like status, sex, and sugar are wired to be pleasurable, and therefore desirable.
Is it wrong to desire?
It is your brain’s way of telling you that you are missing something in life. Contrary to what some people think, desire can actually be quite a good and necessary part of being human. … It is not desire that is bad, it is the lack of checks and balances that can turn a healthy emotion into a self-destructive one.
What can a person desire?
Mindy, I’ve heard it said there are only eight key desires in life:
- Survival, life extension.
- Enjoyment of food and beverage.
- freedom from fear, pain and danger.
- Sexual companionship.
- comfortable living conditions.
- to be superior. winning, keep up with your peer group.
- care and protection of loved ones.
- Social approval.
What is the deepest human desire?
In How to Win Friends & Influence People, Dale Carnegie writes, “There is one longing – almost as deep, almost as imperious, as the desire for food or sleep – which is seldom gratified. It is what Freud calls ‘the desire to be great. ‘ It is what Dewey calls ‘the desire to be important.
What is the strongest human drive?
Sex desire is the most powerful of human desires.” Craving for food is the most powerful of human desires in personal experiences.
Does desire mean love?
But once you take a deep dive into what each really means to you, you may find there are some huge differences. Here’s the thing: While love is a biological need, desire is more centered on a motivation and drive. … Desire is larger than the act of sex—it’s also about feeling like we deserve that wanting.
Why do I desire a relationship?
Actually, there are two very different reasons for wanting a relationship. The first is about what you want to get, and the second is about what you want to learn and share. If you ask people why they want a relationship, many will say things like: I want someone to love me and make me feel special and worthy.
What is desire in a relationship?
Desire is about a space you go into where you stop being the responsible, well-behaved human who looks after others and takes care of things. Desire happens when you can be completely available to, and connected with, yourself while you are with another.
Is desire a emotion?
Desire is the emotion of longing or hoping for a person, object, or outcome. The same sense is expressed by words such as «craving». When a person desires something or someone, their sense of longing is excited by the enjoyment or the thought of the item or person, and they want to take actions to obtain their goal.
Why is excess of desire harmful?
Desire is healthy but it becomes destructive when one has excessive desire for something. … Sometimes excessive desire morphs into obsession. When one is obsessed they can not stop doing something and they often lose control of their lives.
What is the difference between need and desire?
The difference between Desire and Need. When used as nouns, desire means someone or something wished for, whereas need means a for something. When used as verbs, desire means to want, whereas need means to have an absolute requirement for.
Is soap a need or want?
Wants are a step ahead of needs and are largely dependent on the needs of humans themselves. For example, you need to take a bath. … You DONT need a good smelling soap. But you will definitely use it because it is your want.
What is the difference between a psychological desire and a psychological need?
The differences between physiological and psychological needs are that physiological needs deal primarily with basic external needs for the care and maintenance of the human body. … Love, friendship and intimacy are also included in the psychological. Humans also have another inherent need and desire to move forward.
Why is it important to know these desires?
Answer: Having a desire is very important because just like your ambitions in life, it strengthens your will to work hard in order to attain something. Explanation: Desire is defined as a strong feeling of wanting to have something or wishing for something to happen.
How do I get clear on what I want?
To keep your subconscious mind focused on what you want, read your list of goals every day. For an even more powerful approach, close your eyes and focus on each goal and ask yourself, “What is one thing I could do today to move toward the achievement of this goal?” Write down your answers and take those actions.
Why is it important to get clear on what you want?
Every day, strive for increased clarity around what you want. Get really clear about what you want and create a regular practice of evaluating your desires so you gain more clarity. Doing so will make it much easier to create what you want.
Why do I want to be important?
Feeling important gives us a self esteem boost It helps us to view ourselves in a better light. It makes us feel good about ourselves. Feeling more important than others also gives us a shot of self esteem. People want to get self esteem in any way they can.
How do you stop yourself from feeling loved?
Knowing and understanding the things that make you happy is vital in stopping the cycle of craving love from others. Write down a list of all the hobbies you enjoy such as reading or writing. If you do not have a hobby that you enjoy, write down hobbies that you have always wanted to try such as knitting or hiking.
How can I be admired by others?
If you are someone who seeks to be admired, here are 11 tangible ways on how you can make others admire you:
- Learn to be comfortable in your own skin. …
- Choose simplicity over complication. …
- Don’t dream your life; live your dreams. …
- Stop pleasing others despite yourself. …
- Live fully and dare greatly.
How do you make other people feel important?
Make Other People Feel Important
- Be Courteous With Everyone. This should go without saying, but when you are respectful toward someone else, he or she will, more times than not, show the same respect toward you. …
- Never Complain or Criticize. …
- Listen. …
- Show Admiration Toward Accomplishments or Traits. …
- Agree Often. …
- Raise People’s Self-Esteem. …
- Say “Thank You”
Asked by: Daija Jaskolski I
Score: 4.6/5
(57 votes)
Desires are states of mind that are expressed by terms like «wanting», «wishing», «longing» or «craving». A great variety of features is commonly associated with desires. They are seen as propositional attitudes towards conceivable states of affairs.
What is the full meaning of desire?
desire, wish, want, crave, covet mean to have a longing for. desire stresses the strength of feeling and often implies strong intention or aim. desires to start a new life wish sometimes implies a general or transient longing especially for the unattainable.
What does desire mean in the Bible?
1 shares. Desire is one of life’s strongest emotions. It stresses the strength of feeling and often implies strong intention or aim. Our desires fuel our actions; this ability was given to us by God to pull us towards Himself and His ways.
What are the examples of desire?
Desire is defined as physically longing for something. An example of desire is the feeling before a goodnight kiss. To want to have sex with (another person).
Is desire good or bad?
Contrary to what some people think, desire can actually be quite a good and necessary part of being human. … Desire is not the enemy to a happy and balanced life. It is not a roadblock to experiencing a higher self. In fact, desire can often be the driver for all that greater awareness and consciousness we so often seek.
41 related questions found
Why do we desire?
Desire is intimately connected to pleasure and pain. We feel pleasure at the things that, in the course of evolution, have tended to promote the survival and reproduction of our species, and pain at those that have not. Things like status, sex, and sugar are wired to be pleasurable, and therefore desirable.
Is desire an emotion?
While desires are often classified as emotions by laypersons, psychologists often describe desires as ur-emotions, or feelings that do not quite fit the category of basic emotions.
What is the similar meaning of desire?
wish, want. fancy, inclination, aspiration, impulse, preference. yearning, longing, craving, hankering, pining, ache, hunger, thirst, itch, burning, need. eagerness, enthusiasm, determination. predilection, proclivity, predisposition.
How do you describe wanting someone?
Some common synonyms of want are covet, crave, desire, and wish. While all these words mean «to have a longing for,» want specifically suggests a felt need or lack.
What does natural desire mean?
to prioritize using one’s natural abilities and specific skills, especially by pursuing tasks or goals suited to such skills. moreish ; morish adj. so good or pleasant that it causes a desire for more. Ex.: These chocolate truffles are so morish!
What is the strongest human desire?
Sex desire is the most powerful of human desires. When driven by this desire, men develop keenness of imagination, courage, willpower, persistence, and creative ability unknown to them at other times.
What is the deepest human desire?
What is the deepest human desire? What do humans search for the most? There deepest desire is to know that we count for something, to know that we matter for someone. Where does God fit in among the desires of the human heart?
What are desires in life?
The desires are power, independence, curiosity, acceptance, order, saving, honor, idealism, social contact, family, status, vengeance, romance, eating, physical exercise, and tranquility. «These desires are what drive our everyday actions and make us who we are,» Reiss said.
What is a great desire?
A desire is a strong wish to do or have something. I had a strong desire to help and care for people. Synonyms: wish, want, longing, need More Synonyms of desire.
What do you desire out of life?
Spiritual/Emotional Things
- Have at least one true best friend.
- Feel relief from social judgment.
- Reconcile with an enemy.
- Be remembered in a positive way after death.
- Know that you made a difference in someone else’s life.
- Feel important to others.
- Know yourself and feel centered.
- Live each day without regret.
What do humans desire the most?
3 Things All Humans Want at Work (and in Life)
- Survive. «Survive is our need for food, water, and shelter,» says Andreatta. …
- Belong. «Belong is our need to be accepted for who we are, to be cared for by others, and be involved in a meaningful community,» says Andreatta. …
- Become.
What is the difference between feelings and desire?
Just like beliefs, emotions aim at being justified, that is, at according with reality. In particular, they aim at reflecting the significance or meaning of their object for the subject. Desires on the other hand aim at altering reality so that it comes to accord with them.
What is the difference between need and desire?
Needs refer to those that are necessary for survival. On the other hand, desires refer to those that people want in life although there is not threat to survival if the individual fails to accomplish them.
Why do we want things we don’t have?
Sometimes it can feel like you’re always chasing something you can’t have. It can feel like the more someone pulls away, the more you end up wanting them. This is partly due to our vanity and self-esteem, and partly due to our warped sense of their value.
Why is excess of desire harmful?
Desire is healthy but it becomes destructive when one has excessive desire for something. … Sometimes excessive desire morphs into obsession. When one is obsessed they can not stop doing something and they often lose control of their lives.
How do you stop desire?
Here are some tips:
- Engage in a relaxing activity before sex. …
- Communicate your desires. …
- Talk about boundaries. …
- Don’t be afraid to ask questions. …
- Talk to a sex therapist.
Is desire a mental state?
To desire is to be in a particular state of mind. … Desiring is a state of mind that is commonly associated with a number of different effects: a person with a desire tends to act in certain ways, feel in certain ways, and think in certain ways.
What is the role of desires in our life?
You have a goal in mind. You dream about it. Desire keeps an idea person excited and willing to proceed with their dream, urging them to do what it takes to make it a reality. …
Do we desire good because it is good?
Socrates and Aristotle both say that we desire what is (or what we perceive to be) good. Spinoza and Nietzsche both believe that we call good what is it that we (already) desire.
-
1
desiredesire [dɪˊza(ɪ)ə]
1) (си́льное) жела́ние (for)
2) про́сьба; пожела́ние;
3) страсть, вожделе́ние
4) предме́т жела́ния; мечта́
1) жела́ть; хоте́ть;
2) проси́ть, тре́бовать;
Англо-русский словарь Мюллера > desire
-
2
desireEnglish-Russian dictionary of biology and biotechnology > desire
-
3
desireПерсональный Сократ > desire
-
4
desireI [dɪ’zaɪə]
n
желание, мечта, стремление
He has all the desire in the world to help. — Он от всей души хочет помочь.
A sudden (feverish, secret, passionate) desire got hold/took possession of him. — Им овладело неожиданное (лихорадочное, тайное, страстное) желание.
It is one of his inmost/deep-rooted/natural/long-cherished desires. — Это одно из его сокровенных желаний.
— strong desire
— vague desire
— irresistible desire
— earnest desire
— smb’s only desire
— smb’s heart’s desire
— one’s own desires
— against smb’s desire
— desires of all people
— desire of recognition
— desire for fame
— desire for the praise of others
— eager desire for knowledge
— desire after riches
— desire to know
— desire for travelling
— desire of helping people
— without any desire
— at the desire of the majority
— in accordance with smb’s desire
— by their hasty desire
— from a desire to please
— have a desire to do smth
— satisfy all his desires
— feel a violent desire
— feel little no desire for power
— have not the slightest desire to go on holiday
— nurse an evil desire
— have but one desire
— be the victim of one’s desires
— get one’s desire
— carry out one’s desire
— humour smb’s desire
— resist one’s desires
— cross smb’s desires
— awaken desire to do smth
— express a desire to cooperate
— cherish a desire to see the world
— restrain desires
— be burning with desire
— smb’s desires are easily satisfiedUSAGE:
II [dɪ’zaɪə]
v
желать, мечтать, очень хотеть
She desires to remain neutral in the dispute. — Она очень не хочет принимать чью-л. сторону в споре
English-Russian combinatory dictionary > desire
-
5
desire[dɪˈzaɪə]
desire просьба; пожелание; at your desire по вашей просьбе desire (сильное) желание (for) desire желание desire желать; хотеть; to leave much to be desired оставлять желать много лучшего desire желать desire пожелание desire предмет желания; мечта desire просить, требовать; I desire you to go at once я требую (прошу), чтобы вы пошли немедленно desire просить desire просьба; пожелание; at your desire по вашей просьбе desire просьба desire страсть, вожделение desire требовать express a desire for выражать желание desire просить, требовать; I desire you to go at once я требую (прошу), чтобы вы пошли немедленно desire желать; хотеть; to leave much to be desired оставлять желать много лучшего
English-Russian short dictionary > desire
-
6
desiredɪˈzaɪə
1. сущ.
1) (страстное) желание( for), жажда( чего-л.) ;
вожделение, страсть animal desire ≈ животная страсть sexual desire ≈ сексуальное желание sincere desire ≈ искреннее желание to arouse, create, whet (a) desire ≈ возбуждать желание to feel a desire ≈ испытывать желание to satisfy a desire ≈ удовлетворять желание to stifle, suppress a desire ≈ подавлять желание (an) ardent, blind, burning, earnest, fervent, intense, keen, overwhelming, passionate, strong desire ≈ сильное желание Syn: craving, longing
2) просьба, запрос;
пожелание to express, voice a desire ≈ выражать пожелание I also send, at your desire, a full list of articles. ≈ Я также посылаю по Вашей просьбе полный список статей. Syn: petition, request
3) предмет желания, желаемое an unfulfilled desire ≈ неосуществленный замысел, несбывшаяся мечта, неисполненное желание The desire of all nations shall come. ≈ Исполнится мечта/желание всех народов. Syn: wish
2. гл.
1) испытывать сильное желание, жаждать, мечтать;
очень хотеть to deeply, fervently, strongly desire ≈ сильно желать She desires to remain neutral in the dispute. ≈ Она очень не хочет принимать чью-л. сторону в споре. Syn: wish, long, covet, crave
2) просить, требовать;
умолять, упрашивать He desired Velarde would write to the court. ≈ Он очень просил, чтобы Велард написал в суд. Syn: request, pray, entreat( сильное) желание — * for knowledge жажда знаний — * to do smth. желание сделать что-л. — to have /to feel/ no * for smth. /to do smth./ не иметь желания /охоты/ сделать что-л. — to satisfy /to meet/ smb.’s *s удовлетворять чьи-л. желания желание, страсть;
вожделение — consumed with * (весь) во власти желания, пожираемый страстью просьба, пожелание — by * по просьбе, по указанию — in accordance with your *(s), at your * в соответствии с вашим пожеланием;
по вашему желанию /требованию/ предмет желания;
мечта — to have /to get/ one’s * добиться своего;
добиться осуществления своих желаний желать;
испытывать желание, хотеть — to * peace хотеть мира — to * glory жаждать славы — to * to be left alone, to * that one should be left alone хотеть /желать/ остаться одному — since you * it если вам так хочется — it leaves much to be *d это оставляет желать лучшего — to be all that can be *d быть пределом желаний, не оставлять желать ничего лучшего (настоятельно) просить;
выражать желание;
требовать — to * an explanation (по) требовать объяснений — I * you to go at once прошу вас ехать немедленно — * Mr. Jones to come in попросите м-ра Джонса (войти)
~ просьба;
пожелание;
at your desire по вашей просьбе
desire (сильное) желание (for) ~ желание ~ желать;
хотеть;
to leave much to be desired оставлять желать много лучшего ~ желать ~ пожелание ~ предмет желания;
мечта ~ просить, требовать;
I desire you to go at once я требую (прошу), чтобы вы пошли немедленно ~ просить ~ просьба;
пожелание;
at your desire по вашей просьбе ~ просьба ~ страсть, вожделение ~ требовать
express a ~ for выражать желание
~ просить, требовать;
I desire you to go at once я требую (прошу), чтобы вы пошли немедленно
~ желать;
хотеть;
to leave much to be desired оставлять желать много лучшегоБольшой англо-русский и русско-английский словарь > desire
-
7
desire1. [dıʹzaıə]
1. (сильное) желание
desire to do smth. — желание сделать что-л.
to have /to feel/ no desire for smth. /to do smth./ — не иметь желания /охоты/ сделать что-л.
to satisfy /to meet/ smb.’s desires — удовлетворять чьи-л. желания
2. желание, страсть; вожделение
consumed with desire — (весь) во власти желания, пожираемый страстью
3. просьба, пожелание
by desire — по просьбе, по указанию
in accordance with your desire(s), at your desire — в соответствии с вашим пожеланием; по вашему желанию /требованию/
4. предмет желания; мечта
to have /to get/ one’s desire — добиться своего; добиться осуществления своих желаний
2. [dıʹzaıə]
1. желать; испытывать желание, хотеть
to desire peace [happiness] — хотеть мира [счастья]
to desire to be left alone, to desire that one should be left alone — хотеть /желать/ остаться одному
to be all that can be desired — быть пределом желаний, не оставлять желать ничего лучшего
2. (настоятельно) просить; выражать желание; требовать
to desire an explanation [a prompt answer] — (по)требовать объяснений [немедленного ответа]
I desire you to go at once, I desire that you should go at once — прошу вас ехать немедленно
desire Mr. Jones to come in — попросите м-ра Джонса (войти)
НБАРС > desire
-
8
desire1. n желание, страсть; вожделение
2. n просьба, пожелание
3. n предмет желания; мечта
4. v желать; испытывать желание, хотеть
to desire to be left alone, to desire that one should be left alone — хотеть остаться одному
5. v просить; выражать желание; требовать
Синонимический ряд:
1. aspiration (noun) ambition; aspiration; hope; mind; request; want; wish
3. hunger (noun) appetite; craving; hunger; itch; longing; motive; obsession; urge; will; yearning; zeal
4. lust (noun) aphrodisia; appetition; avarice; carnality; concupiscence; eroticism; fervor; fervour; greed; lickerishness; lust; lustfulness; passion; pleasure; prurience; pruriency; rage
5. covet (verb) choose; covet; desiderate; fancy; like; long for; need; please; prefer; want; will; wish
6. long (verb) ache; aspire; crave; hanker; long; pant; yearn; yearn for
7. request (verb) ask; bespeak; request; seek; solicit; urge
Антонимический ряд:
abhor; abhorrence; abominate; abomination; antagonism; aversion; detestation; disgust; dislike; distaste; generosity; hate; horror; loathe; loathing; opposition; reject; spurn
English-Russian base dictionary > desire
-
9
desire[dɪ’zaɪə]
1.гл.
1) испытывать сильное желание, жаждать, мечтать; очень хотеть
to deeply / fervently / strongly desire — сильно желать
She desires to remain neutral in the dispute. — Она не хочет принимать чью-либо сторону в споре.
Syn:
2) просить, требовать; умолять, упрашивать
He desired Velarde would write to the court. — Он очень просил, чтобы Велард написал в суд.
Syn:
2.
сущ.
1) (страстное) желание, жажда ; вожделение, страсть
ardent / blind / burning / earnest / fervent / intense / keen / overwhelming / passionate / strong desire — сильное желание
to arouse / create / whet (a) desire — возбуждать желание
to stifle / suppress a desire — подавлять желание
Syn:
2)
книжн.
просьба, запрос; пожелание
to express / voice a desire — выражать пожелание
I also send, at your desire, a full list of articles. — Я также посылаю по вашей просьбе полный список предметов.
Syn:
3) предмет желания, желаемое
an unfulfilled desire — неосуществлённый замысел, несбывшаяся мечта, неисполненное желание
The desire of all nations shall come. — Исполнится мечта всех народов.
Syn:
Англо-русский современный словарь > desire
-
10
desireжелание
имя существительное:глагол:
Англо-русский синонимический словарь > desire
-
11
desire1. I
2. III
desire smth. desire health желать /хотеть/ здоровья и т. д.; desire peace стремиться к миру
3. IV
desire smth. in some тачает — smth. ardently горячо и т. д. желать /хотеть/ чего-л.
4. VII
desire smb. to do smth. desire smb. to go on a trip желать, чтобы кто-л. отправился в поездку и т. д.
5. XI
be desired our room was all that could be desired лучшей комнаты и желать было нельзя || your behaviour leaves much to be -d ваше поведение и т. д. оставляет желать лучшего
6. XXI1
desire smth. for smb. desire health for one’s family желать здоровья своей семье и т. д. || desire smb. for one’s wife хотеть взять кого-л. в жены
English-Russian dictionary of verb phrases > desire
-
12
desireEnglish-Russian big medical dictionary > desire
-
13
desire[dɪ’zaɪə]
3) просьба, пожелание
1) сильно желать, очень хотеть, испытывать желание, жаждать, мечтать
2) просить, требовать, умолять
2000 самых употребительных английских слов > desire
-
14
desire1) (сильное) желание (for)
2) просьба; пожелание; at your desire по вашей просьбе
3) страсть, вожделение
4) предмет желания; мечта
Syn:
emotion
1) желать; хотеть; to leave much to be desired оставлять желать много лучшего
2) просить, требовать; I desire you to go at once я требую (прошу), чтобы вы пошли немедленно
Syn:
want
* * *
1 (n) желание
* * *
* * *
[de·sire || dɪ’zaɪə]
желание, сильное желание; страсть, вожделение; пожелание, волеизъявление; предмет желания; мечта
желать, хотеть, просить, требовать* * *
алкать
вожделеть
жаждать
желание
желания
желать
пристрастие
соизволение
соизволения
страсть
хотение
хотения
хотеть
* * *
1. сущ.
1) (страстное) желание, жажда (чего-л. — for)
2) просьба
3) предмет желания
2. гл.
1) испытывать сильное желание, жаждать, мечтать; очень хотеть
2) проситьНовый англо-русский словарь > desire
-
15
desireabsence of will, ab[o]ulia drive, attraction, desire
безволие, абулия
————————
Drive, desire, attraction
English-Russian dictionary of medicine > desire
-
16
desireEnglish-russian biological dictionary > desire
-
17
desireEnglish-Russian word troubles > desire
-
18
desireLarge English-Russian phrasebook > desire
-
19
désiréБФРС > désiré
-
20
desire1) хотение
2) желание
3) желатьАнгло-русский технический словарь > desire
Страницы
- Следующая →
- 1
- 2
- 3
- 4
- 5
- 6
- 7
См. также в других словарях:
-
Desire — may refer to: Contents 1 Concepts 2 Music 2.1 Albums 2.2 … Wikipedia
-
desire — vb Desire, wish, want, crave, covet mean having a longing for something. Desire, wish, and want are often used with identical intent though in such situations (usually everyday ones) that the degree of intensity of longing or need is not at issue … New Dictionary of Synonyms
-
Desire — Saltar a navegación, búsqueda El término desire ( deseo , en inglés y otros idiomas) puede hacer referencia a: Desire, film estadounidense de 1936 dirigido por Frank Borzage; «Desire», canción de Do As Infinity del álbum New World; «Desire»,… … Wikipedia Español
-
Desire — De*sire , v. t. [imp. & p. p. {Desired}; p. pr. & vb. n. {Desiring}.] [F. d[ e]sirer, L. desiderare, origin uncertain, perh. fr. de + sidus star, constellation, and hence orig., to turn the eyes from the stars. Cf. {Consider}, and {Desiderate},… … The Collaborative International Dictionary of English
-
Desire — Desire … Википедия
-
desire — [di zīr′] vt. desired, desiring [ME desiren < OFr desirer < L desiderare, orig., prob., to await from the stars < de , from + sidus, star: see SIDEREAL] 1. to wish or long for; crave; covet 2. to ask for; request 3. to want sexually vi.… … English World dictionary
-
Desire — De*sire , n. [F. d[ e]sir, fr. d[ e]sirer. See {Desire}, v. t.] 1. The natural longing that is excited by the enjoyment or the thought of any good, and impels to action or effort its continuance or possession; an eager wish to obtain or enjoy.… … The Collaborative International Dictionary of English
-
desire — refers to the psychological aspects of sexuality, particularly fantasies, operating both consciously and unconsciously. It is distinct from both the biological aspects of sexuality the body and its sensations, its ability to reproduce, and sexual … Dictionary of sociology
-
Desire — Studioalbum von Bob Dylan Veröffentlichung 5. Januar 1976 Label Columbia Records For … Deutsch Wikipedia
-
désiré — désiré, ée (dé zi ré, rée ; plusieurs, dit l Académie, prononcent de zi ré, rée) part. passé. • Peutêtre nous touchons au moment désiré, CORN. Sert. III, 4. • Commander est bon ; être riche est bon ; et ces bonnes choses, mal prises et mal… … Dictionnaire de la Langue Française d’Émile Littré
-
desire — [n1] want, longing admiration, ambition, appetite, ardor, aspiration, attraction, avidity, concupiscence, covetousness, craving, craze, cupidity, devotion, doting, eagerness, fancy, fascination, fervor, fondness, frenzy, greed, hankering*, hunger … New thesaurus