The word mathematics means

Mathematics is an area of knowledge that includes the topics of numbers, formulas and related structures, shapes and the spaces in which they are contained, and quantities and their changes. These topics are represented in modern mathematics with the major subdisciplines of number theory,[1] algebra,[2] geometry,[1] and analysis,[3][4] respectively. There is no general consensus among mathematicians about a common definition for their academic discipline.

Most mathematical activity involves the discovery of properties of abstract objects and the use of pure reason to prove them. These objects consist of either abstractions from nature or—in modern mathematics—entities that are stipulated to have certain properties, called axioms. A proof consists of a succession of applications of deductive rules to already established results. These results include previously proved theorems, axioms, and—in case of abstraction from nature—some basic properties that are considered true starting points of the theory under consideration.[5]

Mathematics is essential in the natural sciences, engineering, medicine, finance, computer science and the social sciences. Although mathematics is extensively used for modeling phenomena, the fundamental truths of mathematics are independent from any scientific experimentation. Some areas of mathematics, such as statistics and game theory, are developed in close correlation with their applications and are often grouped under applied mathematics. Other areas are developed independently from any application (and are therefore called pure mathematics), but often later find practical applications.[6][7] The problem of integer factorization, for example, which goes back to Euclid in 300 BC, had no practical application before its use in the RSA cryptosystem, now widely used for the security of computer networks.

Historically, the concept of a proof and its associated mathematical rigour first appeared in Greek mathematics, most notably in Euclid’s Elements.[8] Since its beginning, mathematics was essentially divided into geometry and arithmetic (the manipulation of natural numbers and fractions), until the 16th and 17th centuries, when algebra[a] and infinitesimal calculus were introduced as new areas. Since then, the interaction between mathematical innovations and scientific discoveries has led to a rapid lockstep increase in the development of both.[9] At the end of the 19th century, the foundational crisis of mathematics led to the systematization of the axiomatic method,[10] which heralded a dramatic increase in the number of mathematical areas and their fields of application. The contemporary Mathematics Subject Classification lists more than 60 first-level areas of mathematics.

Etymology

The word mathematics comes from Ancient Greek máthēma (μάθημα), meaning «that which is learnt»,[11] «what one gets to know», hence also «study» and «science». The word came to have the narrower and more technical meaning of «mathematical study» even in Classical times.[12] Its adjective is mathēmatikós (μαθηματικός), meaning «related to learning» or «studious», which likewise further came to mean «mathematical».[13] In particular, mathēmatikḗ tékhnē (μαθηματικὴ τέχνη; Latin: ars mathematica) meant «the mathematical art».[11]

Similarly, one of the two main schools of thought in Pythagoreanism was known as the mathēmatikoi (μαθηματικοί)—which at the time meant «learners» rather than «mathematicians» in the modern sense. The Pythagoreans were likely the first to constrain the use of the word to just the study of arithmetic and geometry. By the time of Aristotle (384–322 BC) this meaning was fully established.[14]

In Latin, and in English until around 1700, the term mathematics more commonly meant «astrology» (or sometimes «astronomy») rather than «mathematics»; the meaning gradually changed to its present one from about 1500 to 1800. This change has resulted in several mistranslations: For example, Saint Augustine’s warning that Christians should beware of mathematici, meaning «astrologers», is sometimes mistranslated as a condemnation of mathematicians.[15]

The apparent plural form in English goes back to the Latin neuter plural mathematica (Cicero), based on the Greek plural ta mathēmatiká (τὰ μαθηματικά) and means roughly «all things mathematical», although it is plausible that English borrowed only the adjective mathematic(al) and formed the noun mathematics anew, after the pattern of physics and metaphysics, inherited from Greek.[16] In English, the noun mathematics takes a singular verb. It is often shortened to maths or, in North America, math.[17]

Areas of mathematics


Before the Renaissance, mathematics was divided into two main areas: arithmetic—regarding the manipulation of numbers, and geometry, regarding the study of shapes.[18] Some types of pseudoscience, such as numerology and astrology, were not then clearly distinguished from mathematics.[19]

During the Renaissance, two more areas appeared. Mathematical notation led to algebra which, roughly speaking, consists of the study and the manipulation of formulas. Calculus, consisting of the two subfields differential calculus and integral calculus, is the study of continuous functions, which model the typically nonlinear relationships between varying quantities, as represented by variables. This division into four main areas–arithmetic, geometry, algebra, calculus[20]–endured until the end of the 19th century. Areas such as celestial mechanics and solid mechanics were then studied by mathematicians, but now are considered as belonging to physics.[21] The subject of combinatorics has been studied for much of recorded history, yet did not become a separate branch of mathematics until the seventeenth century.[22]

At the end of the 19th century, the foundational crisis in mathematics and the resulting systematization of the axiomatic method led to an explosion of new areas of mathematics.[23][10] The 2020 Mathematics Subject Classification contains no less than sixty-three first-level areas.[24] Some of these areas correspond to the older division, as is true regarding number theory (the modern name for higher arithmetic) and geometry. Several other first-level areas have «geometry» in their names or are otherwise commonly considered part of geometry. Algebra and calculus do not appear as first-level areas but are respectively split into several first-level areas. Other first-level areas emerged during the 20th century or had not previously been considered as mathematics, such as mathematical logic and foundations.[25]

Number theory

Number theory began with the manipulation of numbers, that is, natural numbers {displaystyle (mathbb {N} ),} and later expanded to integers {displaystyle (mathbb {Z} )} and rational numbers {displaystyle (mathbb {Q} ).} Number theory was once called arithmetic, but nowadays this term is mostly used for numerical calculations.[26] Number theory dates back to ancient Babylon and probably China. Two prominent early number theorists were Euclid of ancient Greece and Diophantus of Alexandria.[27] The modern study of number theory in its abstract form is largely attributed to Pierre de Fermat and Leonhard Euler. The field came to full fruition with the contributions of Adrien-Marie Legendre and Carl Friedrich Gauss.[28]

Many easily stated number problems have solutions that require sophisticated methods, often from across mathematics. A prominent example is Fermat’s Last Theorem. This conjecture was stated in 1637 by Pierre de Fermat, but it was proved only in 1994 by Andrew Wiles, who used tools including scheme theory from algebraic geometry, category theory, and homological algebra.[29] Another example is Goldbach’s conjecture, which asserts that every even integer greater than 2 is the sum of two prime numbers. Stated in 1742 by Christian Goldbach, it remains unproven despite considerable effort.[30]

Number theory includes several subareas, including analytic number theory, algebraic number theory, geometry of numbers (method oriented), diophantine equations, and transcendence theory (problem oriented).[25]

Geometry

On the surface of a sphere, Euclidian geometry only applies as a local approximation. For larger scales the sum of the angles of a triangle is not equal to 180°.

Geometry is one of the oldest branches of mathematics. It started with empirical recipes concerning shapes, such as lines, angles and circles, which were developed mainly for the needs of surveying and architecture, but has since blossomed out into many other subfields.[31]

A fundamental innovation was the ancient Greeks’ introduction of the concept of proofs, which require that every assertion must be proved. For example, it is not sufficient to verify by measurement that, say, two lengths are equal; their equality must be proven via reasoning from previously accepted results (theorems) and a few basic statements. The basic statements are not subject to proof because they are self-evident (postulates), or are part of the definition of the subject of study (axioms). This principle, foundational for all mathematics, was first elaborated for geometry, and was systematized by Euclid around 300 BC in his book Elements.[32][33]

The resulting Euclidean geometry is the study of shapes and their arrangements constructed from lines, planes and circles in the Euclidean plane (plane geometry) and the three-dimensional Euclidean space.[b][31]

Euclidean geometry was developed without change of methods or scope until the 17th century, when René Descartes introduced what is now called Cartesian coordinates. This constituted a major change of paradigm: Instead of defining real numbers as lengths of line segments (see number line), it allowed the representation of points using their coordinates, which are numbers. Algebra (and later, calculus) can thus be used to solve geometrical problems. Geometry was split into two new subfields: synthetic geometry, which uses purely geometrical methods, and analytic geometry, which uses coordinates systemically.[34]

Analytic geometry allows the study of curves unrelated to circles and lines. Such curves can be defined as the graph of functions, the study of which led to differential geometry. They can also be defined as implicit equations, often polynomial equations (which spawned algebraic geometry). Analytic geometry also makes it possible to consider Euclidean spaces of higher than three dimensions.[31]

In the 19th century, mathematicians discovered non-Euclidean geometries, which do not follow the parallel postulate. By questioning that postulate’s truth, this discovery has been viewed as joining Russell’s paradox in revealing the foundational crisis of mathematics. This aspect of the crisis was solved by systematizing the axiomatic method, and adopting that the truth of the chosen axioms is not a mathematical problem.[35][10] In turn, the axiomatic method allows for the study of various geometries obtained either by changing the axioms or by considering properties that do not change under specific transformations of the space.[36]

Today’s subareas of geometry include:[25]

  • Projective geometry, introduced in the 16th century by Girard Desargues, extends Euclidean geometry by adding points at infinity at which parallel lines intersect. This simplifies many aspects of classical geometry by unifying the treatments for intersecting and parallel lines.
  • Affine geometry, the study of properties relative to parallelism and independent from the concept of length.
  • Differential geometry, the study of curves, surfaces, and their generalizations, which are defined using differentiable functions.
  • Manifold theory, the study of shapes that are not necessarily embedded in a larger space.
  • Riemannian geometry, the study of distance properties in curved spaces.
  • Algebraic geometry, the study of curves, surfaces, and their generalizations, which are defined using polynomials.
  • Topology, the study of properties that are kept under continuous deformations.
    • Algebraic topology, the use in topology of algebraic methods, mainly homological algebra.
  • Discrete geometry, the study of finite configurations in geometry.
  • Convex geometry, the study of convex sets, which takes its importance from its applications in optimization.
  • Complex geometry, the geometry obtained by replacing real numbers with complex numbers.

Algebra

Algebra is the art of manipulating equations and formulas. Diophantus (3rd century) and al-Khwarizmi (9th century) were the two main precursors of algebra.[38][39] Diophantus solved some equations involving unknown natural numbers by deducing new relations until he obtained the solution. Al-Khwarizmi introduced systematic methods for transforming equations, such as moving a term from one side of an equation into the other side. The term algebra is derived from the Arabic word al-jabr meaning ‘the reunion of broken parts’[40] that he used for naming one of these methods in the title of his main treatise.

Algebra became an area in its own right only with François Viète (1540–1603), who introduced the use of variables for representing unknown or unspecified numbers.[41] Variables allow mathematicians to describe the operations that have to be done on the numbers represented using mathematical formulas.

Until the 19th century, algebra consisted mainly of the study of linear equations (presently linear algebra), and polynomial equations in a single unknown, which were called algebraic equations (a term still in use, although it may be ambiguous). During the 19th century, mathematicians began to use variables to represent things other than numbers (such as matrices, modular integers, and geometric transformations), on which generalizations of arithmetic operations are often valid.[42] The concept of algebraic structure addresses this, consisting of a set whose elements are unspecified, of operations acting on the elements of the set, and rules that these operations must follow. The scope of algebra thus grew to include the study of algebraic structures. This object of algebra was called modern algebra or abstract algebra, as established by the influence and works of Emmy Noether.[43] (The latter term appears mainly in an educational context, in opposition to elementary algebra, which is concerned with the older way of manipulating formulas.)

Some types of algebraic structures have useful and often fundamental properties, in many areas of mathematics. Their study became autonomous parts of algebra, and include:[25]

  • group theory;
  • field theory;
  • vector spaces, whose study is essentially the same as linear algebra;
  • ring theory;
  • commutative algebra, which is the study of commutative rings, includes the study of polynomials, and is a foundational part of algebraic geometry;
  • homological algebra;
  • Lie algebra and Lie group theory;
  • Boolean algebra, which is widely used for the study of the logical structure of computers.

The study of types of algebraic structures as mathematical objects is the purpose of universal algebra and category theory.[44] The latter applies to every mathematical structure (not only algebraic ones). At its origin, it was introduced, together with homological algebra for allowing the algebraic study of non-algebraic objects such as topological spaces; this particular area of application is called algebraic topology.[45]

Calculus and analysis

A Cauchy sequence consists of elements that become arbitrarily close to each other as the sequence progresses (from left to right).

Calculus, formerly called infinitesimal calculus, was introduced independently and simultaneously by 17th-century mathematicians Newton and Leibniz.[46] It is fundamentally the study of the relationship of variables that depend on each other. Calculus was expanded in the 18th century by Euler with the introduction of the concept of a function and many other results.[47] Presently, «calculus» refers mainly to the elementary part of this theory, and «analysis» is commonly used for advanced parts.

Analysis is further subdivided into real analysis, where variables represent real numbers, and complex analysis, where variables represent complex numbers. Analysis includes many subareas shared by other areas of mathematics which include:[25]

  • Multivariable calculus
  • Functional analysis, where variables represent varying functions;
  • Integration, measure theory and potential theory, all strongly related with probability theory on a continuum;
  • Ordinary differential equations;
  • Partial differential equations;
  • Numerical analysis, mainly devoted to the computation on computers of solutions of ordinary and partial differential equations that arise in many applications.

Discrete mathematics

A diagram representing a two-state Markov chain. The states are represented by ‘A’ and ‘E’. The numbers are the probability of flipping the state.

Discrete mathematics, broadly speaking, is the study of individual, countable mathematical objects. An example is the set of all integers.[48] Because the objects of study here are discrete, the methods of calculus and mathematical analysis do not directly apply.[c] Algorithms—especially their implementation and computational complexity—play a major role in discrete mathematics.[49]

The four color theorem and optimal sphere packing were two major problems of discrete mathematics solved in the second half of the 20th century.[50] The P versus NP problem, which remains open to this day, is also important for discrete mathematics, since its solution would potentially impact a large number of computationally difficult problems.[51]

Discrete mathematics includes:[25]

  • Combinatorics, the art of enumerating mathematical objects that satisfy some given constraints. Originally, these objects were elements or subsets of a given set; this has been extended to various objects, which establishes a strong link between combinatorics and other parts of discrete mathematics. For example, discrete geometry includes counting configurations of geometric shapes
  • Graph theory and hypergraphs
  • Coding theory, including error correcting codes and a part of cryptography
  • Matroid theory
  • Discrete geometry
  • Discrete probability distributions
  • Game theory (although continuous games are also studied, most common games, such as chess and poker are discrete)
  • Discrete optimization, including combinatorial optimization, integer programming, constraint programming

Mathematical logic and set theory

The Venn diagram is a commonly used method to illustrate the relations between sets.

The two subjects of mathematical logic and set theory have belonged to mathematics since the end of the 19th century.[52][53] Before this period, sets were not considered to be mathematical objects, and logic, although used for mathematical proofs, belonged to philosophy and was not specifically studied by mathematicians.[54]

Before Cantor’s study of infinite sets, mathematicians were reluctant to consider actually infinite collections, and considered infinity to be the result of endless enumeration. Cantor’s work offended many mathematicians not only by considering actually infinite sets[55] but by showing that this implies different sizes of infinity, per Cantor’s diagonal argument. This led to the controversy over Cantor’s set theory.[56]

In the same period, various areas of mathematics concluded the former intuitive definitions of the basic mathematical objects were insufficient for ensuring mathematical rigour. Examples of such intuitive definitions are «a set is a collection of objects», «natural number is what is used for counting», «a point is a shape with a zero length in every direction», «a curve is a trace left by a moving point», etc.

This became the foundational crisis of mathematics.[57] It was eventually solved in mainstream mathematics by systematizing the axiomatic method inside a formalized set theory. Roughly speaking, each mathematical object is defined by the set of all similar objects and the properties that these objects must have.[23] For example, in Peano arithmetic, the natural numbers are defined by «zero is a number», «each number has a unique successor», «each number but zero has a unique predecessor», and some rules of reasoning.[58] This mathematical abstraction from reality is embodied in the modern philosophy of formalism, as founded by David Hilbert around 1910.[59]

The «nature» of the objects defined this way is a philosophical problem that mathematicians leave to philosophers, even if many mathematicians have opinions on this nature, and use their opinion—sometimes called «intuition»—to guide their study and proofs. The approach allows considering «logics» (that is, sets of allowed deducing rules), theorems, proofs, etc. as mathematical objects, and to prove theorems about them. For example, Gödel’s incompleteness theorems assert, roughly speaking that, in every consistent formal system that contains the natural numbers, there are theorems that are true (that is provable in a stronger system), but not provable inside the system.[60] This approach to the foundations of mathematics was challenged during the first half of the 20th century by mathematicians led by Brouwer, who promoted intuitionistic logic, which explicitly lacks the law of excluded middle.[61][62]

These problems and debates led to a wide expansion of mathematical logic, with subareas such as model theory (modeling some logical theories inside other theories), proof theory, type theory, computability theory and computational complexity theory.[25] Although these aspects of mathematical logic were introduced before the rise of computers, their use in compiler design, program certification, proof assistants and other aspects of computer science, contributed in turn to the expansion of these logical theories.[63]

Statistics and other decision sciences

The field of statistics is a mathematical application that is employed for the collection and processing of data samples, using procedures based on mathematical methods especially probability theory. Statisticians generate data with random sampling or randomized experiments.[65] The design of a statistical sample or experiment determines the analytical methods that will be used. Analysis of data from observational studies is done using statistical models and the theory of inference, using model selection and estimation. The models and consequential predictions should then be tested against new data.[d]

Statistical theory studies decision problems such as minimizing the risk (expected loss) of a statistical action, such as using a procedure in, for example, parameter estimation, hypothesis testing, and selecting the best. In these traditional areas of mathematical statistics, a statistical-decision problem is formulated by minimizing an objective function, like expected loss or cost, under specific constraints. For example, designing a survey often involves minimizing the cost of estimating a population mean with a given level of confidence.[66] Because of its use of optimization, the mathematical theory of statistics overlaps with other decision sciences, such as operations research, control theory, and mathematical economics.[67]

Computational mathematics

Computational mathematics is the study of mathematical problems that are typically too large for human, numerical capacity.[68][69] Numerical analysis studies methods for problems in analysis using functional analysis and approximation theory; numerical analysis broadly includes the study of approximation and discretization with special focus on rounding errors.[70] Numerical analysis and, more broadly, scientific computing also study non-analytic topics of mathematical science, especially algorithmic-matrix-and-graph theory. Other areas of computational mathematics include computer algebra and symbolic computation.

History

Ancient

The history of mathematics is an ever-growing series of abstractions. Evolutionarily speaking, the first abstraction to ever be discovered, one shared by many animals,[71] was probably that of numbers: the realization that, for example, a collection of two apples and a collection of two oranges (say) have something in common, namely that there are two of them. As evidenced by tallies found on bone, in addition to recognizing how to count physical objects, prehistoric peoples may have also known how to count abstract quantities, like time—days, seasons, or years.[72][73]

The Babylonian mathematical tablet Plimpton 322, dated to 1800 BC

Evidence for more complex mathematics does not appear until around 3000 BC, when the Babylonians and Egyptians began using arithmetic, algebra, and geometry for taxation and other financial calculations, for building and construction, and for astronomy.[74] The oldest mathematical texts from Mesopotamia and Egypt are from 2000 to 1800 BC. Many early texts mention Pythagorean triples and so, by inference, the Pythagorean theorem seems to be the most ancient and widespread mathematical concept after basic arithmetic and geometry. It is in Babylonian mathematics that elementary arithmetic (addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division) first appear in the archaeological record. The Babylonians also possessed a place-value system and used a sexagesimal numeral system which is still in use today for measuring angles and time.[75]

In the 6th century BC, Greek mathematics began to emerge as a distinct discipline and some Ancient Greeks such as the Pythagoreans appeared to have considered it a subject in its own right.[76] Around 300 BC, Euclid organized mathematical knowledge by way of postulates and first principles, which evolved into the axiomatic method that is used in mathematics today, consisting of definition, axiom, theorem, and proof.[77] His book, Elements, is widely considered the most successful and influential textbook of all time.[78] The greatest mathematician of antiquity is often held to be Archimedes (c. 287–212 BC) of Syracuse.[79] He developed formulas for calculating the surface area and volume of solids of revolution and used the method of exhaustion to calculate the area under the arc of a parabola with the summation of an infinite series, in a manner not too dissimilar from modern calculus.[80] Other notable achievements of Greek mathematics are conic sections (Apollonius of Perga, 3rd century BC),[81] trigonometry (Hipparchus of Nicaea, 2nd century BC),[82] and the beginnings of algebra (Diophantus, 3rd century AD).[83]

The numerals used in the Bakhshali manuscript, dated between the 2nd century BC and the 2nd century AD

The Hindu–Arabic numeral system and the rules for the use of its operations, in use throughout the world today, evolved over the course of the first millennium AD in India and were transmitted to the Western world via Islamic mathematics.[84] Other notable developments of Indian mathematics include the modern definition and approximation of sine and cosine, and an early form of infinite series.[85][86]

Medieval and later

A page from al-Khwārizmī’s Algebra

During the Golden Age of Islam, especially during the 9th and 10th centuries, mathematics saw many important innovations building on Greek mathematics. The most notable achievement of Islamic mathematics was the development of algebra. Other achievements of the Islamic period include advances in spherical trigonometry and the addition of the decimal point to the Arabic numeral system.[87] Many notable mathematicians from this period were Persian, such as Al-Khwarismi, Omar Khayyam and Sharaf al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī.[88] The Greek and Arabic mathematical texts were in turn translated to Latin during the Middle Ages and made available in Europe.[89]

During the early modern period, mathematics began to develop at an accelerating pace in Western Europe, with innovations that revolutionized mathematics, such as the introduction of variables and symbolic notation by François Viète (1540–1603), the introduction of coordinates by René Descartes (1596–1650) for reducing geometry to algebra, and the development of calculus by Isaac Newton (1642–1726/27) and Gottfried Leibniz (1646–1716) in the 17th century. Leonhard Euler (1707–1783), the most notable mathematician of the 18th century, unified these innovations into a single corpus with a standardized terminology, and completed them with the discovery and the proof of numerous theorems. Perhaps the foremost mathematician of the 19th century was the German mathematician Carl Gauss, who made numerous contributions to fields such as algebra, analysis, differential geometry, matrix theory, number theory, and statistics.[90] In the early 20th century, Kurt Gödel transformed mathematics by publishing his incompleteness theorems, which show in part that any consistent axiomatic system—if powerful enough to describe arithmetic—will contain true propositions that cannot be proved.[60]

Mathematics has since been greatly extended, and there has been a fruitful interaction between mathematics and science, to the benefit of both. Mathematical discoveries continue to be made to this very day. According to Mikhail B. Sevryuk, in the January 2006 issue of the Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, «The number of papers and books included in the Mathematical Reviews database since 1940 (the first year of operation of MR) is now more than 1.9 million, and more than 75 thousand items are added to the database each year. The overwhelming majority of works in this ocean contain new mathematical theorems and their proofs.»[91]

Symbolic notation and terminology

An explanation of the sigma (Σ) summation notation

Mathematical notation is widely used in science and engineering for representing complex concepts and properties in a concise, unambiguous, and accurate way. This notation consists of symbols used for representing operations, unspecified numbers, relations and any other mathematical objects, and then assembling them into expressions and formulas.[92] More precisely, numbers and other mathematical objects are represented by symbols called variables, which are generally Latin or Greek letters, and often include subscripts. Operation and relations are generally represented by specific symbols or glyphs,[93] such as + (plus), × (multiplication), {textstyle int } (integral), = (equal), and < (less than).[94] All these symbols are generally grouped according to specific rules to form expressions and formulas.[95] Normally, expressions and formulas do not appear alone, but are included in sentences of the current language, where expressions play the role of noun phrases and formulas play the role of clauses.

Mathematics has developed a rich terminology covering a broad range of fields that study the properties of various abstract, idealized objects and how they interact. It is based on rigorous definitions that provide a standard foundation for communication. An axiom or postulate is a mathematical statement that is taken to be true without need of proof. If a mathematical statement has yet to be proven (or disproven), it is termed a conjecture. Through a series of rigorous arguments employing deductive reasoning, a statement that is proven to be true becomes a theorem. A specialized theorem that is mainly used to prove another theorem is called a lemma. A proven instance that forms part of a more general finding is termed a corollary.[96]

Numerous technical terms used in mathematics are neologisms, such as polynomial and homeomorphism.[97] Other technical terms are words of the common language that are used in an accurate meaning that may differs slightly from their common meaning. For example, in mathematics, «or» means «one, the other or both», while, in common language, it is either ambiguous or means «one or the other but not both» (in mathematics, the latter is called «exclusive or»). Finally, many mathematical terms are common words that are used with a completely different meaning.[98] This may lead to sentences that are correct and true mathematical assertions, but appear to be nonsense to people who do not have the required background. For example, «every free module is flat» and «a field is always a ring».

Relationship with sciences

Mathematics is used in most sciences for modeling phenomena, which then allows predictions to be made from experimental laws.[99] The independence of mathematical truth from any experimentation implies that the accuracy of such predictions depends only on the adequacy of the model.[100] Inaccurate predictions, rather than being caused by invalid mathematical concepts, imply the need to change the mathematical model used.[101] For example, the perihelion precession of Mercury could only be explained after the emergence of Einstein’s general relativity, which replaced Newton’s law of gravitation as a better mathematical model.[102]

There is still a philosophical debate whether mathematics is a science. However, in practice, mathematicians are typically grouped with scientists, and mathematics shares much in common with the physical sciences. Like them, it is falsifiable, which means in mathematics that, if a result or a theory is wrong, this can be proved by providing a counterexample. Similarly as in science, theories and results (theorems) are often obtained from experimentation.[103] In mathematics, the experimentation may consist of computation on selected examples or of the study of figures or other representations of mathematical objects (often mind representations without physical support). For example, when asked how he came about his theorems, Gauss once replied «durch planmässiges Tattonieren» (through systematic experimentation).[104] However, some authors emphasize that mathematics differs from the modern notion of science by not relying on empirical evidence.[105][106][107][108]

Pure and applied mathematics

Isaac Newton

Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz

Until the 19th century, the development of mathematics in the West was mainly motivated by the needs of technology and science, and there was no clear distinction between pure and applied mathematics.[109] For example, the natural numbers and arithmetic were introduced for the need of counting, and geometry was motivated by surveying, architecture and astronomy. Later, Isaac Newton introduced infinitesimal calculus for explaining the movement of the planets with his law of gravitation. Moreover, most mathematicians were also scientists, and many scientists were also mathematicians.[110] However, a notable exception occurred with the tradition of pure mathematics in Ancient Greece.[111]

In the 19th century, mathematicians such as Karl Weierstrass and Richard Dedekind increasingly focused their research on internal problems, that is, pure mathematics.[109][112] This led to split mathematics into pure mathematics and applied mathematics, the latter being often considered as having a lower value among mathematical purists. However, the lines between the two are frequently blurred.[113]

The aftermath of World War II led to a surge in the development of applied mathematics in the US and elsewhere.[114][115] Many of the theories developed for applications were found interesting from the point of view of pure mathematics, and many results of pure mathematics were shown to have applications outside mathematics; in turn, the study of these applications may give new insights on the «pure theory».[116][117]

An example of the first case is the theory of distributions, introduced by Laurent Schwartz for validating computations done in quantum mechanics, which became immediately an important tool of (pure) mathematical analysis.[118] An example of the second case is the decidability of the first-order theory of the real numbers, a problem of pure mathematics that was proved true by Alfred Tarski, with an algorithm that is impossible to implement because of a computational complexity that is much too high.[119] For getting an algorithm that can be implemented and can solve systems of polynomial equations and inequalities, George Collins introduced the cylindrical algebraic decomposition that became a fundamental tool in real algebraic geometry.[120]

In the present day, the distinction between pure and applied mathematics is more a question of personal research aim of mathematicians than a division of mathematics into broad areas.[121][122] The Mathematics Subject Classification has a section for «general applied mathematics» but does not mention «pure mathematics».[25] However, these terms are still used in names of some university departments, such as at the Faculty of Mathematics at the University of Cambridge.

Unreasonable effectiveness

The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics is a phenomenon that was named and first made explicit by physicist Eugene Wigner.[7] It is the fact that many mathematical theories, even the «purest» have applications outside their initial object. These applications may be completely outside their initial area of mathematics, and may concern physical phenomena that were completely unknown when the mathematical theory was introduced.[123] Examples of unexpected applications of mathematical theories can be found in many areas of mathematics.

A notable example is the prime factorization of natural numbers that was discovered more than 2,000 years before its common use for secure internet communications through the RSA cryptosystem.[124] A second historical example is the theory of ellipses. They were studied by the ancient Greek mathematicians as conic sections (that is, intersections of cones with planes). It is almost 2,000 years later that Johannes Kepler discovered that the trajectories of the planets are ellipses.[125]

In the 19th century, the internal development of geometry (pure mathematics) lead to define and study non-Euclidean geometries, spaces of dimension higher than three and manifolds. At this time, these concepts seemed totally disconnected from the physical reality, but at the beginning of the 20th century, Albert Einstein developed the theory of relativity that uses fundamentally these concepts. In particular, spacetime of the special relativity is a non-Euclidean space of dimension four, and spacetime of the general relativity is a (curved) manifold of dimension four.[126][127]

A striking aspect of the interaction between mathematics and physics is when mathematics drives research in physics. This is illustrated by the discoveries of the positron and the baryon {displaystyle Omega ^{-}.} In both cases, the equations of the theories had unexplained solutions, which led to conjecture the existence of an unknown particle, and to search these particles. In both cases, these particles were discovered a few years later by specific experiments.[128][129][130]

Specific sciences

Physics

Mathematics and physics have influenced each other over their modern history. Modern physics uses mathematics abundantly,[131] and is also the motivation of major mathematical developments.[132] See above for examples of this strong interaction.

Computing

The rise of technology in the 20th century opened the way to a new science: computing.[e] This field is closely related to mathematics in several ways. Theoretical computer science is essentially mathematical in nature. Communication technologies apply branches of mathematics that may be very old (e.g., arithmetic), especially with respect to transmission security, in cryptography and coding theory. Discrete mathematics is useful in many areas of computer science, such as complexity theory, information theory, graph theory, and so on.[citation needed]

In return, computing has also become essential for obtaining new results. This is a group of techniques known as experimental mathematics, which is the use of experimentation to discover mathematical insights.[133] The most well-known example is the four-color theorem, which was proven in 1976 with the help of a computer. This revolutionized traditional mathematics, where the rule was that the mathematician should verify each part of the proof. In 1998, the Kepler conjecture on sphere packing seemed to also be partially proven by computer. An international team had since worked on writing a formal proof; it was finished (and verified) in 2015.[134]

Once written formally, a proof can be verified using a program called a proof assistant.[135] These programs are useful in situations where one is uncertain about a proof’s correctness.[135]

A major open problem in theoretical computer science is P versus NP. It is one of the seven Millennium Prize Problems.[136]

Biology and chemistry

Biology uses probability extensively — for example, in ecology or neurobiology.[137] Most of the discussion of probability in biology, however, centers on the concept of evolutionary fitness.[137]

Ecology heavily uses modeling to simulate population dynamics,[137][138] study ecosystems such as the predator-prey model, measure pollution diffusion,[139] or to assess climate change.[140] The dynamics of a population can be modeled by coupled differential equations, such as the Lotka–Volterra equations.[141] However, there is the problem of model validation. This is particularly acute when the results of modeling influence political decisions; the existence of contradictory models could allow nations to choose the most favorable model.[142]

Genotype evolution can be modeled with the Hardy-Weinberg principle.[citation needed]

Phylogeography uses probabilistic models.[citation needed]

Medicine uses statistical hypothesis testing, run on data from clinical trials, to determine whether a new treatment works.[citation needed]

Since the start of the 20th century, chemistry has used computing to model molecules in three dimensions. It turns out that the form of macromolecules in biology is variable and determines the action. Such modeling uses Euclidean geometry; neighboring atoms form a polyhedron whose distances and angles are fixed by the laws of interaction.[citation needed]

Earth sciences

Structural geology and climatology use probabilistic models to predict the risk of natural catastrophes.[citation needed] Similarly, meteorology, oceanography, and planetology also use mathematics due to their heavy use of models.[citation needed]

Areas of mathematics used in the social sciences include probability/statistics and differential equations (stochastic or deterministic).[citation needed] These areas used in fields such as sociology, psychology, economics, finance, and linguistics.[citation needed]

The fundamental postulate of mathematical economics is that of the rational individual actor – Homo economicus (lit.‘economic man’).[143] In this model, each individual aims solely to accumulate as much profit as possible,[143] and always makes optimal choices using perfect information.[144][better source needed] This atomistic view of economics allows it to relatively easily mathematize its thinking, because individual calculations are transposed into mathematical calculations. Such mathematical modeling allows one to probe economic mechanisms which would be very difficult to discover by a «literary» analysis.[citation needed] For example, explanations of economic cycles are not trivial. Without mathematical modeling, it is hard to go beyond simple statistical observations or unproven speculation.[citation needed]

However, many people have rejected or criticized the concept of Homo economicus.[144][better source needed] Economists note that real people usually have limited information and often make poor choices.[144][better source needed] Also, as shown in laboratory experiments, people care about fairness and sometimes altruism, not just personal gain.[144][better source needed] According to critics, mathematization is a veneer that allows for the material’s scientific valorization.[citation needed]

At the start of the 20th century, there was a movement to express historical movements in formulas.[citation needed] In 1922, Nikolai Kondratiev discerned the ~50-year-long Kondratiev cycle, which explains phases of economic growth or crisis.[145] Towards the end of the 19th century, Nicolas-Remi Brück [fr] and Charles Henri Lagrange [fr] had extended their analysis into geopolitics. They wanted to establish the historical existence of vast movements that took peoples to their apogee, then to their decline.[146][verification needed] More recently, Peter Turchin has been working on developing cliodynamics since the 1990s.[147] (In particular, he discovered the Turchin cycle, which predicts that violence spikes in a short cycle of ~50-year intervals, superimposed over a longer cycle of ~200–300 years.[148])

Even so, mathematization of the social sciences is not without danger. In the controversial book Fashionable Nonsense (1997), Sokal and Bricmont denounced the unfounded or abusive use of scientific terminology, particularly from mathematics or physics, in the social sciences. The study of complex systems (evolution of unemployment, business capital, demographic evolution of a population, etc.) uses elementary mathematical knowledge. However, the choice of counting criteria, particularly for unemployment, or of models can be subject to controversy.[citation needed]

Relationship with astrology and esotericism

Mathematics has had a close relationship with astrology for a long time. Biased by astral themes, it had motivated the study of astronomy. Renowned mathematicians have also been considered to be renowned astrologists; for example, Ptolemy, Arab astronomers, Regiomantus, Cardano, Kepler, or John Dee. In the Middle Ages, astrology was considered a science that included mathematics. In his encyclopedia, Theodor Zwinger wrote that astrology was a mathematical science that studied the «active movement of bodies as they act on other bodies». He reserved to mathematics the need to «calculate with probability the influences [of stars]» to foresee their «conjunctions and oppositions».[149]

These disciplines are no longer considered sciences.[150]

Philosophy

Reality

The connection between mathematics and material reality has led to philosophical debates since at least the time of Pythagoras. The ancient philosopher Plato argued that abstractions that reflect material reality have themselves a reality that exists outside space and time. As a result, the philosophical view that mathematical objects somehow exist on their own in abstraction is often referred to as Platonism. Independently of their possible philosophical opinions, modern mathematicians may be generally considered as Platonists, since they think of and talk of their objects of study as real objects.[151]

Armand Borel summarized this view of mathematics reality as follows, and provided quotations of G. H. Hardy, Charles Hermite, Henri Poincaré and Albert Einstein that support his views.[128]

Something becomes objective (as opposed to «subjective») as soon as we are convinced that it exists in the minds of others in the same form as it does in ours and that we can think about it and discuss it together.[152] Because the language of mathematics is so precise, it is ideally suited to defining concepts for which such a consensus exists. In my opinion, that is sufficient to provide us with a feeling of an objective existence, of a reality of mathematics …

Nevertheless, Platonism and the concurrent views on abstraction do not explain the unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics.[153]

Proposed definitions

There is no general consensus about a definition of mathematics or its epistemological status—that is, its place among other human activities.[154][155] A great many professional mathematicians take no interest in a definition of mathematics, or consider it undefinable.[154] There is not even consensus on whether mathematics is an art or a science.[155] Some just say, «mathematics is what mathematicians do».[154] This makes sense, as there is a strong consensus among them about what is mathematics and what is not. Most proposed definitions try to define mathematics by its object of study.[156]

Aristotle defined mathematics as «the science of quantity» and this definition prevailed until the 18th century. However, Aristotle also noted a focus on quantity alone may not distinguish mathematics from sciences like physics; in his view, abstraction and studying quantity as a property «separable in thought» from real instances set mathematics apart.[157] In the 19th century, when mathematicians began to address topics—such as infinite sets—which have no clear-cut relation to physical reality, a variety of new definitions were given.[158] With the large number of new areas of mathematics that appeared since the beginning of the 20th century and continue to appear, defining mathematics by this object of study becomes an impossible task.

Another approach for defining mathematics is to use its methods. So, an area of study can be qualified as mathematics as soon as one can prove theorems—assertions whose validity relies on a proof, that is, a purely-logical deduction.[159] Others take the perspective that mathematics is an investigation of axiomatic set theory, as this study is now a foundational discipline for much of modern mathematics.[160]

Rigor

Mathematical reasoning requires rigor. This means that the definitions must be absolutely unambiguous and the proofs must be reducible to a succession of applications of inference rules,[f] without any use of empirical evidence and intuition.[g][161] Rigorous reasoning is not specific to mathematics, but, in mathematics, the standard of rigor is much higher than elsewhere. Despite mathematics’ concision, rigorous proofs can require hundreds of pages to express. The emergence of computer-assisted proofs has allowed proof lengths to further expand,[h][162] such as the 255-page Feit–Thompson theorem.[i] The result of this trend is a philosophy of the quasi-empiricist proof that can not be considered infallible, but has a probability attached to it.[10]

The concept of rigor in mathematics dates back to ancient Greece, where their society encouraged logical, deductive reasoning. However, this rigorous approach would tend to discourage exploration of new approaches, such as irrational numbers and concepts of infinity. The method of demonstrating rigorous proof was enhanced in the sixteenth century through the use of symbolic notation. In the 18th century, social transition led to mathematicians earning their keep through teaching, which led to more careful thinking about the underlying concepts of mathematics. This produced more rigorous approaches, while transitioning from geometric methods to algebraic and then arithmetic proofs.[10]

At the end of the 19th century, it appeared that the definitions of the basic concepts of mathematics were not accurate enough for avoiding paradoxes (non-Euclidean geometries and Weierstrass function) and contradictions (Russell’s paradox). This was solved by the inclusion of axioms with the apodictic inference rules of mathematical theories; the re-introduction of axiomatic method pioneered by the ancient Greeks.[10] It results that «rigor» is no more a relevant concept in mathematics, as a proof is either correct or erroneous, and a «rigorous proof» is simply a pleonasm. Where a special concept of rigor comes into play is in the socialized aspects of a proof, wherein it may be demonstrably refuted by other mathematicians. After a proof has been accepted for many years or even decades, it can then be considered as reliable.[163]

Nevertheless, the concept of «rigor» may remain useful for teaching to beginners what is a mathematical proof.[164]

Training and practice

Education

Mathematics has a remarkable ability to cross cultural boundaries and time periods. As a human activity, the practice of mathematics has a social side, which includes education, careers, recognition, popularization, and so on. In education, mathematics is a core part of the curriculum and forms an important element of the STEM academic disciplines. Prominent careers for professional mathematicians include math teacher or professor, statistician, actuary, financial analyst, economist, accountant, commodity trader, or computer consultant.[165]

Archaeological evidence shows that instruction in mathematics occurred as early as the second millennium BCE in ancient Babylonia.[166] Comparable evidence has been unearthed for scribal mathematics training in the ancient Near East and then for the Greco-Roman world starting around 300 BCE.[167] The oldest known mathematics textbook is the Rhind papyrus, dated from circa 1650 BCE in Eygpt.[168] Due to a scarcity of books, mathematical teachings in ancient India were communicated using memorized oral tradition since the Vedic period (c. 1500 – c. 500 BCE).[169] In Imperial China during the Tang dynasty (618–907 CE), a mathematics curriculum was adopted for the civil service exam to join the state bureaucracy.[170]

Following the Dark Ages, mathematics education in Europe was provided by religious schools as part of the Quadrivium. Formal instruction in pedagogy began with Jesuit schools in the 16th and 17th century. Most mathematical curriculum remained at a basic and practical level until the nineteenth century, when it began to flourish in France and Germany. The oldest journal addressing instruction in mathematics was L’Enseignement Mathématique, which began publication in 1899.[171] The Western advancements in science and technology led to the establishment of centralized education systems in many nation-states, with mathematics as a core component—initially for its military applications.[172] While the content of courses varies, in the present day nearly all countries teach mathematics to students for significant amounts of time.[173]

During school, mathematical capabilities and positive expectations have a strong association with career interest in the field. Extrinsic factors such as feedback motivation by teachers, parents, and peer groups can influence the level of interest in mathematics.[174] Some students studying math may develop an apprehension or fear about their performance in the subject. This is known as math anxiety or math phobia, and is considered the most prominent of the disorders impacting academic performance. Math anxiety can develop due to various factors such as parental and teacher attitudes, social stereotypes, and personal traits. Help to counteract the anxiety can come from changes in instructional approaches, by interactions with parents and teachers, and by tailored treatments for the individual.[175]

Psychology (aesthetic, creativity and intuition)

The validity of a mathematical theorem relies only on the rigor of its proof, which could theoretically be done automatically by a computer program. This does not mean that there is no place for creativity in a mathematical work. On the contrary, many important mathematical results (theorems) are solutions of problems that other mathematicians failed to solve, and the invention of a way for solving them may be a fundamental way of the solving process.[176][177] An extreme example is Apery’s theorem: Roger Apery provided only the ideas for a proof, and the formal proof was given only several months later by three other mathematicians.[178]

Creativity and rigor are not the only psychological aspects of the activity of mathematicians. Some mathematicians can see their activity as a game, more specifically as solving puzzles.[179] This aspect of mathematical activity is emphasized in recreational mathematics.

Mathematicians can find an aesthetic value to mathematics. Like beauty, it is hard to define, it is commonly related to elegance, which involves qualities like simplicity, symmetry, completeness, and generality. G. H. Hardy in A Mathematician’s Apology expressed the belief that the aesthetic considerations are, in themselves, sufficient to justify the study of pure mathematics. He also identified other criteria such as significance, unexpectedness, and inevitability, which contribute to mathematical aesthetic.[180] Paul Erdős expressed this sentiment more ironically by speaking of «The Book», a supposed divine collection of the most beautiful proofs. The 1998 book Proofs from THE BOOK, inspired by Erdős, is a collection of particularly succinct and revelatory mathematical arguments. Some examples of particularly elegant results included are Euclid’s proof that there are infinitely many prime numbers and the fast Fourier transform for harmonic analysis.[181]

Some feel that to consider mathematics a science is to downplay its artistry and history in the seven traditional liberal arts.[182] One way this difference of viewpoint plays out is in the philosophical debate as to whether mathematical results are created (as in art) or discovered (as in science).[128] The popularity of recreational mathematics is another sign of the pleasure many find in solving mathematical questions.

In the 20th century, the mathematician L. E. J. Brouwer even initiated a philosophical perspective known as intuitionism, which primarily identifies mathematics with certain creative processes in the mind.[59] Intuitionism is in turn one flavor of a stance known as constructivism, which only considers a mathematical object valid if it can be directly constructed, not merely guaranteed by logic indirectly. This leads committed constructivists to reject certain results, particularly arguments like existential proofs based on the law of excluded middle.[183]

In the end, neither constructivism nor intuitionism displaced classical mathematics or achieved mainstream acceptance. However, these programs have motivated specific developments, such as intuitionistic logic and other foundational insights, which are appreciated in their own right.[183]

Cultural impact

Artistic expression

Cover page of Traité de l’harmonie réduite à ses principes naturels by Jean-Philippe Rameau

Notes that sound well together to a Western ear are sounds whose fundamental frequencies of vibration are in simple ratios. For example, an octave doubles the frequency and a perfect fifth multiplies it by {frac {3}{2}}.[184][185][better source needed]

This link between frequencies and harmony was discussed in Traité de l’harmonie réduite à ses principes naturels by Jean-Philippe Rameau,[186] a French baroque composer and music theoretician. It rests on the analysis of harmonics (noted 2 to 15 in the following figure) of a fundamental Do (noted 1); the first harmonics and their octaves sound well together.

The curve in red has a logarithmic shape, which reflects the following two phenomena:

  • The pitch of the sound, which in our auditory system is proportional to the logarithm of the sound’s frequency.
  • The harmonic frequencies, which are integer multiples of the fundamental frequency.

Fractal with a scaling symmetry and a central symmetry

Humans, as well as some other animals, find symmetric patterns to be more beautiful.[187] Mathematically, the symmetries of an object form a group known as the symmetry group.[188]

For example, the group underlying mirror symmetry is the cyclic group of two elements, mathbb {Z} /2mathbb {Z} . A Rorschach test is a figure invariant by this symmetry, as well as a butterfly, and animal bodies more generally (at least on the surface).[citation needed] Waves on the sea surface possess translation symmetry: moving one’s viewpoint by the distance between wave crests does not change one’s view of the sea.[citation needed] Furthermore, fractals possess (usually approximate[citation needed]) self-similarity.[189][190][better source needed]

Popularization

Popular mathematics is the act of presenting mathematics without technical terms.[191] Presenting mathematics may be hard since the general public suffers from mathematical anxiety and mathematical objects are highly abstract.[192] However, popular mathematics writing can overcome this by using applications or cultural links.[193] Despite this, mathematics is rarely the topic of popularization in printed or televised media.

Awards and prize problems

The most prestigious award in mathematics is the Fields Medal,[194][195] established in 1936 and awarded every four years (except around World War II) to up to four individuals.[196][197] It is considered the mathematical equivalent of the Nobel Prize.[197]

Other prestigious mathematics awards include:[198]

  • The Abel Prize, instituted in 2002[199] and first awarded in 2003[200]
  • The Chern Medal for lifetime achievement, introduced in 2009[201] and first awarded in 2010[202]
  • The AMS Leroy P. Steele Prize, awarded since 1970[203]
  • The Wolf Prize in Mathematics, also for lifetime achievement,[204] instituted in 1978[205]

A famous list of 23 open problems, called «Hilbert’s problems», was compiled in 1900 by German mathematician David Hilbert.[206] This list has achieved great celebrity among mathematicians,[207] and, as of 2022, at least thirteen of the problems (depending how some are interpreted) have been solved.[208]

A new list of seven important problems, titled the «Millennium Prize Problems», was published in 2000. Only one of them, the Riemann hypothesis, duplicates one of Hilbert’s problems. A solution to any of these problems carries a 1 million dollar reward.[209] To date, only one of these problems, the Poincaré conjecture, has been solved.[210]

See also

  • List of mathematical jargon
  • Lists of mathematicians
  • Lists of mathematics topics
  • Mathematical constant
  • Mathematical sciences
  • Mathematics and art
  • Mathematics education
  • Outline of mathematics
  • Philosophy of mathematics
  • Relationship between mathematics and physics
  • Science, technology, engineering, and mathematics

Notes

  1. ^ Here, algebra is taken in its modern sense, which is, roughly speaking, the art of manipulating formulas.
  2. ^ This includes conic sections, which are intersections of circular cylinders and planes.
  3. ^ However, some advanced methods of analysis are sometimes used; for example, methods of complex analysis applied to generating series.
  4. ^ Like other mathematical sciences such as physics and computer science, statistics is an autonomous discipline rather than a branch of applied mathematics. Like research physicists and computer scientists, research statisticians are mathematical scientists. Many statisticians have a degree in mathematics, and some statisticians are also mathematicians.
  5. ^ Ada Lovelace, in the 1840s, is known for having written the first computer program ever in collaboration with Charles Babbage
  6. ^ This does not mean to make explicit all inference rules that are used. On the contrary, this is generally impossible, without computers and proof assistants. Even with this modern technology, it may take years of human work for writing down a completely detailed proof.
  7. ^ This does not mean that empirical evidence and intuition are not needed for choosing the theorems to be proved and to prove them.
  8. ^ For considering as reliable a large computation occurring in a proof, one generally requires two computations using independent software
  9. ^ The book containing the complete proof has more than 1,000 pages.

References

  1. ^ a b «mathematics, n.«. Oxford English Dictionary. Oxford University Press. 2012. Archived from the original on November 16, 2019. Retrieved June 16, 2012. The science of space, number, quantity, and arrangement, whose methods involve logical reasoning and usually the use of symbolic notation, and which includes geometry, arithmetic, algebra, and analysis.
  2. ^ Kneebone, G. T. (1963). Mathematical Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics: An Introductory Survey. Dover. p. 4. ISBN 978-0-486-41712-7. Archived from the original on January 7, 2017. Retrieved June 20, 2015. Mathematics … is simply the study of abstract structures, or formal patterns of connectedness.
  3. ^ LaTorre, Donald R.; Kenelly, John W.; Biggers, Sherry S.; Carpenter, Laurel R.; Reed, Iris B.; Harris, Cynthia R. (2011). Calculus Concepts: An Informal Approach to the Mathematics of Change. Cengage Learning. p. 2. ISBN 978-1-4390-4957-0. Archived from the original on January 7, 2017. Retrieved June 20, 2015. Calculus is the study of change—how things change, and how quickly they change.
  4. ^ Ramana, B. V. (2007). Applied Mathematics. Tata McGraw–Hill Education. p. 2.10. ISBN 978-0-07-066753-2. Archived from the original on July 12, 2022. Retrieved July 30, 2022. The mathematical study of change, motion, growth or decay is calculus.
  5. ^ Hipólito, Inês Viegas (2015). «Abstract Cognition and the Nature of Mathematical Proof» (PDF). In Kanzian, Christian; Mitterer, Josef; Neges, Katharina (eds.). Realism – Relativism – Constructivism. 38th International Wittgenstein Symposium, August 9–15, 2015. Kirchberg am Wechsel, Austria. Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society. pp. 132–134. Archived (PDF) from the original on November 7, 2022. Retrieved November 5, 2022. (at ResearchGate Archived November 5, 2022, at the Wayback Machine)
  6. ^ Peterson 2001, p. 12.
  7. ^ a b Wigner, Eugene (1960). «The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences». Communications on Pure and Applied Mathematics. 13 (1): 1–14. Bibcode:1960CPAM…13….1W. doi:10.1002/cpa.3160130102. Archived from the original on February 28, 2011.
  8. ^ Wise, David. «Eudoxus’ Influence on Euclid’s Elements with a close look at The Method of Exhaustion». jwilson.coe.uga.edu. Archived from the original on June 1, 2019. Retrieved October 26, 2019.
  9. ^ Alexander, Amir (2011). «The Skeleton in the Closet: Should Historians of Science Care about the History of Mathematics?». Isis. 102 (3): 475–480. doi:10.1086/661620. PMID 22073771. S2CID 21629993.
  10. ^ a b c d e f Kleiner, Israel (December 1991). «Rigor and Proof in Mathematics: A Historical Perspective». Mathematics Magazine. Taylor & Francis, Ltd. 64 (5): 291–314. doi:10.1080/0025570X.1991.11977625. JSTOR 2690647.
  11. ^ a b Harper, Douglas. «mathematic (n.)». Online Etymology Dictionary. Archived from the original on March 7, 2013. Retrieved November 26, 2022.
  12. ^ Both meanings can be found in Plato, the narrower in Republic. 510c. «Plato, Republic, Book 6, section 510c». Archived from the original on February 24, 2021. Retrieved June 19, 2019.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: bot: original URL status unknown (link), but Plato did not use a math- word; Aristotle did, commenting on it. μαθηματική. Liddell, Henry George; Scott, Robert; A Greek–English Lexicon at the Perseus Project. OED Online. Mathematics.
  13. ^ Harper, Douglas. «mathematical (adj.)». Online Etymology Dictionary. Archived from the original on November 26, 2022. Retrieved November 26, 2022.
  14. ^ Perisho, Margaret W. (Spring 1965). «The Etymology of Mathematical Terms». Pi Mu Epsilon Journal. 4 (2): 62–66. JSTOR 24338341.
  15. ^ Boas, Ralph (1995) [1991]. «What Augustine Didn’t Say About Mathematicians». Lion Hunting and Other Mathematical Pursuits: A Collection of Mathematics, Verse, and Stories by the Late Ralph P. Boas, Jr. Cambridge University Press. p. 257. ISBN 978-0-88385-323-8. Archived from the original on May 20, 2020. Retrieved January 17, 2018.
  16. ^ The Oxford Dictionary of English Etymology, Oxford English Dictionary, sub «mathematics», «mathematic», «mathematics».
  17. ^ «maths, n.» and «math, n.3» Archived April 4, 2020, at the Wayback Machine. Oxford English Dictionary, on-line version (2012).
  18. ^ Bell, E. T. (2012). The Development of Mathematics. Dover Books on Mathematics (reprint, revised ed.). Courier Corporation. p. 3. ISBN 9780486152288. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved November 11, 2022.
  19. ^ Tiwari, Sarju (1992). Mathematics in History, Culture, Philosophy, and Science. Mittal Publications. p. 27. ISBN 9788170994046. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved March 19, 2023.
  20. ^ Restivo, S. (December 2013). Mathematics in Society and History. Springer Netherlands. pp. 14–15. ISBN 9789401129442. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved March 19, 2023.
  21. ^ Musielak, Dora (2022). Leonhard Euler and the Foundations of Celestial Mechanics. Springer International Publishing. pp. 1–183. ISBN 9783031123221. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved March 19, 2023.
  22. ^ Biggs, N. L. (May 1979). «The roots of combinatorics». Historia Mathematica. 6 (2): 109–136. doi:10.1016/0315-0860(79)90074-0.
  23. ^ a b Warner, Evan (2013). «Splash Talk: The Foundational Crisis of Mathematics» (PDF). Columbia University. pp. 1–17. Archived (PDF) from the original on April 14, 2021. Retrieved November 4, 2022.
  24. ^ Dunne, Edward; Hulek, Klaus (March 2020). «Mathematics Subject Classification 2020» (PDF). Notices of the American Mathematical Society. 67 (3). Archived (PDF) from the original on November 20, 2022. Retrieved November 4, 2022.
  25. ^ a b c d e f g h «MSC2020-Mathematics Subject Classification System» (PDF). zbMath. Associate Editors of Mathematical Reviews and zbMATH. Archived (PDF) from the original on July 31, 2020. Retrieved November 26, 2022.
  26. ^ LeVeque, William J. (January 5, 2014). Fundamentals of Number Theory. Dover Publications. pp. 1–30. ISBN 9780486141503. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved March 19, 2023.
  27. ^ Goldman, Jay (1997). The Queen of Mathematics: A Historically Motivated Guide to Number Theory. CRC Press. pp. 1–3. ISBN 9781439864623. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved November 11, 2022.
  28. ^ Weil, André (2007). Number Theory, An Approach Through History From Hammurapi to Legendre. Birkhäuser Boston. pp. 1–3. ISBN 9780817645717. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved March 19, 2023.
  29. ^ Kleiner, Israel (February 2000). «From Fermat to Wiles: Fermat’s Last Theorem Becomes a Theorem». Elemente der Mathematik. 55: 19–37. doi:10.1007/PL00000079. S2CID 53319514.
  30. ^ Wang, Yuan (2002). The Goldbach Conjecture. Series in pure mathematics. Vol. 4 (revised ed.). World Scientific. pp. 1–18. ISBN 9789812776600. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved November 11, 2022.
  31. ^ a b c Straume, Eldar (September 2014). «A Survey of the Development of Geometry up to 1870». ePrint. arXiv:1409.1140. Bibcode:2014arXiv1409.1140S.
  32. ^ Hilbert, David (1962). The Foundations of Geometry. Open Court Publishing Company. p. 1. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved March 22, 2023.
  33. ^ Hartshorne, Robin (November 11, 2013). Geometry: Euclid and Beyond. Springer New York. pp. 9–13. ISBN 9780387226767. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved March 19, 2023.
  34. ^ Boyer, Carl B. (June 28, 2012). History of Analytic Geometry. Dover Publications. pp. 74–102. ISBN 9780486154510. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved March 19, 2023.
  35. ^ Stump, David J. (1997). «Reconstructing the Unity of Mathematics circa 1900». Perspectives on Science. 5 (3): 383. doi:10.1162/posc_a_00532. S2CID 117709681. Archived from the original on November 6, 2022. Retrieved November 6, 2022.
  36. ^ O’Connor, J. J.; Robertson, E. F. (February 1996). «Non-Euclidean geometry». MacTuror. School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland. Archived from the original on November 6, 2022. Retrieved November 6, 2022.
  37. ^ Joyner, D. (2008). Adventures in group theory: Rubik’s Cube, Merlin’s machine, and other mathematical toys (2nd ed.). Johns Hopkins University Press. pp. 219–232. ISBN 9780801890130.
  38. ^ Christianidis, Jean; Oaks, Jeffrey (May 2013). «Practicing algebra in late antiquity: The problem-solving of Diophantus of Alexandria». Historia Mathematica. 40 (2): 127–163. doi:10.1016/j.hm.2012.09.001.
  39. ^ Kleiner 2007, «History of Classical Algebra» pp. 3–5.
  40. ^ Lim, Lisa (December 21, 2018). «Where algebra got its x from, and Xmas its X». South China Morning Post. Archived from the original on August 9, 2022. Retrieved August 9, 2022.
  41. ^ Oaks, J. A. (2018). «François Viète’s revolution in algebra» (PDF). Archive for History of Exact Sciences. 72 (3): 245–302. doi:10.1007/s00407-018-0208-0. S2CID 125704699. Archived (PDF) from the original on November 8, 2022. Retrieved November 8, 2022.
  42. ^ Kleiner 2007, «History of Linear Algebra» pp. 79–101.
  43. ^ Corry, Leo (December 6, 2012). Modern Algebra and the Rise of Mathematical Structures. Birkhäuser Basel. pp. 247–252. ISBN 9783034879170. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved March 19, 2023.
  44. ^ Riche, Jacques (2007). Beziau, J. Y.; Costa-Leite, Alexandre (eds.). From Universal Algebra to Universal Logic. Perspective on Universal Logic. Italy: Polimetrica International Scientific. pp. 3–39. ISBN 9788876990779. Archived from the original on March 7, 2023. Retrieved November 25, 2022.
  45. ^ Krömer, Ralph (2007). Tool and Object: A History and Philosophy of Category Theory. Science Networks. Historical Studies. Vol. 32. Springer Science & Business Media. pp. xxi–xxv, 1–91. ISBN 9783764375249. Archived from the original on March 7, 2023. Retrieved November 25, 2022.
  46. ^ Guicciardini, Niccolo (2017). «The Newton–Leibniz Calculus Controversy, 1708–1730» (PDF). In Schliesser, Eric; Smeenk, Chris (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Newton. Oxford handbooks. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199930418.013.9. ISBN 9780199930418. Archived (PDF) from the original on November 9, 2022. Retrieved November 9, 2022.
  47. ^ O’Connor, J. J.; Robertson, E. F. (September 1998). «Leonhard Euler». MacTutor. School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland. Archived from the original on November 9, 2022. Retrieved November 9, 2022.
  48. ^ Franklin, James (2017). «Discrete and continuous: a fundamental dichotomy in mathematics». Journal of Humanistic Mathematics. 7 (2): 355–378. doi:10.5642/jhummath.201702.18. S2CID 6945363. Archived from the original on November 10, 2022. Retrieved November 10, 2022.
  49. ^ Maurer, Stephen B. (1997). Rosenstein, Joseph G.; Franzblau, Deborah S.; Roberts, Fred S. (eds.). What is Discrete Mathematics? The Many Answers. Discrete Mathematics in the Schools. DIMACS: Series in Discrete Mathematics and Theoretical Computer Science. Vol. 36. American Mathematical Society. pp. 121–124. ISBN 9780821885789. Archived from the original on November 10, 2022. Retrieved November 10, 2022.
  50. ^ Downey, Rod (2014). Turing’s Legacy: Developments from Turing’s Ideas in Logic. Issue 42 of Lecture Notes in Logic. Cambridge University Press. pp. 260–261. ISBN 9781107043480. Archived from the original on November 10, 2022. Retrieved November 10, 2022.
  51. ^ Sipser, Michael (July 1992). The history and status of the P versus NP question. STOC ’92: Proceedings of the twenty-fourth annual ACM symposium on Theory of Computing. pp. 603–618. doi:10.1145/129712.129771.
  52. ^ Ewald, William (November 17, 2018). «The Emergence of First-Order Logic». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on May 12, 2021. Retrieved November 2, 2022.
  53. ^ Ferreirós, José (June 18, 2020). «The Early Development of Set Theory». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on May 12, 2021. Retrieved November 2, 2022.
  54. ^ Ferreirós, José (2001). «The Road to Modern Logic—An Interpretation» (PDF). Bulletin of Symbolic Logic. 7 (4): 441–484. doi:10.2307/2687794. hdl:11441/38373. JSTOR 2687794. S2CID 43258676. Retrieved November 11, 2022.
  55. ^ Wolchover, Natalie (December 3, 2013). «Dispute over Infinity Divides Mathematicians». Scientific American. Archived from the original on November 2, 2022. Retrieved November 1, 2022.
  56. ^ Zhuang, C. «Wittgenstein’s analysis on Cantor’s diagonal argument». PhilArchive. Retrieved November 18, 2022.
  57. ^ Avigad, Jeremy; Reck, Erich H. (December 11, 2001). ««Clarifying the nature of the infinite»: the development of metamathematics and proof theory» (PDF). Carnegie Mellon Technical Report CMU-PHIL-120. Archived (PDF) from the original on October 9, 2022. Retrieved November 12, 2022.
  58. ^ Hamilton, Alan G. (1982). Numbers, Sets and Axioms: The Apparatus of Mathematics. Cambridge University Press. pp. 3–4. ISBN 9780521287616. Archived from the original on November 12, 2022. Retrieved November 12, 2022.
  59. ^ a b Snapper, Ernst (September 1979). «The Three Crises in Mathematics: Logicism, Intuitionism, and Formalism». Mathematics Magazine. 52 (4): 207–16. doi:10.2307/2689412. JSTOR 2689412.
  60. ^ a b Raatikainen, Panu (October 2005). «On the Philosophical Relevance of Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems». Revue Internationale de Philosophie. 59 (4): 513–534. doi:10.3917/rip.234.0513. JSTOR 23955909. S2CID 52083793. Archived from the original on November 12, 2022. Retrieved November 12, 2022.
  61. ^ Moschovakis, Joan (September 4, 2018). «Intuitionistic Logic». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on December 16, 2022. Retrieved November 12, 2022.
  62. ^ McCarty, Charles (2006). «At the Heart of Analysis: Intuitionism and Philosophy». Philosophia Scientiæ, Cahier spécial 6: 81–94. doi:10.4000/philosophiascientiae.411.
  63. ^ Halpern, Joseph; Harper, Robert; Immerman, Neil; Kolaitis, Phokion; Vardi, Moshe; Vianu, Victor (2001). «On the Unusual Effectiveness of Logic in Computer Science» (PDF). Archived (PDF) from the original on March 3, 2021. Retrieved January 15, 2021.
  64. ^ Rouaud, Mathieu (2013). Probability, Statistics and Estimation (PDF). p. 10. Archived (PDF) from the original on October 9, 2022.
  65. ^ Rao, C.R. (1997). Statistics and Truth: Putting Chance to Work. World Scientific. ISBN 978-981-02-3111-8.
  66. ^ Rao, C.R. (1981). «Foreword». In Arthanari, T.S.; Dodge, Yadolah (eds.). Mathematical programming in statistics. Wiley Series in Probability and Mathematical Statistics. New York: Wiley. pp. vii–viii. ISBN 978-0-471-08073-2. MR 0607328.
  67. ^ Whittle 1994, pp. 10–11, 14–18.
  68. ^ Marchuk, Gurii Ivanovich (April 2020). «G I Marchuk’s plenary: ICM 1970». MacTutor. School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland. Archived from the original on November 13, 2022. Retrieved November 13, 2022.
  69. ^ Johnson, Gary M.; Cavallini, John S. (September 1991). Phua, Kang Hoh; Loe, Kia Fock (eds.). Grand Challenges, High Performance Computing, and Computational Science. Singapore Supercomputing Conference’90: Supercomputing For Strategic Advantage. World Scientific. p. 28. Archived from the original on November 13, 2022. Retrieved November 13, 2022.
  70. ^ Trefethen, Lloyd N. (2008). Gowers, Timothy; Barrow-Green, June; Leader, Imre (eds.). Numerical Analysis (PDF). The Princeton Companion to Mathematics. Princeton University Press. pp. 604–615. ISBN 9780691118802. Archived (PDF) from the original on March 7, 2023. Retrieved November 13, 2022.
  71. ^ Dehaene, Stanislas; Dehaene-Lambertz, Ghislaine; Cohen, Laurent (August 1998). «Abstract representations of numbers in the animal and human brain». Trends in Neurosciences. 21 (8): 355–61. doi:10.1016/S0166-2236(98)01263-6. PMID 9720604. S2CID 17414557.
  72. ^ See, for example, Wilder, Raymond L. Evolution of Mathematical Concepts; an Elementary Study. passim.
  73. ^ Zaslavsky, Claudia (1999). Africa Counts: Number and Pattern in African Culture. Chicago Review Press. ISBN 978-1-61374-115-3. OCLC 843204342.
  74. ^ Kline 1990, Chapter 1.
  75. ^ Boyer 1991, «Mesopotamia» pp. 24–27.
  76. ^ Heath, Thomas Little (1981) [1921]. A History of Greek Mathematics: From Thales to Euclid. New York: Dover Publications. p. 1. ISBN 978-0-486-24073-2.
  77. ^ Mueller, I. (1969). «Euclid’s Elements and the Axiomatic Method». The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 20 (4): 289–309. doi:10.1093/bjps/20.4.289. ISSN 0007-0882. JSTOR 686258.
  78. ^ Boyer 1991, «Euclid of Alexandria» p. 119.
  79. ^ Boyer 1991, «Archimedes of Syracuse» p. 120.
  80. ^ Boyer 1991, «Archimedes of Syracuse» p. 130.
  81. ^ Boyer 1991, «Apollonius of Perga» p. 145.
  82. ^ Boyer 1991, «Greek Trigonometry and Mensuration» p. 162.
  83. ^ Boyer 1991, «Revival and Decline of Greek Mathematics» p. 180.
  84. ^ Ore, Øystein (1988). Number Theory and Its History. Courier Corporation. pp. 19–24. ISBN 9780486656205. Archived from the original on November 14, 2022. Retrieved November 14, 2022.
  85. ^ Singh, A. N. (January 1936). «On the Use of Series in Hindu Mathematics». Osiris. 1: 606–628. doi:10.1086/368443. JSTOR 301627. S2CID 144760421.
  86. ^ Kolachana, A.; Mahesh, K.; Ramasubramanian, K. (2019). Use of series in India. Studies in Indian Mathematics and Astronomy. Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences. Singapore: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-981-13-7326-8_20. ISBN 978-981-13-7325-1. S2CID 190176726.
  87. ^ Saliba, George (1994). A history of Arabic astronomy: planetary theories during the golden age of Islam. New York University Press. ISBN 978-0-8147-7962-0. OCLC 28723059.
  88. ^ Faruqi, Yasmeen M. (2006). «Contributions of Islamic scholars to the scientific enterprise». International Education Journal. Shannon Research Press. 7 (4): 391–399. Archived from the original on November 14, 2022. Retrieved November 14, 2022.
  89. ^ Lorch, Richard (June 2001). «Greek-Arabic-Latin: The Transmission of Mathematical Texts in the Middle Ages» (PDF). Science in Context. Cambridge University Press. 14 (1–2): 313–331. doi:10.1017/S0269889701000114. S2CID 146539132. Archived (PDF) from the original on December 17, 2022. Retrieved December 5, 2022.
  90. ^ Archibald, Raymond Clare (January 1949). «History of Mathematics After the Sixteenth Century». The American Mathematical Monthly. Part 2: Outline of the History of Mathematics. 56 (1): 35–56. doi:10.2307/2304570. JSTOR 2304570.
  91. ^ Sevryuk 2006, pp. 101–09.
  92. ^ Wolfram, Stephan (October 2000). Mathematical notation: Past and future. MathML and Math on the Web: MathML International Conference 2000, Urbana Champaign, USA. Archived from the original on November 16, 2022. Retrieved November 16, 2022.
  93. ^ Douglas, Heather; Headley, Marcia Gail; Hadden, Stephanie; LeFevre, Jo-Anne (December 3, 2020). «Knowledge of Mathematical Symbols Goes Beyond Numbers». Journal of Numerical Cognition. 6 (3): 322–354. doi:10.5964/jnc.v6i3.293. S2CID 228085700.
  94. ^ Letourneau, Mary; Wright Sharp, Jennifer (2017). «AMS style guide» (PDF). American Mathematical Society. p. 75. Archived (PDF) from the original on December 8, 2022. Retrieved November 16, 2022.
  95. ^ Jansen, A. R.; Marriott, K.; Yelland, G. W. (2000). Constituent structure in mathematical expressions (PDF). Proceedings of the 22th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society. Vol. 22. p. 238. Archived (PDF) from the original on November 16, 2022. Retrieved November 16, 2022.
  96. ^ Rossi, Richard J. (2011). Theorems, Corollaries, Lemmas, and Methods of Proof. Pure and Applied Mathematics: A Wiley Series of Texts, Monographs and Tracts. John Wiley & Sons. pp. 1–14, 47–48. ISBN 9781118030578. Archived from the original on November 17, 2022. Retrieved November 17, 2022.
  97. ^ «Earliest Uses of Some Words of Mathematics». MacTutor. School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland. Archived from the original on September 29, 2022. Retrieved November 19, 2022.
  98. ^ Silver, Daniel S. (2017). «The New Language of Mathematics». The American Scientist. 105 (6): 364–371. doi:10.1511/2017.105.6.364. Archived from the original on October 22, 2022. Retrieved November 19, 2022.
  99. ^ Bellomo, Nicola; Preziosi, Luigi (December 22, 1994). Modelling Mathematical Methods and Scientific Computation. Mathematical Modeling. Vol. 1. CRC Press. p. 1. ISBN 9780849383311. Archived from the original on November 16, 2022. Retrieved November 16, 2022.
  100. ^ Hennig, Christian (2010). «Mathematical Models and Reality: A Constructivist Perspective». Foundations of Science. 15: 29–48. doi:10.1007/s10699-009-9167-x. S2CID 6229200. Retrieved November 17, 2022.
  101. ^ Frigg, Roman; Hartmann, Stephan (February 4, 2020). «Models in Science». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on November 17, 2022. Retrieved November 17, 2022.
  102. ^ Stewart, Ian (2018). «Mathematics, Maps, and Models». In Wuppuluri, Shyam; Doria, Francisco Antonio (eds.). The Map and the Territory: Exploring the Foundations of Science, Thought and Reality. The Frontiers Collection. Springer. pp. 345–356. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-72478-2_18. ISBN 9783319724782. Archived from the original on March 7, 2023. Retrieved November 17, 2022.
  103. ^ «The science checklist applied: Mathematics». undsci.berkeley.edu. Archived from the original on October 27, 2019. Retrieved October 27, 2019.
  104. ^ Mackay, A. L. (1991). Dictionary of Scientific Quotations. London: Taylor & Francis. p. 100. ISBN 9780750301060. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved March 19, 2023.
  105. ^ Bishop, Alan (1991). «Environmental activities and mathematical culture». Mathematical Enculturation: A Cultural Perspective on Mathematics Education. Norwell, Massachusetts: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 20–59. ISBN 978-0-7923-1270-3. Archived from the original on December 25, 2020. Retrieved April 5, 2020.
  106. ^ Shasha, Dennis Elliot; Lazere, Cathy A. (1998). Out of Their Minds: The Lives and Discoveries of 15 Great Computer Scientists. Springer. p. 228. ISBN 9780387982694.
  107. ^ Nickles, Thomas (2013). «The Problem of Demarcation». Philosophy of Pseudoscience: Reconsidering the Demarcation Problem. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. p. 104. ISBN 9780226051826.
  108. ^ Pigliucci, Massimo (2014). «Are There ‘Other’ Ways of Knowing?». Philosophy Now. Archived from the original on May 13, 2020. Retrieved April 6, 2020.
  109. ^ a b Ferreirós, J. (2007). «Ό Θεὸς Άριθμητίζει: The Rise of Pure Mathematics as Arithmetic with Gauss». In Goldstein, Catherine; Schappacher, Norbert; Schwermer, Joachim (eds.). The Shaping of Arithmetic after C.F. Gauss’s Disquisitiones Arithmeticae. Springer Science & Business Media. pp. 235–268. ISBN 9783540347200.
  110. ^ Kuhn, Thomas S. (1976). «Mathematical vs. Experimental Traditions in the Development of Physical Science». The Journal of Interdisciplinary History. The MIT Press. 7 (1): 1–31. doi:10.2307/202372. JSTOR 202372.
  111. ^ Asper, Markus (2009). «The two cultures of mathematics in ancient Greece». In Robson, Eleanor; Stedall, Jacqueline (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of the History of Mathematics. Oxford Handbooks in Mathematics. OUP Oxford. pp. 107–132. ISBN 9780199213122. Archived from the original on November 18, 2022. Retrieved November 18, 2022.
  112. ^ Maddy, P. (2008). «How applied mathematics became pure» (PDF). The Review of Symbolic Logic. 1 (1): 16–41. doi:10.1017/S1755020308080027. S2CID 18122406. Archived from the original on August 12, 2017. Retrieved November 19, 2022.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: bot: original URL status unknown (link)
  113. ^ Silver, Daniel S. (2017). «In Defense of Pure Mathematics». In Pitici, Mircea (ed.). The Best Writing on Mathematics, 2016. Princeton University Press. pp. 17–26. ISBN 9780691175294. Archived from the original on November 19, 2022. Retrieved November 19, 2022.
  114. ^ Parshall, Karen Hunger (2022). «The American Mathematical Society and Applied Mathematics from the 1920s to the 1950s: A Revisionist Account». Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society. 59 (3): 405–427. doi:10.1090/bull/1754. S2CID 249561106. Archived from the original on November 20, 2022. Retrieved November 20, 2022.
  115. ^ Stolz, Michael (2002). «The History Of Applied Mathematics And The History Of Society». Synthese. 133: 43–57. doi:10.1023/A:1020823608217. S2CID 34271623. Retrieved November 20, 2022.
  116. ^ Lin, C. C . (March 1976). «On the role of applied mathematics». Advances in Mathematics. 19 (3): 267–288. doi:10.1016/0001-8708(76)90024-4.
  117. ^ Peressini, Anthony (September 1999). Applying Pure Mathematics (PDF). Philosophy of Science. Proceedings of the 1998 Biennial Meetings of the Philosophy of Science Association. Part I: Contributed Papers. Vol. 66. pp. S1–S13. JSTOR 188757. Retrieved November 30, 2022.
  118. ^ Lützen, J. (2011). «Examples and reflections on the interplay between mathematics and physics in the 19th and 20th century». In Schlote, K. H.; Schneider, M. (eds.). Mathematics meets physics: A contribution to their interaction in the 19th and the first half of the 20th century. Frankfurt am Main: Verlag Harri Deutsch. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved November 19, 2022.
  119. ^ Marker, Dave (July 1996). «Model theory and exponentiation». Notices of the American Mathematical Society. 43 (7): 753–759. Archived from the original on March 13, 2014. Retrieved November 19, 2022.
  120. ^ Chen, Changbo; Maza, Marc Moreno (August 2014). Cylindrical Algebraic Decomposition in the RegularChains Library. International Congress on Mathematical Software 2014. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Vol. 8592. Berlin: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-662-44199-2_65. Retrieved November 19, 2022.
  121. ^ Pérez-Escobar, José Antonio; Sarikaya, Deniz (2021). «Purifying applied mathematics and applying pure mathematics: how a late Wittgensteinian perspective sheds light onto the dichotomy». European Journal for Philosophy of Science. 12 (1): 1–22. doi:10.1007/s13194-021-00435-9. S2CID 245465895.
  122. ^ Takase, M. (2014). «Pure Mathematics and Applied Mathematics are Inseparably Intertwined: Observation of the Early Analysis of the Infinity». A Mathematical Approach to Research Problems of Science and Technology. Mathematics for Industry. Vol. 5. Tokyo: Springer. pp. 393–399. doi:10.1007/978-4-431-55060-0_29. ISBN 978-4-431-55059-4. Archived from the original on November 20, 2022. Retrieved November 20, 2022.
  123. ^ Sarukkai, Sundar (February 10, 2005). «Revisiting the ‘unreasonable effectiveness’ of mathematics». Current Science. 88 (3): 415–423. JSTOR 24110208.
  124. ^ Wagstaff, Jr., Samuel S. (2021). «History of Integer Factoring» (PDF). In Bos, Joppe W.; Stam, Martijn (eds.). Computational Cryptography, Algorithmic Aspects of Cryptography, A Tribute to AKL. London Mathematical Society Lecture Notes Series 469. Cambridge University Press. pp. 41–77. Archived (PDF) from the original on November 20, 2022. Retrieved November 20, 2022.
  125. ^ «Curves: Ellipse». MacTutor. School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland. Archived from the original on October 14, 2022. Retrieved November 20, 2022.
  126. ^ Mukunth, Vasudevan (September 10, 2015). «Beyond the Surface of Einstein’s Relativity Lay a Chimerical Geometry». The Wire. Archived from the original on November 20, 2022. Retrieved November 20, 2022.
  127. ^ Wilson, Edwin B.; Lewis, Gilbert N. (November 1912). «The Space-Time Manifold of Relativity. The Non-Euclidean Geometry of Mechanics and Electromagnetics». Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. 48 (11): 389–507. doi:10.2307/20022840. JSTOR 20022840.
  128. ^ a b c Borel, Armand (1983). «Mathematics: Art and Science». The Mathematical Intelligencer. Springer. 5 (4): 9–17. doi:10.4171/news/103/8. ISSN 1027-488X.
  129. ^ Hanson, Norwood Russell (November 1961). «Discovering the Positron (I)». The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. The University of Chicago Press. 12 (47): 194–214. doi:10.1093/bjps/xiii.49.54. JSTOR 685207.
  130. ^ Ginammi, Michele (February 2016). «Avoiding reification: Heuristic effectiveness of mathematics and the prediction of the Ω particle». Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 53: 20–27. Bibcode:2016SHPMP..53…20G. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2015.12.001.
  131. ^ Wagh, Sanjay Moreshwar; Deshpande, Dilip Abasaheb (September 27, 2012). ESSENTIALS OF PHYSICS. PHI Learning Pvt. Ltd. p. 3. ISBN 978-81-203-4642-0. Archived from the original on October 5, 2020. Retrieved January 3, 2023.
  132. ^ Atiyah, Michael (1990). On the Work of Edward Witten (PDF). Proceedings of the International Congress of Mathematicians. p. 31. Archived from the original (PDF) on September 28, 2013. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  133. ^ Borwein, J.; Borwein, P.; Girgensohn, R.; Parnes, S. (1996). «Conclusion». oldweb.cecm.sfu.ca. Archived from the original on January 21, 2008.
  134. ^ Hales, Thomas; Adams, Mark; Bauer, Gertrud; Dang, Tat Dat; Harrison, John; Hoang, Le Truong; Kaliszyk, Cezary; Magron, Victor; Mclaughlin, Sean; Nguyen, Tat Thang; Nguyen, Quang Truong; Nipkow, Tobias; Obua, Steven; Pleso, Joseph; Rute, Jason; Solovyev, Alexey; Ta, Thi Hoai An; Tran, Nam Trung; Trieu, Thi Diep; Urban, Josef; Vu, Ky; Zumkeller, Roland (2017). «A Formal Proof of the Kepler Conjecture». Forum of Mathematics, Pi. 5: e2. doi:10.1017/fmp.2017.1. ISSN 2050-5086. S2CID 216912822. Archived from the original on December 4, 2020. Retrieved February 25, 2023.
  135. ^ a b Geuvers, H. (February 2009). «Proof assistants: History, ideas and future». Sādhanā. 34: 3–4. doi:10.1007/s12046-009-0001-5. S2CID 14827467. Archived from the original on December 29, 2022. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  136. ^ «P versus NP problem | mathematics | Britannica». www.britannica.com. Archived from the original on December 6, 2022. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  137. ^ a b c Millstein, Roberta (September 8, 2016). «Probability in Biology: The Case of Fitness» (PDF). In Hájek, Alan; Hitchcock, Christopher (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Probability and Philosophy. pp. 601–622. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199607617.013.27. Archived (PDF) from the original on March 7, 2023. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  138. ^ See for example Anne Laurent, Roland Gamet, Jérôme Pantel, Tendances nouvelles en modélisation pour l’environnement, actes du congrès «Programme environnement, vie et sociétés» 15-17 janvier 1996, CNRS
  139. ^ Bouleau 1999, pp. 282–283.
  140. ^ Bouleau 1999, p. 285.
  141. ^ «1.4: The Lotka-Volterra Predator-Prey Model». Mathematics LibreTexts. January 5, 2022. Archived from the original on December 29, 2022. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  142. ^ Bouleau 1999, p. 287.
  143. ^ a b Zak, Paul J. (December 16, 2010). Moral Markets: The Critical Role of Values in the Economy. Princeton University Press. p. 158. ISBN 978-1-4008-3736-6. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2023.
  144. ^ a b c d Kim, Oliver W. (May 29, 2014). «Meet Homo Economicus». The Harvard Crimson. Archived from the original on December 29, 2022. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  145. ^ «Kondratiev, Nikolai Dmitrievich | Encyclopedia.com». www.encyclopedia.com. Archived from the original on July 1, 2016. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  146. ^ Dictionnaire en économie et science sociale, Ed.Nathan Paris, dictionnaire Larousse en 3. vol, Paris. Les définitions des cycles sont nombreuses, entre autres, en sciences: évolution de systèmes qui les ramènent à leur état initial ou, en sociologie, mouvement(s) récurrent(s) d’activité(s) politique(s) et économique(s).[full citation needed]
  147. ^ «Cliodynamics: a science for predicting the future». ZDNET. Archived from the original on December 29, 2022. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  148. ^ Wolchover, Natalie (August 3, 2012). «Will the US Really Experience a Violent Upheaval in 2020?». Live Science. Archived from the original on December 29, 2022. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  149. ^ Beaujouan, Guy (1994). Comprendre et maîtriser la nature au Moyen Age: mélanges d’histoire des sciences offerts à Guy Beaujouan (in French). Librairie Droz. p. 130. ISBN 978-2-600-00040-6. Archived from the original on March 7, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2023.
  150. ^ «L’astrologie à l’épreuve : ça ne marche pas, ça n’a jamais marché ! / Afis Science — Association française pour l’information scientifique». Afis Science — Association française pour l’information scientifique (in French). Archived from the original on January 29, 2023. Retrieved December 28, 2022.
  151. ^ Balaguer, Mark (2016). «Platonism in Metaphysics». In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on January 30, 2022. Retrieved April 2, 2022.
  152. ^ See White, L. (1947). «The locus of mathematical reality: An anthropological footnote». Philosophy of Science. 14 (4): 289–303. doi:10.1086/286957. S2CID 119887253. 189303; also in Newman, J. R. (1956). The World of Mathematics. Vol. 4. New York: Simon and Schuster. pp. 2348–2364.
  153. ^ Dorato, Mauro (2005). «Why are laws mathematical?» (PDF). The Software of the Universe, An Introduction to the History and Philosophy of Laws of Nature. Ashgate. pp. 31–66. ISBN 9780754639947. Retrieved December 5, 2022.
  154. ^ a b c Mura, Roberta (December 1993). «Images of Mathematics Held by University Teachers of Mathematical Sciences». Educational Studies in Mathematics. 25 (4): 375–85. doi:10.1007/BF01273907. JSTOR 3482762. S2CID 122351146.
  155. ^ a b Tobies, Renate; Neunzert, Helmut (2012). Iris Runge: A Life at the Crossroads of Mathematics, Science, and Industry. Springer. p. 9. ISBN 978-3-0348-0229-1. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved June 20, 2015. [I]t is first necessary to ask what is meant by mathematics in general. Illustrious scholars have debated this matter until they were blue in the face, and yet no consensus has been reached about whether mathematics is a natural science, a branch of the humanities, or an art form.
  156. ^ Ziegler, Günter M.; Loos, Andreas (November 2, 2017). Kaiser, G. (ed.). «What is Mathematics?» and why we should ask, where one should experience and learn that, and how to teach it. Proceedings of the 13th International Congress on Mathematical Education. ICME-13 Monographs. Springer. pp. 63–77. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-62597-3_5. ISBN 978-3-319-62596-6.
  157. ^ Franklin, James (July 8, 2009). Philosophy of Mathematics. pp. 104–106. ISBN 978-0-08-093058-9. Archived from the original on January 19, 2023. Retrieved June 20, 2015.
  158. ^ Cajori, Florian (1893). A History of Mathematics. American Mathematical Society (1991 reprint). pp. 285–286. ISBN 978-0-8218-2102-2. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved June 20, 2015.
  159. ^ Brown, Ronald; Porter, Timothy (January 2000). «The Methodology of Mathematics». The Mathematical Gazette. 79 (485): 321–334. doi:10.2307/3618304. JSTOR 3618304. S2CID 178923299. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved November 25, 2022.
  160. ^ Strauss, Danie (2011). «Defining mathematics». Acta Academica. 43 (4): 1–28. Retrieved November 25, 2022.
  161. ^ Hamami, Yacin (June 2022). «Mathematical Rigor and Proof» (PDF). The Review of Symbolic Logic. 15 (2): 409–449. doi:10.1017/S1755020319000443. S2CID 209980693. Archived (PDF) from the original on December 5, 2022. Retrieved November 21, 2022.
  162. ^ Peterson, Ivars (1988). The Mathematical Tourist. Freeman. p. 4. ISBN 978-0-7167-1953-3. A few complain that the computer program can’t be verified properly, (in reference to the Haken–Apple proof of the Four Color Theorem).
  163. ^ Perminov, V. Ya. (1988). «On the Reliability of Mathematical Proofs». Philosophy of Mathematics. Revue Internationale de Philosophie. 42 (167 (4)): 500–508.
  164. ^ Davis, Jon D.; McDuffie, Amy Roth; Drake, Corey; Seiwelld, Amanda L. (2019). «Teachers’ perceptions of the official curriculum: Problem solving and rigor». International Journal of Educational Research. 93: 91–100. doi:10.1016/j.ijer.2018.10.002. S2CID 149753721.
  165. ^ Endsley, Kezia (2021). Mathematicians and Statisticians: A Practical Career Guide. Practical Career Guides. Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 1–3. ISBN 9781538145173. Archived from the original on November 29, 2022. Retrieved November 29, 2022.
  166. ^ Robson, Eleanor (2009). «Mathematics education in an Old Babylonian scribal school». In Robson, Eleanor; Stedall, Jacqueline (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of the History of Mathematics. OUP Oxford. ISBN 9780199213122. Archived from the original on November 24, 2022. Retrieved November 24, 2022.
  167. ^ Bernard, Alain; Proust, Christine; Ross, Micah (2014). «Mathematics Education in Antiquity». In Karp, A.; Schubring, G. (eds.). Handbook on the History of Mathematics Education. New York: Springer. pp. 27–53. doi:10.1007/978-1-4614-9155-2_3. ISBN 978-1-4614-9154-5.
  168. ^ Dudley, Underwood (April 2002). «The World’s First Mathematics Textbook». Math Horizons. Taylor & Francis, Ltd. 9 (4): 8–11. doi:10.1080/10724117.2002.11975154. JSTOR 25678363. S2CID 126067145.
  169. ^ Subramarian, F. Indian pedagogy and problem solving in ancient Thamizhakam (PDF). History and Pedagogy of Mathematics conference, 16–20 July 2012. Archived (PDF) from the original on November 28, 2022. Retrieved November 29, 2022.
  170. ^ Siu, Man Keung (2004). «Official Curriculum in Mathematics in Ancient China: How did Candidates Study for the Examination?». How Chinese Learn Mathematics (PDF). Series on Mathematics Education. Vol. 1. pp. 157–185. doi:10.1142/9789812562241_0006. ISBN 978-981-256-014-8. Retrieved November 26, 2022.
  171. ^ Jones, Phillip S. (1967). «The History of Mathematical Education». The American Mathematical Monthly. Taylor & Francis, Ltd. 74 (1): 38–55. doi:10.2307/2314867. JSTOR 2314867.
  172. ^ Schubring, Gert; Furinghetti, Fulvia; Siu, Man Keung (August 2012). «Introduction: the history of mathematics teaching. Indicators for modernization processes in societies». ZDM Mathematics Education. 44 (4): 457–459. doi:10.1007/s11858-012-0445-7. S2CID 145507519.
  173. ^ von Davier, Matthias; Foy, Pierre; Martin, Michael O.; Mullis, Ina V.S. (2020). «Examining eTIMSS Country Differences Between eTIMSS Data and Bridge Data: A Look at Country-Level Mode of Administration Effects». TIMSS 2019 International Results in Mathematics and Science (PDF). TIMSS & PIRLS International Study Center, Lynch School of Education and Human Development, Boston College and International Association for the Evaluation of Educational Achievement. p. 13.1. ISBN 978-1-889938-54-7. Archived (PDF) from the original on November 29, 2022. Retrieved November 29, 2022.
  174. ^ Rowan-Kenyon, Heather T.; Swan, Amy K.; Creager, Marie F. (March 2012). «Social Cognitive Factors, Support, and Engagement: Early Adolescents’ Math Interests as Precursors to Choice of Career» (PDF). The Career Development Quarterly. 60 (1): 2–15. doi:10.1002/j.2161-0045.2012.00001.x. Retrieved November 29, 2022.
  175. ^ Luttenberger, Silke; Wimmer, Sigrid; Paechter, Manuela (2018). «Spotlight on math anxiety». Psychology Research and Behavior Management. 11: 311–322. doi:10.2147/PRBM.S141421. PMC 6087017. PMID 30123014.
  176. ^ Yaftian, Narges (June 2, 2015). «The Outlook of the Mathematicians’ Creative Processes». Procedia — Social and Behavioral Sciences. 191: 2519–2525. doi:10.1016/j.sbspro.2015.04.617.
  177. ^ Nadjafikhah, Mehdi; Yaftian, Narges (October 10, 2013). «The Frontage of Creativity and Mathematical Creativity». Procedia — Social and Behavioral Sciences. 90: 344–350. doi:10.1016/j.sbspro.2013.07.101.
  178. ^ van der Poorten, A. (1979). «A proof that Euler missed… Apéry’s Proof of the irrationality of ζ(3)» (PDF). The Mathematical Intelligencer. 1 (4): 195–203. doi:10.1007/BF03028234. S2CID 121589323. Archived (PDF) from the original on September 6, 2015. Retrieved November 22, 2022.
  179. ^ Petkovi, Miodrag (September 2, 2009). Famous Puzzles of Great Mathematicians. American Mathematical Society. pp. xiii–xiv. ISBN 9780821848142. Archived from the original on March 7, 2023. Retrieved November 25, 2022.
  180. ^ Hardy, G. H. (1940). A Mathematician’s Apology. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-42706-7. Retrieved November 22, 2022. See also A Mathematician’s Apology.
  181. ^ Alon, Noga; Goldston, Dan; Sárközy, András; Szabados, József; Tenenbaum, Gérald; Garcia, Stephan Ramon; Shoemaker, Amy L. (March 2015). Alladi, Krishnaswami; Krantz, Steven G. (eds.). «Reflections on Paul Erdős on His Birth Centenary, Part II». Notices of the American Mathematical Society. 62 (3): 226–247. doi:10.1090/noti1223.
  182. ^ See, for example Bertrand Russell’s statement «Mathematics, rightly viewed, possesses not only truth, but supreme beauty …» in his History of Western Philosophy. 1919. p. 60.
  183. ^ a b Iemhoff, Rosalie (2020). «Intuitionism in the Philosophy of Mathematics». In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2020 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on April 21, 2022. Retrieved April 2, 2022.
  184. ^ «Musical Mathematics: Just Intonation – The Chrysalis Foundation». www.chrysalis-foundation.org. Archived from the original on December 29, 2022. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  185. ^ «Just Intonation Explained». www.kylegann.com. Archived from the original on December 29, 2022. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  186. ^ Rameau, Jean-Philippe (1986) [1722]. «Traité de l’harmonie réduite à ses principes naturels». Collection de musicologie. Paris: Méridiens Klincksieck [fr]. p. 432. ISBN 978-2-86563-157-5.
  187. ^ Enquist, Magnus; Arak, Anthony (November 1994). «Symmetry, beauty and evolution». Nature. 372 (6502): 169–172. Bibcode:1994Natur.372..169E. doi:10.1038/372169a0. ISSN 1476-4687. PMID 7969448. S2CID 4310147. Archived from the original on December 28, 2022. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  188. ^ Hestenes, David (1999). «Symmetry Groups» (PDF). geocalc.clas.asu.edu. Archived (PDF) from the original on January 1, 2023. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  189. ^ Bradley, Larry (2010). «Fractals — Chaos & Fractals». www.stsci.edu. Archived from the original on March 7, 2023. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  190. ^ «Self-similarity». math.bu.edu. Archived from the original on March 2, 2023. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  191. ^ Kissane, Barry (July 2009). Popular mathematics. 22nd Biennial Conference of The Australian Association of Mathematics Teachers. Fremantle, Western Australia: Australian Association of Mathematics Teachers. pp. 125–126. Archived from the original on March 7, 2023. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  192. ^ Steen, L. A. (December 6, 2012). Mathematics Today Twelve Informal Essays. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 2. ISBN 978-1-4613-9435-8. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2023.
  193. ^ Pitici, Mircea (February 14, 2017). The Best Writing on Mathematics 2016. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-1-4008-8560-2. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2023.
  194. ^ Monastyrsky 2001, p. 1: «The Fields Medal is now indisputably the best known and most influential award in mathematics.»
  195. ^ Riehm 2002, pp. 778–82.
  196. ^ «Fields Medal | International Mathematical Union (IMU)». www.mathunion.org. Archived from the original on December 26, 2018. Retrieved February 21, 2022.
  197. ^ a b «Fields Medal». Maths History. Archived from the original on March 22, 2019. Retrieved February 21, 2022.
  198. ^ «Honours/Prizes Index». MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive. Archived from the original on December 17, 2021. Retrieved February 20, 2023.
  199. ^ «About the Abel Prize». The Abel Prize. Archived from the original on April 14, 2022. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  200. ^ «Abel Prize | mathematics award». Encyclopedia Britannica. Archived from the original on January 26, 2020. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  201. ^ «CHERN MEDAL AWARD» (PDF). www.mathunion.org. June 1, 2009. Archived (PDF) from the original on June 17, 2009. Retrieved February 21, 2022.
  202. ^ «Chern Medal Award». International Mathematical Union (IMU). Archived from the original on August 25, 2010. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  203. ^ «The Leroy P Steele Prize of the AMS». School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland. Archived from the original on November 17, 2022. Retrieved November 17, 2022.
  204. ^ Chern, S. S.; Hirzebruch, F. (September 2000). Wolf Prize in Mathematics. doi:10.1142/4149. ISBN 978-981-02-3945-9. Archived from the original on February 21, 2022. Retrieved February 21, 2022.
  205. ^ «The Wolf Prize». Wolf Foundation. Archived from the original on January 12, 2020. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  206. ^ «Hilbert’s Problems: 23 and Math». Simons Foundation. May 6, 2020. Archived from the original on January 23, 2022. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  207. ^ Feferman, Solomon (1998). «Deciding the undecidable: Wrestling with Hilbert’s problems» (PDF). In the Light of Logic. Logic and Computation in Philosophy series. Oxford University Press. pp. 3–27. ISBN 0-19-508030-0. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved November 29, 2022.
  208. ^ «Hilbert’s Problems: 23 and Math». Simons Foundation. May 6, 2020. Archived from the original on January 23, 2022. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  209. ^ «The Millennium Prize Problems». Clay Mathematics Institute. Archived from the original on July 3, 2015. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  210. ^ «Millennium Problems». Clay Mathematics Institute. Archived from the original on December 20, 2018. Retrieved January 23, 2022.

Bibliography

  • Bouleau, Nicolas (1999). Philosophie des mathématiques et de la modélisation: Du chercheur à l’ingénieur. L’Harmattan. ISBN 9782738481252.
  • Boyer, Carl Benjamin (1991). A History of Mathematics (2nd ed.). New York: Wiley. ISBN 978-0-471-54397-8.
  • Eves, Howard (1990). An Introduction to the History of Mathematics (6th ed.). Saunders. ISBN 978-0-03-029558-4.
  • Kleiner, Izraïl’ (2007). A History of Abstract Algebra. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 9780817646844. Archived from the original on March 7, 2023. Retrieved November 11, 2022.
  • Kline, Morris (1990). Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times (Paperback ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-506135-2.
  • Monastyrsky, Michael (2001). «Some Trends in Modern Mathematics and the Fields Medal» (PDF). CMS – NOTES – de la SMC. Canadian Mathematical Society. 33 (2–3). Archived (PDF) from the original on August 13, 2006. Retrieved July 28, 2006.
  • Oakley, Barbara (2014). A Mind For Numbers: How to Excel at Math and Science (Even If You Flunked Algebra). New York: Penguin Random House. ISBN 978-0-399-16524-5. A Mind for Numbers.
  • Peirce, Benjamin (1881). Peirce, Charles Sanders (ed.). «Linear associative algebra». American Journal of Mathematics (Corrected, expanded, and annotated revision with an 1875 paper by B. Peirce and annotations by his son, C.S. Peirce, of the 1872 lithograph ed.). 4 (1–4): 97–229. doi:10.2307/2369153. hdl:2027/hvd.32044030622997. JSTOR 2369153. Corrected, expanded, and annotated revision with an 1875 paper by B. Peirce and annotations by his son, C. S. Peirce, of the 1872 lithograph ed. Google Eprint and as an extract, D. Van Nostrand, 1882, Google Eprint. Archived from the original on March 31, 2021. Retrieved November 17, 2020..
  • Peterson, Ivars (2001). Mathematical Tourist, New and Updated Snapshots of Modern Mathematics. Owl Books. ISBN 978-0-8050-7159-7.
  • Popper, Karl R. (1995). «On knowledge». In Search of a Better World: Lectures and Essays from Thirty Years. New York: Routledge. Bibcode:1992sbwl.book…..P. ISBN 978-0-415-13548-1.
  • Riehm, Carl (August 2002). «The Early History of the Fields Medal» (PDF). Notices of the AMS. 49 (7): 778–82. Archived (PDF) from the original on October 26, 2006. Retrieved October 2, 2006.
  • Sevryuk, Mikhail B. (January 2006). «Book Reviews» (PDF). Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society. 43 (1): 101–09. doi:10.1090/S0273-0979-05-01069-4. Archived (PDF) from the original on July 23, 2006. Retrieved June 24, 2006.
  • Waltershausen, Wolfgang Sartorius von (1965) [first published 1856]. Gauss zum Gedächtniss. Sändig Reprint Verlag H. R. Wohlwend. ISBN 978-3-253-01702-5.
  • Whittle, Peter (1994). «Almost home». In Kelly, F.P. (ed.). Probability, statistics and optimisation: A Tribute to Peter Whittle (previously «A realised path: The Cambridge Statistical Laboratory up to 1993 (revised 2002)» ed.). Chichester: John Wiley. pp. 1–28. ISBN 978-0-471-94829-2. Archived from the original on December 19, 2013.

Further reading

  • Benson, Donald C. (1999). The Moment of Proof: Mathematical Epiphanies. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-513919-8.
  • Davis, Philip J.; Hersh, Reuben (1999). The Mathematical Experience (Reprint ed.). Boston; New York: Mariner Books. ISBN 978-0-395-92968-1. Available online (registration required).
  • Courant, Richard; Robbins, Herbert (1996). What Is Mathematics?: An Elementary Approach to Ideas and Methods (2nd ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-510519-3.
  • Gullberg, Jan (1997). Mathematics: From the Birth of Numbers. W. W. Norton & Company. ISBN 978-0-393-04002-9.
  • Hazewinkel, Michiel, ed. (2000). Encyclopaedia of Mathematics. Kluwer Academic Publishers. – A translated and expanded version of a Soviet mathematics encyclopedia, in ten volumes. Also in paperback and on CD-ROM, and online. Archived July 3, 2011, at the Wayback Machine.
  • Hodgkin, Luke Howard (2005). A History of Mathematics: From Mesopotamia to Modernity. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-152383-0.
  • Jourdain, Philip E. B. (2003). «The Nature of Mathematics». In James R. Newman (ed.). The World of Mathematics. Dover Publications. ISBN 978-0-486-43268-7.
  • Pappas, Theoni (1986). The Joy Of Mathematics. San Carlos, California: Wide World Publishing. ISBN 978-0-933174-65-8.

Mathematics is one of the most important subjects. Mathematics is a subject of numbers, shapes, data, measurements and also logical activities. It has a huge scope in every field of our life, such as medicine, engineering, finance, natural science, economics, etc. We are all surrounded by a mathematical world.

The concepts, theories and formulas that we learn in Maths books have huge applications in real-life. To find the solutions for various problems we need to learn the formulas and concepts. Therefore, it is important to learn this subject to understand its various applications and significance.

What Is The Definition of Mathematics?

Mathematics simply means to learn or to study or gain knowledge. The theories and concepts given in mathematics help us understand and solve various types of problems in academic as well as in real life situations.

Mathematics is a subject of logic. Learning mathematics will help students to grow their problem-solving and logical reasoning skills. Solving mathematical problems is one of the best brain exercises.

Basic Mathematics

The fundamentals of mathematics begin with arithmetic operations such as addition, subtraction, multiplication and division. These are the basics that every student learns in their elementary school. Here is a brief of these operations.

  • Addition: Sum of numbers (Eg. 1 + 2 = 3)
  • Subtraction: Difference between two or more numbers (Eg. 5 – 4 = 1)
  • Multiplication: Product of two or more numbers (Eg. 3 x 9 = 27)
  • Division: Dividing a number into equal parts (Eg. 10 ÷ 2 = 5, 10 is divided in 2 equal parts)

Mathematics is a historical subject. It has been explored by various mathematicians across the world since centuries, in different civilizations. Archimedes, from the BC century is known to be the Father of Mathematics. He introduced formulas to calculate surface area and volume of solids. Whereas, Aryabhatt, born in 476 CE, is known as the Father of Indian Mathematics.

In the 6th century BC, the study of mathematics began with the Pythagoreans, as a “demonstrative discipline”. The word mathematics originated from the Greek word “mathema”, which means “subject of instruction”.

Another mathematician, named Euclid, introduced the axiom, postulates, theorems and proofs, which are also used in today’s mathematics.

History of Mathematics has been an ancient study and is described by each part of the world, in a varying method. There were many mathematicians who have given different theories for many concepts, which we are applying in modern mathematics.

Numbers, which we use for calculations, had variations in the medieval period. The Romans introduced the Roman numerals that uses English alphabets to represent a number, such as:

1

2

3

4

5

6

7

8

9

10

I

II

III

IV

V

VI

VII

VIII

IX

X

Branches of Mathematics

The main branches of mathematics are:

  • Number System
  • Algebra
  • Geometry
  • Calculus
  • Topology
  • Trigonometry
  • Probability and Statistics

These mathematical concepts fall under pure mathematics. These form the base of mathematics. In our academics we will come across all these theories and fundamentals to solve questions based on them.

Applied mathematics is another form, where mathematicians, scientists or technicians use mathematical concepts to solve practical problems. It describes the professional use of mathematics.

Symbols in Mathematics

Some of the basic and most important symbols, used in mathematics, are listed below in the table.

Symbol

Name

Meaning

Application

not equal sign

inequality

11 ≠ 6

=

equals sign

equality

4 = 2 + 2

<

strict inequality

less than

6 < 11

>

strict inequality

greater than

9 > 8

[ ]

brackets

calculate expression inside first

[2×5] + 7 = 17

( )

parentheses

calculate expression inside first

3 × (3 + 7) = 30

minus sign

subtraction

5 − 2 = 3

+

plus sign

addition

4 + 5 = 9

×

times sign

multiplication

4 × 3 = 12

*

asterisk

multiplication

2 * 3 = 6

÷

division sign / obelus

division

15 ÷ 5 = 3

These are the most common symbols used in basic mathematical calculations. To get more maths symbols click here.

Properties in Mathematics

In mathematics, we learn about four major properties of numbers. They are:

  • Commutative Property
  • Associative property
  • Distributive Property
  • Identity Property

These are the four basic properties of numbers. These properties are also applicable to some other mathematical concepts such as algebra.

Rules in Mathematics

The most common rule used in mathematics is the BODMAS rule. As per this rule, the arithmetic operations are performed based on the brackets and order of operations. By the full form of BODMAS, we can easily understand this logic.

BODMAS – Brackets Orders Division Multiplication Addition and Subtraction

Therefore, the first priority here is given to the brackets then division>multiplication>addition>subtraction.

For example, if we have to solve [5+(3 x 5)÷2], then using the BODMAS rule, first multiply 3 and 5, within the brackets.

→ 5+(3 x 5)÷2 = 5 + 15÷2

Now divide 15 by 2

→ 5 + 7.5

→ 12.5

Formulas in Mathematics

Here are some common formulas used in mathematics to solve multiple problems.

  • Area and Perimeter Formula
  • Coordinate Geometry Formulas
  • Heron’s Formula
  • Quadratic Formula
  • Differentiation Formulas
  • Distance Formula
  • Section Formula & Conic Sections
  • Standard Deviation Formula
  • Trigonometry Formulas

Topics in Mathematics

Let us see some important topics for each Class (from 1 to 12) that are covered under mathematics.

Class 1 Mathematics

  • Numbers In Words
  • Addition And Subtraction Of Integers
  • Shapes

Class 2 Mathematics

  • Counting Numbers
  • Place Value

Class 3 Mathematics

  • Multiplication Tables
  • Multiplication And Division Of Integers
  • Comparing Fractions
  • Introduction To Data

Class 4 Mathematics

  • Factors And Multiples
  • Multiplication And Division Of Decimals
  • Multiplying Fractions
  • Introduction to Large Numbers

Class 5 Mathematics

  • Dividing Fractions
  • Addition and Subtraction of Decimals
  • Lines and Angles Introduction
  • Area Of A Square – Introduction To Area

Class 6 Mathematics

  • Whole Numbers
  • Algebra
  • Integers
  • Fractions

Class 7 Mathematics

  • Lines And Angles
  • Triangles
  • Percentage: Means Of Comparing Quantities
  • Visualising Solid Shapes

Class 8 Mathematics

  • Rational Numbers
  • Mensuration
  • Squares and Square Roots
  • Exponents And Powers

Class 9 Mathematics

  • Number System
  • Polynomials
  • Quadrilateral
  • Surface Areas and Volume

Class 10 Mathematics

  • Quadratics
  • Circles
  • Arithmetic Progression
  • Co-ordinate Geometry
  • Constructions
  • Probability And Statistics

Class 11 Mathematics

  • Sets
  • Relations and Functions
  • Trigonometric Functions
  • Linear Inequalities
  • Permutation And Combination
  • Conic Sections
  • Limits and Derivatives

Class 12 Mathematics

  • Matrices
  • Inverse Trigonometric Functions
  • Determinants
  • Application of Integrals
  • Vector algebra
  • Linear Programming
  • Continuity And Differentiability

Frequently Asked Questions on Mathematics

Q1

Define Mathematics.

Mathematics is a subject that deals with numbers, shapes, logic, quantity and arrangements. Mathematics teaches to solve problems based on numerical calculations and find the solutions.

Q2

Why is Mathematics an important subject for students?

Learning mathematics will help students to build their logical thinking and problem solving skills. It has huge applications in day to day life. The basic arithmetic operations such as addition, subtraction, multiplication and division are the most important part of our lives. Based on these operations, we do numerous calculations.

Q3

Who is the Father of Mathematics?

Archimedes, (287-212 BC) is known to be the Father of Mathematics.

Q4

Which part of mathematics does Trigonometry belong to?

Geometry is one of the most important branches of mathematics that includes trigonometry, where we deal with sides and angles of a right triangle. It has huge applications in the fields of construction and architecture.

Q5

What are the two forms of Mathematics?

Mathematics is described in two forms:

Pure mathematics and Applied mathematics

A reflection of their fundamental philosophy, the Pythagoreans invented the term mathematics, from the Greek word mathema, which meant “science.” ❋ Leonard Mlodinow (2001)

Considered a child prodigy, he went to Harvard and graduated, then he got his PhD in mathematics from the University of Michigan. ❋ Unknown (2010)

Education: Bachelor’s degree in mathematics from the University of Delhi and an MBA in marketing and finance from the Indian Institute of Management-Ahmedabad. ❋ Unknown (2009)

Only a philosophical topology, analogous to what in mathematics is defined as analysis situ (analysis of site), in opposition to analysis magnitudinis ❋ Unknown (2008)

Regarding an underlying mathematical edifice, a possible analogy in mathematics is the existence of non-computable numbers, these numbers have no deterministic, no algorithmic description, yet they exist. ❋ Unknown (2008)

The question asked which branch of mathematics comes from the Greek word for reunite. ❋ Unknown (2008)

We compose our systems of music, which we call mathematics, that are model systems of internal consistency. ❋ Sean (2008)

Society, who, accepting Bacon’s demand for certainty and not finding it in the hypothetical physics, empha — sized the necessity for a more Archimedean approach: what they called mathematics and what today might be termed mathematical physics. ❋ ROBERT H. KARGON (1968)

Things which may at first sight appear comparatively valueless in education — such as the study of the dead languages, and the relations of lines and surfaces which we call mathematics — are really of the greatest practical value, not so much because of the information which they yield, as because of the development which they compel. ❋ Samuel Smiles (1858)

I will now explain my meaning by literal examples, leaving aside all purely abstract reasoning, which I call the mathematics of thought. ❋ Honor�� De Balzac (1824)

The word «mathematics» comes from the Greek μάθημα (máthēma), which means learning, study, science, and additionally came to have the narrower and more technical meaning «mathematical study», even in Classical times. ❋ Unknown (2009)

That most exact and convincing of all sciences, mathematics, is sheerly metaphysical. ❋ Unknown (2010)

Already had Dick taken his coaches in mathematics duck hunting for weeks in the sloughs of the Sacramento and the San Joaquin. ❋ Unknown (2010)

From goaltenders using an understanding of angles to reduce the amount of exposed net, to simulating sports seasons based on score distributions (like in the linked Demonstration), students can see that mathematics is at the core of sports. ❋ Unknown (2010)

But when the impediment of mathematics is removed and the ideas themselves are rephrased in common language, they’re not that hard to understand. ❋ Unknown (2010)

Hey Cuthberton, did I tell you that I used some kickass [zen master] mathematics to calculate which [mathgirl] I would ask out to the [science fair]? ❋ Costa Del Barto (2006)

i love mathematics so much [i can] [study] it [all day long]!!! ❋ Jamanworld_2000 (2018)

Why did one straw break [the camel’s] back? Here’s the secret:
the million other straws underneath it — it’s all [mathematics] — [Mos Def] — [Mathematics] ❋ Neeraj.S (2005)

Get the [hell] [outta] [my face] with that mathematics ❋ Badmanahooo (2005)

«Hey baby. [Whas] yo mathematics
«My what?»
«Your mathematics
«[Oh my] [number]. No.» ❋ …<@!+Y (2007)

Mathematics is the language of tenure. Since university administrators invariably come from more serious disciplines, they could give [a rat’s] what goes on in the math department, excepting, of course the math professors’ occasional brush with the FBI and [kiddy porn].
She: Why am I having to take all this goddamn math?
He: To help Dr. Goldbaum enjoy lap dances down at [the truck stop]. ❋ Hoze-a (2007)

[The professor] taught math to his students to help them [engineer] better [computers]. ❋ Cp (2003)

person 1: dude we have math period now!
person 2: *leaves
person 1: dude where [you going]?
person 2: to [lick] a [cows ass] then do mathematics ❋ Your Daddy Truely (2022)

To understand many [branches] of science, one must be well [versed] in [mathematical] knowledge.
Dog: Hey, lets go do something fun!
Boy: [Mathematical]! ❋ Strange Comma (2010)

Michael: Hey man, what are you doing?
George: Solving some [math problems].
Michael: You need to cut off on [mathematics] man or we’ll have send you to [rehabilitation]. ❋ TheUchihaHawk (2015)

Mathematical formulas on green background. Mathematics is at the heart of science and our daily lives.
Mathematics is at the heart of science and our daily lives.
(Image credit: HandmadePictures / Shutterstock.com)

Mathematics is the science that deals with the logic of shape, quantity and arrangement. Math is all around us, in everything we do. It is the building block for everything in our daily lives, including mobile devices, computers, software, architecture (ancient and modern), art, money, engineering and even sports.

Since the beginning of recorded history, mathematical discovery has been at the forefront of every civilized society, and math has been used by even the most primitive and earliest cultures. The need for math arose because of the increasingly complex demands from societies around the world, which required more advanced mathematical solutions, as outlined by mathematician Raymond L. Wilder in his book «Evolution of Mathematical Concepts (opens in new tab)» (Dover Publications, 2013). 

The more complex a society, the more complex the mathematical needs. Primitive tribes needed little more than the ability to count, but also used math to calculate the position of the sun and the physics of hunting. «All the records — anthropological and historical — show that counting and, ultimately, numeral systems as a device for counting form the inception of the mathematical element in all cultures,» Wilder wrote in 1968.

Who invented mathematics?

Several civilizations — in China, India, Egypt, Central America and Mesopotamia — contributed to mathematics as we know it today. The Sumerians, who lived in the region that is now southern Iraq, were the first people to develop a counting system with a base 60 system, according to Wilder. 

This was based on using the bones in the fingers to count and then use as sets, according to Georges Ifrah in his book «The Universal History Of Numbers (opens in new tab)» (John Wiley & Sons, 2000). From these systems we have the basis of arithmetic, which includes basic operations of addition, multiplication, division, fractions and square roots. Wilder explained that the Sumerians’ system passed through the Akkadian Empire to the Babylonians around 300 B.C. Six hundred years later, in Central America, the Maya developed elaborate calendar systems and were skilled astronomers. About this time, the concept of zero was developed in India.

As civilizations developed, mathematicians began to work with geometry, which computes areas, volumes and angles, and has many practical applications. Geometry is used in everything from home construction to fashion and interior design. As Richard J. Gillings wrote in his book «Mathematics in the Time of the Pharaohs (opens in new tab)» (Dover Publications, 1982), the pyramids of Giza in Egypt are stunning examples of ancient civilizations’ advanced use of geometry.

Statue of Muhammad ibn Musa al-Khwarizmi

A statue of Muḥammad ibn Mūsā al-Khwārizmī that stands in Khiva, Uzbekistan. (Image credit: Konstik)

(opens in new tab)

Geometry went hand in hand with algebra. Persian mathematician Muḥammad ibn Mūsā al-Khwārizmī authored the earliest recorded work on algebra called «The Compendious Book on Calculation by Completion and Balancing» around 820 A.D., according to Philip K. Hitti (opens in new tab), a history professor at Princeton and Harvard University. Al-Khwārizmī also developed quick methods for multiplying and dividing numbers, which are known as algorithms — a corruption of his name, which in Latin was translated to Algorithmi.

Algebra offered civilizations a way to divide inheritances and allocate resources. The study of algebra meant mathematicians could solve linear equations and systems, as well as quadratics, and delve into positive and negative solutions. Mathematicians in ancient times also began to look at number theory, which «deals with properties of the whole numbers, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, …,» Tom M. Apostol, a professor at the California Institute of Technology, wrote in «Introduction to Analytic Number Theory (opens in new tab)» (Springer, 1976). With origins in the construction of shape, number theory looks at figurate numbers, the characterization of numbers, and theorems.

Mathematics in ancient Greece

The word mathematics comes from the ancient Greeks and is derived from the word máthēma, meaning «that which is learnt,» according to Douglas R. Harper, author of the «Online Etymology Dictionary (opens in new tab).» The ancient Greeks built on other ancient civilizations’ mathematical studies, and they developed the model of abstract mathematics through geometry. 

Greek mathematicians were divided into several schools, as outlined by G. Donald Allen, professor of Mathematics at Texas A&M University in his paper, «The Origins of Greek Mathematics (opens in new tab)«:

In addition to the Greek mathematicians listed above, a number of other ancient Greeks made an indelible mark on the history of mathematics, including Archimedes, most famous for the Archimedes’ principle around the buoyant force; Apollonius, who did important work with parabolas; Diophantus, the first Greek mathematician to recognize fractions as numbers; Pappus, known for his hexagon theorem; and Euclid, who first described the golden ratio.

The golden ratio is one of the most famous irrational numbers; it goes on forever and can’t be expressed accurately without infinite space.

The golden ratio is one of the most famous irrational numbers; it goes on forever and can’t be expressed accurately without infinite space. (Image credit: Shutterstock)

(opens in new tab)

During this time, mathematicians began working with trigonometry, which studies relationships between the sides and angles of triangles and computes trigonometric functions, including sine, cosine, tangent and their reciprocals. Trigonometry relies on the synthetic geometry developed by Greek mathematicians like Euclid. In past cultures, trigonometry was applied to astronomy (opens in new tab) and the computation of angles in the celestial sphere.

The development of mathematics was taken on by the Islamic empires, then concurrently in Europe and China, according to Wilder. Leonardo Fibonacci was a medieval European mathematician and was famous for his theories on arithmetic, algebra and geometry. The Renaissance led to advances that included decimal fractions, logarithms and projective geometry. Number theory was greatly expanded upon, and theories like probability and analytic geometry ushered in a new age of mathematics, with calculus at the forefront.

Development of calculus

In the 17th century, Isaac Newton in England and Gottfried Leibniz in Germany independently developed the foundations for calculus, Carl B. Boyer, a science historian, explained in «The History of the Calculus and Its Conceptual Development (opens in new tab)» (Dover Publications, 1959). Calculus development went through three periods: anticipation, development and rigorization. 

In the anticipation stage, mathematicians attempted to use techniques that involved infinite processes to find areas under curves or maximize certain qualities. In the development stage, Newton and Leibniz brought these techniques together through the derivative (the curve of mathematical function) and integral (the area under the curve). Though their methods were not always logically sound, mathematicians in the 18th century took on the rigorization stage and were able to justify their methods and create the final stage of calculus. Today, we define the derivative and integral in terms of limits.

In contrast to calculus, which is a type of continuous mathematics (dealing with real numbers), other mathematicians have taken a more theoretical approach. Discrete mathematics is the branch of math that deals with objects that can assume only distinct, separated value, as mathematician and computer scientist Richard Johnsonbaugh explained in «Discrete Mathematics (opens in new tab)» (Pearson, 2017). Discrete objects can be characterized by integers, rather than real numbers. Discrete mathematics is the mathematical language of computer science, as it includes the study of algorithms. Fields of discrete mathematics include combinatorics, graph theory and the theory of computation.

hazy mathematical formulas in a book

While complex math may not appear important to people’s daily lives, it’s at the heart of finance, travel, computing and more. (Image credit: Anton Belitskiy/Getty)

(opens in new tab)

Why mathematics is important

It’s not uncommon for people to wonder what relevance mathematics serves in their daily lives. In the modern world, math such as applied mathematics is not only relevant, it’s crucial. Applied mathematics covers the branches that study the physical, biological or sociological world. 

«The goal of applied mathematics is to establish the connections between separate academic fields,» wrote Alain Goriely in «Applied Mathematics: A Very Short Introduction (opens in new tab)» (Oxford University Press, 2018). Modern areas of applied math include mathematical physics, mathematical biology, control theory, aerospace engineering and math finance. Not only does applied math solve problems, but it also discovers new problems or develops new engineering disciplines, Goriely added. The common approach in applied math is to build a mathematical model of a phenomenon, solve the model and develop recommendations for performance improvement.

While not necessarily an opposite to applied mathematics, pure mathematics is driven by abstract problems, rather than real-world problems. Much of the subjects that are pursued by pure mathematicians have their roots in concrete physical problems, but a deeper understanding of these phenomena brings about problems and technicalities. 

These abstract problems and technicalities are what pure mathematics attempts to solve, and these attempts have led to major discoveries for humankind, including the universal Turing machine, theorized by Alan Turing in 1937. This machine, which began as an abstract idea, later laid the groundwork for the development of modern computers. Pure mathematics is abstract and based in theory, and is thus not constrained by the limitations of the physical world.

According to Goriely, «Applied mathematics is to pure mathematics, what pop music is to classical music.» Pure and applied are not mutually exclusive, but they are rooted in different areas of math and problem solving. Though the complex math involved in pure and applied mathematics is beyond the understanding of most people, the solutions developed from the processes have affected and improved the lives of many.

Originally published on Live Science.

Most Popular

Mathematics is the long word for «math,» or the science of numbers and shapes and what they mean. Most people need mathematics everyday to count and measure.

Mathematics is technically a plural noun — geometry, algebra, calculus: all of these are mathematics — but usually it is treated as singular. That’s why a person says, mathematics is my favorite subjects, not mathematics are my favorite subject. The word mathematics comes from the Greek word manthanein, meaning «to learn.»

Definitions of mathematics

  1. noun

    a science (or group of related sciences) dealing with the logic of quantity and shape and arrangement

    synonyms:

    math, maths

    see moresee less

    types:

    show 15 types…
    hide 15 types…
    pure mathematics

    the branches of mathematics that study and develop the principles of mathematics for their own sake rather than for their immediate usefulness

    applied math, applied mathematics

    the branches of mathematics that are involved in the study of the physical or biological or sociological world

    arithmetic

    the branch of pure mathematics dealing with the theory of numerical calculations

    geometry

    the pure mathematics of points and lines and curves and surfaces

    numerical analysis

    (mathematics) the branch of mathematics that studies algorithms for approximating solutions to problems in the infinitesimal calculus

    trig, trigonometry

    the mathematics of triangles and trigonometric functions

    algebra

    the mathematics of generalized arithmetical operations

    calculus, infinitesimal calculus

    the branch of mathematics that is concerned with limits and with the differentiation and integration of functions

    set theory

    the branch of pure mathematics that deals with the nature and relations of sets

    group theory

    the branch of mathematics dealing with groups

    analysis situs, topology

    the branch of pure mathematics that deals only with the properties of a figure X that hold for every figure into which X can be transformed with a one-to-one correspondence that is continuous in both directions

    metamathematics

    the logical analysis of mathematical reasoning

    linear programming

    a mathematical technique used in economics; finds the maximum or minimum of linear functions in many variables subject to constraints

    statistics

    a branch of applied mathematics concerned with the collection and interpretation of quantitative data and the use of probability theory to estimate population parameters

    probability theory, theory of probability

    the branch of applied mathematics that deals with probabilities

    type of:

    science, scientific discipline

    a particular branch of scientific knowledge

DISCLAIMER: These example sentences appear in various news sources and books to reflect the usage of the word ‘mathematics’.
Views expressed in the examples do not represent the opinion of Vocabulary.com or its editors.
Send us feedback

EDITOR’S CHOICE

Look up mathematics for the last time

Close your vocabulary gaps with personalized learning that focuses on teaching the
words you need to know.

VocabTrainer - Vocabulary.com's Vocabulary Trainer

Sign up now (it’s free!)

Whether you’re a teacher or a learner, Vocabulary.com can put you or your class on the path to systematic vocabulary improvement.

Get started

Like this post? Please share to your friends:
  • The word mathematics in a sentence
  • The word mathematics comes from the greek
  • The word mate in a sentence
  • The word mass comes from
  • The word market means