The word beauty in colors

what is beauty? image of a woman
(Image credit: Shutterstock)

What is beauty? Well, beauty is a six-letter word, and a loaded one, especially when it comes to working in the creative industries, but, while there’s the old adage that it’s ‘in the eye of the beholder’, some argue that what is (and isn’t beautiful) is far from subjective. 

The Oxford Dictionary defines beauty as «A combination of qualities, such as shape, colour, or form, that pleases the aesthetic senses, especially the sight.» But we all know it’s more than that: we often say a person is beautiful, or that they have a beautiful soul. 

Beauty, then, is nebulous – it isn’t dependent on certain aesthetic qualities, but has a deeper resonance that’s more about feeling than composition or colour. If it were that simple, we’d all make things that were universally agreed to be beautiful. (If you want to focus on your own creations, see our guide to oil painting techniques, or our how to draw tutorials).

What is beauty?

Maria-Alina Asavei is a lecturer and postdoctoral researcher in Russian and East European Department at the Institute of International Studies at Charles University in Prague and an independent curator of contemporary art. «We often fail to make clear what we mean by ‘beauty’, even if we use this word quite frequently, in all kinds of occasions, related to art or not,» she writes in the essay Beauty and Critical Art: is beauty at odds with critical–political engagement? (opens in new tab)

Asavei continues: «When we appreciate that something has beauty, we implicitly accept that X is a source of positive aesthetic value or positive aesthetic appreciation. In the history of philosophical aesthetics, there are many theories and definitions of beauty. Despite differences, most of these theories connect the experience of the beautiful with a certain type of pleasure and enjoyment.»

what is beauty

Alan Moore, in a suitably beautiful setting (Image credit: Alan Moore)

Yet many would argue that by our very nature, there’s a certain universal set of indices that inform beauty. Alan Moore, a former designer and typographer who worked under the mentorship of letterpress guru Alan Fletcher and in roles including head of art at Publicis in London, now focuses his entire career on beauty in design, and its role in successful businesses. 

However, his take on beauty isn’t about what something looks like: he often speaks about it in terms of Einstein’s Theory of Relativity, Dirac’s theorem, spirituality and the laws of nature. «At an atomic level, everything is connected; they dance and are attracted to one another at a nuclear level. The law of nature seeks things to be made of symmetry and harmony, and even in opposites they’re complementary: we have night and day, up and down. We’re all made of the same stuff molecularly, so we intuit beauty – we know it to be the life-enhancing force.»

As a designer, your duty is to only bring good things into the world

As such, Moore sees beauty not just as symmetry, but as regeneration: the first law of thermodynamics, also known as Law of Conservation of Energy, states that energy can neither be created nor destroyed; energy can only be transferred or changed from one form to another. This is intrinsically related to good design. «It’s about the idea of bringing good into the world and regeneration,» Moore says. «People really connect to the idea of beautiful people because it relates to values, it relates to ethics. You have to think about if someone asked you as a designer, ‘Is that the most beautiful decision we could make?’ If you see that, then as a designer, your duty is to only bring good things into the world.»

Is beauty useful?

These are big concepts, but are increasingly ones that designers have to think about in times of climate crisis and political turmoil. They’re as crucial (and as such, as «beautiful») as how good their type looks, or which Pantone they’ll select. 

It’s also about utility: Moore points out that «Mother Nature works with purpose in everything she does.» In legendary designer Paul Rand’s 1947 book Thoughts on Design (opens in new tab) he stated that, «Ideally, beauty and utility are mutually generative»; the combination of both is when you reach the pinnacle of design. «Visual communications of any kind… should be seen as the embodiment of form and function: the integration of the beautiful and the useful.» 

While this doesn’t help us to define what is and isn’t beautiful, it does underscore the notion of beauty as being a concept we all understand, but that can be mutable and dependent on context. Asavei echoes this view: «What we know about an event or object and our world-view and moral values always determine our perception about what is beautiful, why it is beautiful, and what is not beautiful.» 

what is beauty?

Will this be considered beautiful in one hundred years? (Image credit: Paper)

It goes without saying that what is and isn’t considered beautiful has changed throughout history, whether in art, design or the human form (for women in particular – think fetishising plumpness when it signified wealth during the Renaissance era; 90s «heroin chic» waifs; today’s Kardashian-esque big ass, little waist, big lips).

At one end of the historical beauty-definition spectrum is the «rational understanding of beauty and the search to boil down the essence into formulae and models for application,» as Alan Powers, a design writer and professor of architecture and cultural history at the University of Greenwich puts it in Beauty: A Short History (opens in new tab)

This was seen during the Renaissance when the prevailing belief around beauty was that it was based on numbers «akin to the harmonies of music and the movements of the planets». At the other end is a far more romanticised notion, such as the Middle Ages’ view of beauty as part of the «divine order» or poet John Keats’ «beauty is truth, truth beauty» from his Ode on a Grecian Urn. 

Then Modernism came along: everything was stripped back to its most basic components and that continues to play a huge role in today’s frequently Swiss-leaning, grid-loving design education. It was the far-reaching cultural shifts (at least in the Western world) of the rise of Modernism in the late 19th and early 20th centuries that saw the earlier decorative values of pattern and opulent lettering styles in print, or the decorative flourishes of architecture that had formerly dominated, fall out of favour. It also saw a swift shift toward pared-based design and prioritised rigid proportions and functionality. 

This marked the start of an underlying reluctance to embrace beauty as a core value, which continues to this day. The idea of beauty, to many, is (perhaps subconsciously) seen as trite or old-fashioned – an aesthetic principle at odds with the rigid frameworks of 21st century design. The divisive Guardian art critic Jonathan Jones wrote a piece in 2012 about the rejection of beauty in contemporary art, which aligned this view with far older beliefs that «beauty is the most dangerous idea in art… It tantalises and confuses, inspires and crushes», and that «beauty has been worshipped as the highest artistic value and denigrated as a pagan temptation.» 

The value of beauty

what is beauty

Beauty isn’t in the eyes of the beholder, argues this book (Image credit: Sagmeister & Walsh)

Yet in design, it’s not so much about «pagan temptation» or danger, but a focus on problem-solving, form-following-function, conceptual rigour and evolutions in technology that drive how interfaces, software and even print design are viewed. As grids and rules came in, beauty in its more traditional sense went out. As Alan Powers puts it, «The ideal of pure geometry remains deeply rooted in western consciousness as the basis of beauty. It sits well with the idea that beauty is an expert business, not accessible to the untrained mind.» 

However, one designer who consistently rails against the notion that beauty is unimportant, subjective or «not accessible to the untrained mind» is Stefan Sagmeister. In his talks and the book Sagmeister & Walsh: Beauty (opens in new tab), created with Jessica Walsh, he uses numerous scientific and cultural examples to point out that beauty is far from being «in the eye of the beholder» (he points out the phrase only came to prominence thanks to a line stating as such in Margaret Wolfe Hungerford’s 1878 novel Molly Bawn.) 

In talks, Stefan has shown his audience a slide with five different colours, another with five different shapes, and asked people to vote for their favourite. The results are almost identical wherever and whenever he does this (turns out circles and blue or purple come out top). Sure, it’s a crude experiment, but it says a lot about how our tastes are not as unique or subjective as we might have thought. Stefan often blames Modernism for the devaluation of beauty, and the suspicion that beautiful work might not be taken seriously, or derided as merely decorative or commercial. 

what is beauty

Inside Sagmeister & Walsh’s book (Image credit: Sagmeister & Walsh)

To avoid this risk, the grid was firmly laid out in design schools as the safe, clean, rational solution, to the point that it became non-expressive to the exclusion of physical beauty. Jan Tschichold – one of the most famous proponents of Modern ideals through his Die Neue Typographie (opens in new tab) – eventually went back on his espousal of modernist values, describing Modernism as «inherently authoritarian and fascist», and a style that had become a «default» that lacked wit and innovation.

The public will respond to any attempt to rehabilitate beauty

Jan Tschichold

Although his text is still a staple in design education, Tschichold went further, saying that a designer doesn’t have to be inventive or innovative to create design work based around the grid. Despite this apparent ongoing renunciation for many designers of beauty as a priority, «there is every reason to work with it again,» says Powers. He cites MORI research that showed «the public values beauty and not only wants it in their homes, clothes and other personal belongings, but also in the great outdoors, the public realm and public life… especially in these difficult times, the public will respond to any attempt to rehabilitate beauty.» Designers, take note! 

Alan Moore’s views echo this, and make a case for the importance of beauty in commercial design: «Beauty is a powerful quality for a business to have,» he wrote in The Business Case for Beauty (opens in new tab), originally published in Management Today. «People experience the world qualitatively, not quantitatively… a Temkin survey shows that customers with a positive emotional experience of a company are six times more likely to buy more, 12 times more likely to recommend and five times more likely to forgive a mistake.» This, clearly, defies any suspicions that beauty in creative work has no function, or serves a merely decorative purpose. 

Alan Moore’s commitment to preaching the values of the beautiful was born of a «road to Damascus» moment, he says. This arrived after many years working for various organisations and agencies and his view that there was a «form of myopia in the way they were working: making money at any cost until it cost them everything,» he says. «I got very angry at the greed across incumbent industries, whether they were TV, radio or print. I thought ‘this is not okay, we’re supplanting the idea that a good life is one born out of material consumption – nothing to do with the wealth of life’.» 

If there are so many cases in favour of beautiful design, why then in recent years and even decades have we seen designers move towards not just function over form, but deliberately «ugly» design: the post-ironic clashing of typefaces and so on? We’d suggest that this is because such work isn’t in fact ugly at all when it’s done well, but what we mean by beauty has radically shifted. 

Nature and beauty

Alan Moore points out that if everything in nature is beautiful, and that nature thrives on diversity and regeneration, then how we view what is and isn’t beautiful or aesthetically appealing will patently shift over time. Therefore, the notion of beauty as either a representation of subjective, aesthetic pleasure or something purely aesthetic with little intellectual or conceptual underpinning, is something that the designers who consider their role as simply «problem solving» might want to rethink.

Indeed, Jonathan points out that artwork that shuns beauty may well be in vogue; but once we’ve «look[ed] at it earnestly,» we then go and look at gorgeous photos, films, magazines – the true art of our time.» With so much of the commercial creative landscape responsible for such imagery, this suggests that a great editorial layout or careful selection of typefaces, a well-art directed campaign, or even a brand film has as much need for beauty as an artwork simply created for art’s sake. 

what is beauty

Dazed Beauty (Image credit: Dazed Beauty)

One newish platform pushing radically new and innovative ideas around what’s beautiful is Dazed Beauty (opens in new tab). Launched in late 2018, and art directed by Ben Ditto, who’s also creative director of Ditto Publishing, with creative direction from Isamaya Ffrench, the pair brought a more internet-led, fantasy-like, occasionally gore/horror-inspired look to the platform. 

The platform stated its mission as «celebrating identity, self-expression and creativity through the transformational power of beauty.» This means alongside covering faces and products, there’s a considerable focus on art. Pieces range from the sexuality of maternal women to nipple removal and other «extreme body modification» to profiles on creative coders and an artist who claims that we’re «already living in a video game». 

Beauty is personal, and platforms like Instagram have helped people to leverage beauty on their terms

Nellie Eden

This idea of creativity and self-expression as integral to beauty has meant the design of the site is thoroughly futuristic, using gloopy metallic type that floats around the pages, lurid neon green lines to break up the site’s grid and sections that are predominantly image-led, clearly taking a cue or two from certain image-sharing platforms. It’s a far cry from the usual look of beauty or fashion publications: all clean, neat layouts; white space, femininity and mastheads set in black, traditional serif capitals. «This is beauty for the social media age,» as Ffrench puts it. 

«Beauty is personal, and platforms like Instagram have helped people to leverage beauty on their terms,» says Dazed Beauty’s editor Nellie Eden. «Our design is informed by the convergence of the beauty and the tech industries. When we talk about beauty it’s not about products or who’s the face of YSL – it’s what a teenager in Poland is doing with his contact lenses.» 

what is beauty

Dazed Beauty’s logo (Image credit: Dazed Beauty)

Eden continues: «Dazed Beauty has a distinctive personality: you can put something on Instagram that people find disgusting or appalling or strange, and that’s fantastic, because beauty imagery has become so sanitised and so far from what it means to be human… We always say make it weirder or more digressive or obscure.» These presentations of future-facing, deliberately «weirder» or «appalling» takes on what is beautiful doesn’t mean that beauty needn’t be a consideration for designers – quite the opposite – but it does mean they need to dig deep to think about what could make their work more beautiful, and their approach to doing so. 

Beauty, states Powers, is «cultivated through a deeper understanding of what we already have, and by looking after and appreciating the unique characteristics of the places where we live.» He adds, «we should commit ourselves to living better on less. Perhaps the key thing is to have the confidence to say beauty matters, and not to be afraid of the reaction.» But it’s not just about these deeper philosophies, or trend-bucking. 

In Sagmeister and Walsh’s book, they state the case that attention to form (in other words, beauty) in turn makes a design more functional. Beautiful packaging design, for instance, sells better. Moore firmly backs this: «Beauty as a frame, philosophy, language even, shows how to build businesses that are more relevant and needed in the world we all live in today: businesses that build legacy, that go beyond sustainability, that are places the best people want to work for, and that deliver outstanding customer experience, all of which translates into long-term growth and profitability.» 

Alan Moore also argues that rather than form making something more functional, «beauty flows from purpose», citing companies such as Patagonia as exemplary in attracting creative talent and effective decision-making and leadership through the sense of purpose embedded across the business. To him, beauty isn’t just about design or even design teams: it’s about a workplace culture built around generosity and positivity. This in turn brings deeper engagement with the tasks at hand, trust and overall better well-being. 

It’s also about sustainability, for both the business and the world: Moore states that «beautiful businesses… take less, make better with less and waste nothing» – they are «regenerative, existing as part of living systems rather than trying to disrupt or destroy them.» Moore adds, «Beauty isn’t incompatible with rigour. It won’t hurt your bottom line or your return on equity to have a beautiful business with a beautiful culture, making beautiful products. Indeed, in the long term it could be one of your greatest assets.» 

what is beauty

Which one is most beautiful? (Image credit: Sagmeister & Walsh)

To make more beautiful design runs deeper than the images you put into the world, it’s about the social purpose of what you’re doing and how you’re running your creative business. So if we run with the idea that beauty remains vital to design, but the foundations of what is seen as «beautiful» are more mutable than ever, how as a designer do you make more beautiful work?

Describing beauty as «the sweet spot between order and chaos» (rather than the Modernist designers’ rejection of chaos of any form); Sagmeister and Walsh use the equation M = O/C to decide on something’s beauty (beauty, M, is the ratio of Organization (O) to Complexity (C).) Whether a commission requires simplicity, ornamentation or boundary-pushing image-making, beauty is, and always will be vital. 

In an age where designers increasingly see AI and other tech innovations gradually making gains on the grub work of design, one thing that computers will never be able to do is judge an innate, more nebulous sense of what is beautiful. Beauty is innately related to humanity, and whatever face you put on it, computers will never be truly human.

This article originally appeared in issue 300 of Computer Arts, the world’s leading design magazine. Buy issue 300 (opens in new tab) or subscribe here (opens in new tab).

Read more:

  • Graphic design history: 25 landmark events
  • Design for good: ways to use your creativity to make a difference
  • Design’s gender problem, and what you can do about it

Thank you for reading 5 articles this month* Join now for unlimited access

Enjoy your first month for just £1 / $1 / €1

*Read 5 free articles per month without a subscription

Join now for unlimited access

Try first month for just £1 / $1 / €1

Sign up below to get the latest from Creative Bloq, plus exclusive special offers, direct to your inbox!

Emily Gosling is a freelance art and design journalist currently writing for titles including Creative Review, Eye on Design, Creative Boom and People of Print. She’s previously worked at Elephant magazine, It’s Nice That and Design Week, and was editor of Type Notes magazine. Her book Creative Minds Don’t Think Alike was published by Ilex Press in 2018, and she also plays bass as one-quarter of the eight-titted beast, Superstation Twatville.

Related articles

Beauty is commonly described as a feature of objects that makes these objects pleasurable to perceive. Such objects include landscapes, sunsets, humans and works of art. Beauty, together with art and taste, is the main subject of aesthetics, one of the major branches of philosophy. As a positive aesthetic value, it is contrasted with ugliness as its negative counterpart. It is often listed as one of the three fundamental concepts of human understanding besides truth and goodness.

One difficulty for understanding beauty is due to the fact that it has both objective and subjective aspects: it is seen as a property of things but also as depending on the emotional response of observers. Because of its subjective side, beauty is said to be «in the eye of the beholder».[2] It has been argued that the ability on the side of the subject needed to perceive and judge beauty, sometimes referred to as the «sense of taste», can be trained and that the verdicts of experts coincide in the long run. This would suggest that the standards of validity of judgments of beauty are intersubjective, i.e. dependent on a group of judges, rather than fully subjective or fully objective.

Conceptions of beauty aim to capture what is essential to all beautiful things. Classical conceptions define beauty in terms of the relation between the beautiful object as a whole and its parts: the parts should stand in the right proportion to each other and thus compose an integrated harmonious whole. Hedonist conceptions see a necessary connection between pleasure and beauty, e.g. that for an object to be beautiful is for it to cause disinterested pleasure. Other conceptions include defining beautiful objects in terms of their value, of a loving attitude towards them or of their function.

Contents

  • 1 Overview
  • 2 Objectivism and subjectivism
  • 3 Conceptions
    • 3.1 Classical
    • 3.2 Hedonism
    • 3.3 Others
  • 4 Beauty in philosophy
    • 4.1 Greco-Roman tradition
      • 4.1.1 Pre-Socratic
      • 4.1.2 Classical period
      • 4.1.3 Roman
    • 4.2 Western Middle Ages
    • 4.3 Renaissance
    • 4.4 Age of Reason
    • 4.5 Western 19th and 20th century
    • 4.6 Chinese philosophy
  • 5 Human beauty
    • 5.1 Western concept of beauty
  • 6 Effects on society
  • 7 See also
  • 8 References
  • 9 External links

Overview

Beauty, together with art and taste, is the main subject of aesthetics, one of the major branches of philosophy.[3][4] Beauty is usually categorized as an aesthetic property besides other properties, like grace, elegance or the sublime.[5][6][7] As a positive aesthetic value, beauty is contrasted with ugliness as its negative counterpart. Beauty is often listed as one of the three fundamental concepts of human understanding besides truth and goodness.[5][8][6]

Objectivists or realists see beauty as an objective or mind-independent feature of beautiful things, which is denied by subjectivists.[3][9] The source of this debate is that judgments of beauty seem to be based on subjective grounds, namely our feelings, while claiming universal correctness at the same time.[10] This tension is sometimes referred to as the «antinomy of taste».[4] Adherents of both sides have suggested that a certain faculty, commonly called a sense of taste, is necessary for making reliable judgments about beauty.[3][10] David Hume, for example, suggests that this faculty can be trained and that the verdicts of experts coincide in the long run.[3][9]

Beauty is mainly discussed in relation to concrete objects accessible to sensory perception. It is often suggested that the beauty of a thing supervenes on the sensory features of this thing.[10] But it has also been proposed that abstract objects like stories or mathematical proofs can be beautiful.[11] Beauty plays a central role in works of art but there is also beauty outside the field of art, especially concerning the beauty of nature.[12][10] An influential distinction among beautiful things, due to Immanuel Kant, is that between dependent and free beauty. A thing has dependent beauty if its beauty depends on the conception or function of this thing, unlike free or absolute beauty.[10] Examples of dependent beauty include an ox that is beautiful as an ox but not as a horse[3] or a photograph that is beautiful because it depicts a beautiful building but that lacks beauty generally speaking because of its low quality.[9]

Objectivism and subjectivism

Judgments of beauty seem to occupy an intermediary position between objective judgments, e.g. concerning the mass and shape of a grapefruit, and subjective likes, e.g. concerning whether the grapefruit tastes good.[13][10][9] Judgments of beauty differ from the former because they are based on subjective feelings rather than objective perception. But they also differ from the latter because they lay claim on universal correctness.[10] This tension is also reflected in common language. On the one hand, we talk about beauty as an objective feature of the world that is ascribed, for example, to landscapes, paintings or humans.[14] The subjective side, on the other hand, is expressed in sayings like «beauty is in the eye of the beholder».[3]

These two positions are often referred to as objectivism or realism and subjectivism.[3] Objectivism is the traditional view while subjectivism developed more recently in western philosophy. Objectivists hold that beauty is a mind-independent feature of things. On this account, the beauty of a landscape is independent of who perceives it or whether it is perceived at all.[3][9] Disagreements may be explained by an inability to perceive this feature, sometimes referred to as a «lack of taste».[15] Subjectivism, on the other hand, denies the mind-independent existence of beauty.[5][3][9] Influential for the development of this position was John Locke’s distinction between primary qualities, which the object has independent of the observer, and secondary qualities, which constitute powers in the object to produce certain ideas in the observer.[3][16][5] When applied to beauty, there is still a sense in which it depends on the object and its powers.[9] But this account makes the possibility of genuine disagreements about claims of beauty implausible since the same object may produce very different ideas in distinct observers. The notion of «taste» can still be used to explain why different people disagree about what is beautiful. But there is no objectively right or wrong taste, there are just different tastes.[3]

The problem with both the objectivist and the subjectivist position in their extreme form is that each has to deny some intuitions about beauty. This issue is sometimes discussed under the label «antinomy of taste».[3][4] It has prompted various philosophers to seek a unified theory that can take all these intuitions into account. One promising route to solve this problem is to move from subjective to intersubjective theories, which hold that the standards of validity of judgments of taste are intersubjective or dependent on a group of judges rather than objective. This approach tries to explain how genuine disagreement about beauty is possible despite the fact that beauty is a mind-dependent property, dependent not on an individual but a group.[3][4] A closely related theory sees beauty as a secondary or response-dependent property.[9] On one such account, an object is beautiful «if it causes pleasure by virtue of its aesthetic properties».[5] The problem that different people respond differently can be addressed by combining response-dependence theories with so-called ideal-observer theories: it only matters how an ideal observer would respond.[10] There is no general agreement on how «ideal observers» are to be defined, but it is usually assumed that they are experienced judges of beauty with a fully developed sense of taste. This suggests an indirect way of solving the antinomy of taste: instead of looking for necessary and sufficient conditions of beauty itself, we may learn to identify the qualities of good critics and rely on their judgments.[3] This approach only works if unanimity among experts was ensured. But even experienced judges may disagree in their judgments, which threatens to undermine ideal-observer theories.[3][9]

Conceptions

Various conceptions of the essential features of beautiful things have been proposed but there is no consensus as to which is the right one.

Classical

The classical conception defines beauty in terms of the relation between the beautiful object as a whole and its parts: the parts should stand in the right proportion to each other and thus compose an integrated harmonious whole.[3][5][9] On this account, which found its most explicit articulation in the Italian Renaissance, the beauty of a human body, for example, depends, among other things, on the right proportion of the different parts of the body and on the overall symmetry.[3] One problem with this conception is that it is difficult to give a general and detailed description of what is meant by «harmony between parts».[3] This raises the suspicion that defining beauty through harmony only results in exchanging one unclear term for another one. Some attempts have been made to dissolve this suspicion by searching for laws of beauty, like the golden ratio. Alexander Baumgarten, for example, saw laws of beauty in analogy with laws of nature and believed that they could be discovered through empirical research.[5] But these attempts have failed so far to find a general definition of beauty. Several authors even take the opposite claim, that such laws cannot be formulated, as part of their definition of beauty.[10]

Hedonism

A very common element in many conceptions of beauty is its relation to pleasure.[11][5] Hedonism makes this relation part of the definition of beauty by holding that there is a necessary connection between pleasure and beauty, e.g. that for an object to be beautiful is for it to cause pleasure or that the experience of beauty is always accompanied by pleasure.[12] This account is sometimes labeled as «aesthetic hedonism» in order to distinguish it from other forms of hedonism.[17][18] An influential articulation of this position comes from Thomas Aquinas, who treats beauty as «that which pleases in the very apprehension of it».[19] Immanuel Kant explains this pleasure through a harmonious interplay between the faculties of understanding and imagination.[11] A further question for hedonists is how to explain the relation between beauty and pleasure. This problem is akin to the Euthyphro dilemma: is something beautiful because we enjoy it or do we enjoy it because it is beautiful?[5] Identity theorists solve this problem by denying that there is a difference between beauty and pleasure: they identify beauty, or the appearance of it, with the experience of aesthetic pleasure.[11]

Hedonists usually restrict and specify the notion of pleasure in various ways in order to avoid obvious counterexamples. One important distinction in this context is the difference between pure and mixed pleasure.[11] Pure pleasure excludes any form of pain or unpleasant feeling while the experience of mixed pleasure can include unpleasant elements.[20] But beauty can involve mixed pleasure, for example, in the case of a beautifully tragic story, which is why mixed pleasure is usually allowed in hedonist conceptions of beauty.[11]

Another problem faced by hedonist theories is that we take pleasure from many things that are not beautiful. One way to address this issue is to associate beauty with a special type of pleasure: aesthetic or disinterested pleasure.[3][4][7] A pleasure is disinterested if it is indifferent to the existence of the beautiful object or if it did not arise due to an antecedent desire through means-end reasoning.[21][11] For example, the joy of looking at a beautiful landscape would still be valuable if it turned out that this experience was an illusion, which would not be true if this joy was due to seeing the landscape as a valuable real estate opportunity.[3] Opponents of hedonism usually concede that many experiences of beauty are pleasurable but deny that this is true for all cases.[12] For example, a cold jaded critic may still be a good judge of beauty due to her years of experience but lack the joy that initially accompanied her work.[11] One way to avoid this objection is to allow responses to beautiful things to lack pleasure while insisting that all beautiful things merit pleasure, that aesthetic pleasure is the only appropriate response to them.[12]

Others

Various other conceptions of beauty have been proposed. G. E. Moore explains beauty in regard to intrinsic value as «that of which the admiring contemplation is good in itself».[21][5] This definition connects beauty to experience while managing to avoid some of the problems usually associated with subjectivist positions since it allows that things may be beautiful even if they are never experienced.[21] Another subjectivist theory of beauty comes from George Santayana, who suggests that we project pleasure onto the things we call «beautiful». So in a process akin to a category mistake, we treat our subjective pleasure as an objective property of the beautiful thing.[11][3][5] Other conceptions include defining beauty in terms of a loving or longing attitude towards the beautiful object or in terms of its usefulness or function.[3][22] Functionalists can follow Charles Darwin, for example, in explaining beauty according to its role in sexual selection.[5]

Beauty in philosophy

Greco-Roman tradition

The classical Greek noun that best translates to the English-language words «beauty» or «beautiful» was κάλλος, kallos, and the adjective was καλός, kalos. However, kalos may and is also translated as ″good″ or ″of fine quality″ and thus has a broader meaning than mere physical or material beauty. Similarly, kallos was used differently from the English word beauty in that it first and foremost applied to humans and bears an erotic connotation.[23] The Koine Greek word for beautiful was ὡραῖος, hōraios,[24] an adjective etymologically coming from the word ὥρα, hōra, meaning «hour». In Koine Greek, beauty was thus associated with «being of one’s hour».[25] Thus, a ripe fruit (of its time) was considered beautiful, whereas a young woman trying to appear older or an older woman trying to appear younger would not be considered beautiful. In Attic Greek, hōraios had many meanings, including «youthful» and «ripe old age».[25] Another classical term in use to describe beauty was pulchrum (Latin).[26]

Beauty for ancient thinkers existed both in form, which is the material world as it is, and as embodied in the spirit, which is the world of mental formations.[27] Greek mythology mentions Helen of Troy as the most beautiful woman.[28][29][30][31][32] Ancient Greek architecture is based on this view of symmetry and proportion.

Pre-Socratic

In one fragment of Heraclitus’s writings (Fragment 106) he mentions beauty, this reads : To God all things are beautiful, good, right… [33] The earliest Western theory of beauty can be found in the works of early Greek philosophers from the pre-Socratic period, such as Pythagoras, who conceived of beauty as useful for a moral education of the soul.[34] He wrote of how people experience pleasure when aware of a certain type of formal situation present in reality, perceivable by sight or through the ear[35] and discovered the underlying mathematical ratios in the harmonic scales in music.[34] The Pythagoreans conceived of the presence of beauty in universal terms, which is, as existing in a cosmological state, they observed beauty in the heavens.[27] They saw a strong connection between mathematics and beauty. In particular, they noted that objects proportioned according to the golden ratio seemed more attractive.[36]

Classical period

The classical concept of beauty is one that exhibits perfect proportion (Wolfflin).[37] In this context, the concept belonged often within the discipline of mathematics.[26] An idea of spiritual beauty emerged during the classical period,[27] beauty was something embodying divine goodness, while the demonstration of behaviour which might be classified as beautiful, from an inner state of morality which is aligned to the good.[38]

The writing of Xenophon shows a conversation between Socrates and Aristippus. Socrates discerned differences in the conception of the beautiful, for example, in inanimate objects, the effectiveness of execution of design was a deciding factor on the perception of beauty in something.[27] By the account of Xenophon, Socrates found beauty congruent with that to which was defined as the morally good, in short, he thought beauty coincident with the good.[39]

Beauty is a subject of Plato in his work Symposium.[34] In the work, the high priestess Diotima describes how beauty moves out from a core singular appreciation of the body to outer appreciations via loved ones, to the world in its state of culture and society (Wright).[35] In other words, Diotoma gives to Socrates an explanation of how love should begin with erotic attachment, and end with the transcending of the physical to an appreciation of beauty as a thing in itself. The ascent of love begins with one’s own body, then secondarily, in appreciating beauty in another’s body, thirdly beauty in the soul, which cognates to beauty in the mind in the modern sense, fourthly beauty in institutions, laws and activities, fifthly beauty in knowledge, the sciences, and finally to lastly love beauty itself, which translates to the original Greek language term as auto to kalon.[40] In the final state, auto to kalon and truth are united as one.[41] There is the sense in the text, concerning love and beauty they both co-exist but are still independent or, in other words, mutually exclusive, since love does not have beauty since it seeks beauty.[42] The work toward the end provides a description of beauty in a negative sense.[42]

Plato also discusses beauty in his work Phaedrus,[41] and identifies Alcibiades as beautiful in Parmenides.[43] He considered beauty to be the Idea (Form) above all other Ideas.[44] Platonic thought synthesized beauty with the divine.[35] Scruton (cited: Konstan) states Plato states of the idea of beauty, of it (the idea), being something inviting desirousness (c.f seducing), and, promotes an intellectual renunciation (c.f. denouncing) of desire.[45] For Alexander Nehamas, it is only the locating of desire to which the sense of beauty exists, in the considerations of Plato.[46]

Aristotle defines beauty in Metaphysics as having order, symmetry and definiteness which the mathematical sciences exhibit to a special degree.[37] He saw a relationship between the beautiful (to kalon) and virtue, arguing that «Virtue aims at the beautiful.»[47]

Roman

In De Natura Deorum Cicero wrote: the splendour and beauty of creation, in respect to this, and all the facets of reality resulting from creation, he postulated these to be a reason to see the existence of a God as creator.[48]

Western Middle Ages

In the Middle Ages, Catholic philosophers like Thomas Aquinas included beauty among the transcendental attributes of being.[49] In his Summa Theologica, Aquinas described the three conditions of beauty as: integritas (wholeness), consonantia (harmony and proportion), and claritas (a radiance and clarity that makes the form of a thing apparent to the mind).[50]

In the Gothic Architecture of the High and Late Middle Ages, light was considered the most beautiful revelation of God, which was heralded in design.[1] Examples are the stained glass of Gothic Cathedrals including Notre-Dame de Paris and Chartes Cathedral.[51]

St. Augustine said of beauty «Beauty is indeed a good gift of God; but that the good may not think it a great good, God dispenses it even to the wicked.»[52]

Renaissance

Classical philosophy and sculptures of men and women produced according to the Greek philosophers’ tenets of ideal human beauty were rediscovered in Renaissance Europe, leading to a re-adoption of what became known as a «classical ideal». In terms of female human beauty, a woman whose appearance conforms to these tenets is still called a «classical beauty» or said to possess a «classical beauty», whilst the foundations laid by Greek and Roman artists have also supplied the standard for male beauty and female beauty in western civilization as seen, for example, in the Winged Victory of Samothrace. During the Gothic era, the classical aesthetical canon of beauty was rejected as sinful. Later, Renaissance and Humanist thinkers rejected this view, and considered beauty to be the product of rational order and harmonious proportions. Renaissance artists and architects (such as Giorgio Vasari in his «Lives of Artists») criticised the Gothic period as irrational and barbarian. This point of view of Gothic art lasted until Romanticism, in the 19th century. Vasari aligned himself to the classical notion and thought of beauty as defined as arising from proportion and order.[38]

Age of Reason

The Age of Reason saw a rise in an interest in beauty as a philosophical subject. For example, Scottish philosopher Francis Hutcheson argued that beauty is «unity in variety and variety in unity».[53] He wrote that beauty was neither purely subjective nor purely objective—it could be understood not as «any Quality suppos’d to be in the Object, which should of itself be beautiful, without relation to any Mind which perceives it: For Beauty, like other Names of sensible Ideas, properly denotes the Perception of some mind; … however we generally imagine that there is something in the Object just like our Perception.»[54]

Immanuel Kant believed that there could be no «universal criterion of the beautiful» and that the experience of beauty is subjective, but that an object is judged to be beautiful when it seems to display «purposiveness»; that is, when its form is perceived to have the character of a thing designed according to some principle and fitted for a purpose.[55] He distinguished «free beauty» from «merely dependent beauty», explaining that «the first presupposes no concept of what the object ought to be; the second does presuppose such a concept and the perfection of the object in accordance therewith.»[56] By this definition, free beauty is found in seashells and wordless music; dependent beauty in buildings and the human body.[56]

The Romantic poets, too, became highly concerned with the nature of beauty, with John Keats arguing in Ode on a Grecian Urn that:

Beauty is truth, truth beauty, —that is all
Ye know on earth, and all ye need to know.

Western 19th and 20th century

In the Romantic period, Edmund Burke postulated a difference between beauty in its classical meaning and the sublime.[57] The concept of the sublime, as explicated by Burke and Kant, suggested viewing Gothic art and architecture, though not in accordance with the classical standard of beauty, as sublime.[58]

The 20th century saw an increasing rejection of beauty by artists and philosophers alike, culminating in postmodernism’s anti-aesthetics.[59] This is despite beauty being a central concern of one of postmodernism’s main influences, Friedrich Nietzsche, who argued that the Will to Power was the Will to Beauty.[60]

In the aftermath of postmodernism’s rejection of beauty, thinkers have returned to beauty as an important value. American analytic philosopher Guy Sircello proposed his New Theory of Beauty as an effort to reaffirm the status of beauty as an important philosophical concept.[61][62] He rejected the subjectivism of Kant and sought to identify the properties inherent in an object that make it beautiful. He called qualities such as vividness, boldness, and subtlety «properties of qualitative degree» (PQDs) and stated that a PQD makes an object beautiful if it is not—and does not create the appearance of—»a property of deficiency, lack, or defect»; and if the PQD is strongly present in the object.[63]

Elaine Scarry argues that beauty is related to justice.[64]

Beauty is also studied by psychologists and neuroscientists in the field of experimental aesthetics and neuroesthetics respectively. Psychological theories see beauty as a form of pleasure.[65][66] Correlational findings support the view that more beautiful objects are also more pleasing.[67][68][69] Some studies suggest that higher experienced beauty is associated with activity in the medial orbitofrontal cortex.[70][71] This approach of localizing the processing of beauty in one brain region has received criticism within the field.[72]

Philosopher and novelist Umberto Eco wrote On Beauty: A History of a Western Idea (2004)[73] and On Ugliness (2007).[74] The narrator of his novel The Name of the Rose follows Aquinas in declaring: «three things concur in creating beauty: first of all integrity or perfection, and for this reason, we consider ugly all incomplete things; then proper proportion or consonance; and finally clarity and light», before going on to say «the sight of the beautiful implies peace».[75][76]

Chinese philosophy

Chinese philosophy has traditionally not made a separate discipline of the philosophy of beauty.[77] Confucius identified beauty with goodness, and considered a virtuous personality to be the greatest of beauties: In his philosophy, «a neighborhood with a ren man in it is a beautiful neighborhood.»[78] Confucius’s student Zeng Shen expressed a similar idea: «few men could see the beauty in some one whom they dislike.»[78] Mencius considered «complete truthfulness» to be beauty.[79] Zhu Xi said: «When one has strenuously implemented goodness until it is filled to completion and has accumulated truth, then the beauty will reside within it and will not depend on externals.»[79]

Human beauty

The word «beauty» is often used as a countable noun to describe a beautiful woman.[80][81]

The characterization of a person as “beautiful”, whether on an individual basis or by community consensus, is often based on some combination of inner beauty, which includes psychological factors such as personality, intelligence, grace, politeness, charisma, integrity, congruence and elegance, and outer beauty (i.e. physical attractiveness) which includes physical attributes which are valued on an aesthetic basis.

Standards of beauty have changed over time, based on changing cultural values. Historically, paintings show a wide range of different standards for beauty.[82][83] However, humans who are relatively young, with smooth skin, well-proportioned bodies, and regular features, have traditionally been considered the most beautiful throughout history.[citation needed]

A strong indicator of physical beauty is «averageness».[84][85][86][87][88] When images of human faces are averaged together to form a composite image, they become progressively closer to the «ideal» image and are perceived as more attractive. This was first noticed in 1883, when Francis Galton overlaid photographic composite images of the faces of vegetarians and criminals to see if there was a typical facial appearance for each. When doing this, he noticed that the composite images were more attractive compared to any of the individual images.[89] Researchers have replicated the result under more controlled conditions and found that the computer-generated, mathematical average of a series of faces is rated more favorably than individual faces.[90] It is argued that it is evolutionarily advantageous that sexual creatures are attracted to mates who possess predominantly common or average features, because it suggests the absence of genetic or acquired defects.[84][91][92][93] There is also evidence that a preference for beautiful faces emerges early in infancy, and is probably innate,[94][95][85][96][97] and that the rules by which attractiveness is established are similar across different genders and cultures.[98][99]

An Indian girl in her traditional attire

A feature of beautiful women that has been explored by researchers is a waist–hip ratio of approximately 0.70. Physiologists have shown that women with hourglass figures are more fertile than other women due to higher levels of certain female hormones, a fact that may subconsciously condition males choosing mates.[100][101] However, other commentators have suggested that this preference may not be universal. For instance, in some non-Western cultures in which women have to do work such as finding food, men tend to have preferences for higher waist-hip ratios.[102][103][104]

Beauty standards are rooted in cultural norms crafted by societies and media over centuries. Globally, it is argued that the predominance of white women featured in movies and advertising leads to a Eurocentric concept of beauty, breeding cultures that assign inferiority to women of color.[105] Thus, societies and cultures across the globe struggle to diminish the longstanding internalized racism.[106] The black is beautiful cultural movement sought to dispel this notion in the 1960s.[107]

Exposure to the thin ideal in mass media, such as fashion magazines, directly correlates with body dissatisfaction, low self-esteem, and the development of eating disorders among female viewers.[108][109] Further, the widening gap between individual body sizes and societal ideals continues to breed anxiety among young girls as they grow, highlighting the dangerous nature of beauty standards in society.[110]

The concept of beauty in men is known as ‘bishōnen’ in Japan. Bishōnen refers to males with distinctly feminine features, physical characteristics establishing the standard of beauty in Japan and typically exhibited in their pop culture idols. A multibillion-dollar industry of Japanese Aesthetic Salons exists for this reason. However, different nations have varying male beauty ideals; Eurocentric standards for men include tallness, leanness, and muscularity; thus, these features are idolized through American media, such as in Hollywood films and magazine covers.[111]

Western concept of beauty

The prevailing Eurocentric concept of beauty has varying effects on different cultures. Primarily, adherence to this standard among African American women has bred a lack of positive reification of African beauty, and philosopher Cornel West elaborates that, «much of black self-hatred and self-contempt has to do with the refusal of many black Americans to love their own black bodies-especially their black noses, hips, lips, and hair.»[112] These insecurities can be traced back to global idealization of women with light skin, green or blue eyes, and long straight or wavy hair in magazines and media that starkly contrast with the natural features of African women.[113]

In East Asian cultures, familial pressures and cultural norms shape beauty ideals; professor and scholar Stephanie Wong’s experimental study concluded that expecting that men in Asian culture didn’t like women who look “fragile” impacted the lifestyle, eating, and appearance choices made by Asian American women.[114][115] In addition to the male gaze, media portrayals of Asian women as petite and the portrayal of beautiful women in American media as fair complexioned and slim-figured induce anxiety and depressive symptoms among Asian American women who don’t fit either of these beauty ideals.[114][115] Further, the high status associated with fairer skin can be attributed to Asian societal history; upper-class people hired workers to perform outdoor, manual labor, cultivating a visual divide over time between lighter complexioned, wealthier families and sun tanned, darker laborers.[115] This along with the Eurocentric beauty ideals embedded in Asian culture has made skin lightening creams, rhinoplasty, and blepharoplasty (an eyelid surgery meant to give Asians a more European, «double-eyelid» appearance) commonplace among Asian women, illuminating the insecurity that results from cultural beauty standards.[115]

Much criticism has been directed at models of beauty which depend solely upon Western ideals of beauty as seen for example in the Barbie model franchise. Criticisms of Barbie are often centered around concerns that children consider Barbie a role model of beauty and will attempt to emulate her. One of the most common criticisms of Barbie is that she promotes an unrealistic idea of body image for a young woman, leading to a risk that girls who attempt to emulate her will become anorexic.[116]

These criticisms have led to a constructive dialogue to enhance the presence of non-exclusive models of Western ideals in body type and beauty. Complaints also point to a lack of diversity in such franchises as the Barbie model of beauty in Western culture.[117] Mattel responded to these criticisms. Starting in 1980, it produced Hispanic dolls, and later came models from across the globe. For example, in 2007, it introduced «Cinco de Mayo Barbie» wearing a ruffled red, white, and green dress (echoing the Mexican flag). Hispanic magazine reports that:

<templatestyles src=»Template:Blockquote/styles.css» />

[O]ne of the most dramatic developments in Barbie’s history came when she embraced multi-culturalism and was released in a wide variety of native costumes, hair colors and skin tones to more closely resemble the girls who idolized her. Among these were Cinco De Mayo Barbie, Spanish Barbie, Peruvian Barbie, Mexican Barbie and Puerto Rican Barbie. She also has had close Hispanic friends, such as Teresa.[118]

Effects on society

Researchers have found that good-looking students get higher grades from their teachers than students with an ordinary appearance.[119] Some studies using mock criminal trials have shown that physically attractive «defendants» are less likely to be convicted—and if convicted are likely to receive lighter sentences—than less attractive ones (although the opposite effect was observed when the alleged crime was swindling, perhaps because jurors perceived the defendant’s attractiveness as facilitating the crime).[120] Studies among teens and young adults, such as those of psychiatrist and self-help author Eva Ritvo show that skin conditions have a profound effect on social behavior and opportunity.[121]

How much money a person earns may also be influenced by physical beauty. One study found that people low in physical attractiveness earn 5 to 10 percent less than ordinary-looking people, who in turn earn 3 to 8 percent less than those who are considered good-looking.[122] In the market for loans, the least attractive people are less likely to get approvals, although they are less likely to default. In the marriage market, women’s looks are at a premium, but men’s looks do not matter much.[123] The impact of physical attractiveness on earnings varies across races, with the largest beauty wage gap among black women and black men.[124]

Conversely, being very unattractive increases the individual’s propensity for criminal activity for a number of crimes ranging from burglary to theft to selling illicit drugs.[125]

Discrimination against others based on their appearance is known as lookism.[126]

See also

  • Adornment
  • Aesthetics
  • Beauty pageant
  • Body modification
  • Glamour (presentation)
  • Processing fluency theory of aesthetic pleasure
  • Mathematical beauty

References

  1. 1.0 1.1 Stegers, Rudolf (2008). Sacred Buildings: A Design Manual. Berlin: De Gruyter. p. 60. ISBN 3764382767.
  2. Gary Martin (2007). «Beauty is in the eye of the beholder». The Phrase Finder. Archived from the original on November 30, 2007. Retrieved December 4, 2007.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  3. 3.00 3.01 3.02 3.03 3.04 3.05 3.06 3.07 3.08 3.09 3.10 3.11 3.12 3.13 3.14 3.15 3.16 3.17 3.18 3.19 3.20 3.21 Sartwell, Crispin (2017). «Beauty». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  4. 4.0 4.1 4.2 4.3 4.4 «Aesthetics». Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved February 9, 2021.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  5. 5.00 5.01 5.02 5.03 5.04 5.05 5.06 5.07 5.08 5.09 5.10 5.11 «Beauty and Ugliness». www.encyclopedia.com. Retrieved February 9, 2021.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  6. 6.0 6.1 «Beauty in Aesthetics». www.encyclopedia.com. Retrieved February 9, 2021.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  7. 7.0 7.1 Levinson, Jerrold (2003). «Philosophical Aesthetics: An Overview». The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics. Oxford University Press. pp. 3–24.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  8. Kriegel, Uriah (2019). «The Value of Consciousness». Analysis. 79 (3): 503–520. doi:10.1093/analys/anz045.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  9. 9.0 9.1 9.2 9.3 9.4 9.5 9.6 9.7 9.8 9.9 De Clercq, Rafael (2013). «Beauty». The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics. Routledge.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  10. 10.0 10.1 10.2 10.3 10.4 10.5 10.6 10.7 10.8 Zangwill, Nick (2003). «Beauty». Oxford Handbook to Aesthetics. Oxford University Press.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  11. 11.0 11.1 11.2 11.3 11.4 11.5 11.6 11.7 11.8 De Clercq, Rafael (2019). «Aesthetic Pleasure Explained». Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism. 77 (2): 121–132. doi:10.1111/jaac.12636.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  12. 12.0 12.1 12.2 12.3 Gorodeisky, Keren (2019). «On Liking Aesthetic Value». Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 102 (2): 261–280. doi:10.1111/phpr.12641. ISSN 1933-1592.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  13. Honderich, Ted (2005). «Aesthetic judgment». The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  14. Scruton, Roger. Beauty: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press. p. 5.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  15. Rogerson, Kenneth F. (1982). «The Meaning of Universal Validity in Kant’s Aesthetics». The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism. 40 (3): 304. doi:10.2307/429687. JSTOR 429687.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  16. Uzgalis, William (2020). «John Locke». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved February 9, 2021.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  17. Berg, Servaas Van der (2020). «Aesthetic Hedonism and Its Critics». Philosophy Compass. 15 (1): e12645. doi:10.1111/phc3.12645.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  18. Matthen, Mohan; Weinstein, Zachary. «Aesthetic Hedonism». Oxford Bibliographies. Retrieved February 10, 2021.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  19. Honderich, Ted (2005). «Beauty». The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  20. Spicher, Michael R. «Aesthetic Taste». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  21. 21.0 21.1 21.2 Craig, Edward (1996). «Beauty». Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  22. Hansson, Sven Ove (2005). «Aesthetic Functionalism». Contemporary Aesthetics. 3.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  23. Konstan, David (2014). Beauty — The Fortunes of an Ancient Greek Idea. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 30–35. ISBN 978-0-19-992726-5.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  24. Matthew 23:27, Acts 3:10, Flavius Josephus, 12.65
  25. 25.0 25.1 Euripides, Alcestis 515.
  26. 26.0 26.1 G Parsons (2008). Aesthetics and Nature. A&C Black. p. 7. ISBN 978-0826496768. Retrieved May 11, 2015.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  27. 27.0 27.1 27.2 27.3 J. Harrell; C. Barrett; D. Petsch, eds. (2006). History of Aesthetics. A&C Black. p. 102. ISBN 0826488552. Retrieved May 11, 2015.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  28. P.T. Struck — The Trojan War Classics Department of University of Penn [Retrieved 2015-05-12]( < 1250> )
  29. R Highfield — Scientists calculate the exact date of the Trojan horse using eclipse in Homer Telegraph Media Group Limited 24 Jun 2008 [Retrieved 2015-05-12]
  30. Bronze Age first source C Freeman — Egypt, Greece, and Rome: Civilizations of the Ancient Mediterranean — p.116, verified at A. F. Harding — European Societies in the Bronze Age — p.1 [Retrieved 2015-05-12]
  31. Sources for War with Troy Cambridge University Classics Department [Retrieved 2015-05-12]( < 750, 850 > )
  32. the most beautiful — C.Braider — The Cambridge History of Literary Criticism: Volume 3, The Renaissance: Zeuxis portrait (p.174) ISBN 0521300088 — Ed. G.A. Kennedy, G.P. Norton & The British Museum — Helen runs off with Paris [Retrieved 2015-05-12]
  33. W.W. Clohesy — The Strength of the Invisible: Reflections on Heraclitus (p.177) Auslegung Volume XIII ISSN 0733-4311 [Retrieved 2015-05-12]
  34. 34.0 34.1 34.2 Fistioc, M.C. The Beautiful Shape of the Good: Platonic and Pythagorean Themes in Kant’s Critique of the Power of Judgment. Review by S Naragon, Manchester College. Routledge, 2002 (University of Notre Dame philosophy reviews). Retrieved May 11, 2015.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  35. 35.0 35.1 35.2 J.L. Wright. Review of The Beautiful Shape of the Good:Platonic and Pythagorean Themes in Kant’s Critique of the Power of Judgment by M.C.Fistioc Volume 4 Issue 2 Medical Research Ethics. Pacific University Library. Retrieved May 11, 2015.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>(ed. 4th paragraph — beauty and the divine)
  36. Seife, Charles (2000). Zero: The Biography of a Dangerous Idea. Penguin. p. 32. ISBN 0-14-029647-6.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  37. 37.0 37.1 Sartwell, C. Edward N. Zalta (ed.). Beauty. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition). Retrieved May 11, 2015.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  38. 38.0 38.1 L Cheney (2007). Giorgio Vasari’s Teachers: Sacred & Profane Art. Peter Lang. p. 118. ISBN 978-0820488134. Retrieved May 11, 2015.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  39. N Wilson — Encyclopedia of Ancient Greece (p.20) Routledge, 31 Oct 2013 ISBN 113678800X [Retrieved 2015-05-12]
  40. K Urstad. Loving Socrates:The Individual and the Ladder of Love in Plato’s Symposium (PDF). Res Cogitans 2010 no.7, vol. 1. Archived from the original (PDF) on October 10, 2015. Retrieved May 11, 2015.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  41. 41.0 41.1 W. K. C. Guthrie; J. Warren (2012). The Greek Philosophers from Thales to Aristotle (p.112). Routledge. ISBN 978-0415522281. Retrieved May 12, 2015.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  42. 42.0 42.1 A Preus (1996). Notes on Greek Philosophy from Thales to Aristotle (parts 198 and 210). Global Academic Publishing. ISBN 1883058090. Retrieved May 12, 2015.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  43. S Scolnicov (2003). Plato’s Parmenides. University of California Press. p. 21. ISBN 0520925114. Retrieved May 12, 2015.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  44. Phaedrus
  45. D. Konstan (2015). text. published by Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0199927265. Retrieved November 24, 2015.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  46. F. McGhee — review of text written by David Konstan published by the Oxonian Review March 31, 2015 [Retrieved 2015-11-24](references not sources: Bryn Mawr Classical Review 2014.06.08 (Donald Sells) + DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199605507.001.0001 )
  47. Nicomachean Ethics
  48. M Garani (2007). Empedocles Redivivus: Poetry and Analogy in Lucretius. Routledge. ISBN 978-1135859831. Retrieved May 12, 2015.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  49. Eco, Umberto (1988). The Aesthetics of Thomas Aquinas. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard Univ. Press. p. 98. ISBN 0674006755.
  50. McNamara, Denis Robert (2009). Catholic Church Architecture and the Spirit of the Liturgy. Hillenbrand Books. pp. 24–28. ISBN 1595250271.
  51. Duiker, William J., and Spielvogel, Jackson J. (2019). World History. United States: Cengage Learning. p. 351. ISBN 1337401048
  52. «NPNF1-02. St. Augustine’s City of God and Christian Doctrine — Christian Classics Ethereal Library». www.ccel.org. Archived from the original on July 1, 2017. Retrieved May 1, 2018.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  53. Francis Hutcheson (1726). An Inquiry Into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue: In Two Treatises. J. Darby. ISBN 9780598982698.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  54. Kennick, William Elmer (1979). Art and Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics; 2nd ed. New York: St. Martin’s Press. p. 421. ISBN 0312053916.
  55. Kennick, William Elmer (1979). Art and Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics; 2nd ed. New York: St. Martin’s Press. pp. 482–483. ISBN 0312053916.
  56. 56.0 56.1 Kennick, William Elmer (1979). Art and Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics; 2nd ed. New York: St. Martin’s Press. p. 517. ISBN 0312053916.
  57. Doran, Robert (2017). The Theory of the Sublime from Longinus to Kant. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 144. ISBN 1107499151.
  58. Monk, Samuel Holt (1960). The Sublime: A Study of Critical Theories in XVIII-century England. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. pp. 6–9, 141. OCLC 943884.
  59. Hal Foster (1998). The Anti-aesthetic: Essays on Postmodern Culture. New Press. ISBN 978-1-56584-462-9.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  60. Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche (1967). The Will To Power. Random House. ISBN 978-0-394-70437-1.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  61. A New Theory of Beauty. Princeton Essays on the Arts, 1. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1975.
  62. Love and Beauty. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989.
  63. Kennick, William Elmer (1979). Art and Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics; 2nd ed. New York: St. Martin’s Press. pp. 535–537. ISBN 0312053916.
  64. Elaine Scarry (November 4, 2001). On Beauty and Being Just. Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-08959-0.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  65. Reber, Rolf; Schwarz, Norbert; Winkielman, Piotr (2004). «Processing fluency and aesthetic pleasure: is beauty in the perceiver’s processing experience?». Personality and Social Psychology Review. 8 (4): 364–382. doi:10.1207/s15327957pspr0804_3. hdl:1956/594. ISSN 1088-8683. PMID 15582859. S2CID 1868463.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  66. Armstrong, Thomas; Detweiler-Bedell, Brian (December 2008). «Beauty as an emotion: The exhilarating prospect of mastering a challenging world». Review of General Psychology. 12 (4): 305–329. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.406.1825. doi:10.1037/a0012558. ISSN 1939-1552. S2CID 8375375.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  67. Vartanian, Oshin; Navarrete, Gorka; Chatterjee, Anjan; Fich, Lars Brorson; Leder, Helmut; Modroño, Cristián; Nadal, Marcos; Rostrup, Nicolai; Skov, Martin (June 18, 2013). «Impact of contour on aesthetic judgments and approach-avoidance decisions in architecture». Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 110 (Supplement 2): 10446–10453. doi:10.1073/pnas.1301227110. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 3690611. PMID 23754408.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  68. Marin, Manuela M.; Lampatz, Allegra; Wandl, Michaela; Leder, Helmut (November 4, 2016). «Berlyne Revisited: Evidence for the Multifaceted Nature of Hedonic Tone in the Appreciation of Paintings and Music». Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. 10: 536. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2016.00536. ISSN 1662-5161. PMC 5095118. PMID 27867350.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  69. Brielmann, Aenne A.; Pelli, Denis G. (May 22, 2017). «Beauty Requires Thought». Current Biology. 27 (10): 1506–1513.e3. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2017.04.018. ISSN 0960-9822. PMC 6778408. PMID 28502660.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  70. Kawabata, Hideaki; Zeki, Semir (April 2004). «Neural correlates of beauty». Journal of Neurophysiology. 91 (4): 1699–1705. doi:10.1152/jn.00696.2003. ISSN 0022-3077. PMID 15010496.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  71. Ishizu, Tomohiro; Zeki, Semir (July 6, 2011). «Toward A Brain-Based Theory of Beauty». PLOS ONE. 6 (7): e21852. Bibcode:2011PLoSO…621852I. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0021852. ISSN 1932-6203. PMC 3130765. PMID 21755004.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  72. Conway, Bevil R.; Rehding, Alexander (March 19, 2013). «Neuroaesthetics and the Trouble with Beauty». PLOS Biology. 11 (3): e1001504. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.1001504. ISSN 1545-7885. PMC 3601993. PMID 23526878.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  73. Eco, Umberto (2004). On Beauty: A historyof a western idea. London: Secker & Warburg. ISBN 978-0436205170.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  74. Eco, Umberto (2007). On Ugliness. London: Harvill Secker. ISBN 9781846551222.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  75. Eco, Umberto (1980). The Name of the Rose. London: Vintage. p. 65. ISBN 9780099466031.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  76. Fasolini, Diego (2006). «The Intrusion of Laughter into the Abbey of Umberto Eco’s The Name of the Rose: The Christian Paradox of Joy Mingling with Sorrow». Romance Notes 46 (2): 119–129.
  77. The Chinese Text: Studies in Comparative Literature (1986). Cocos (Keeling) Islands: Chinese University Press. p. 119. ISBN 962201318X.
  78. 78.0 78.1 Chang, Chi-yun (2013). Confucianism: A Modern Interpretation (2012 Edition). Singapore: World Scientific Publishing Company. p. 213. ISBN 9814439894
  79. 79.0 79.1 Tang, Yijie (2015). Confucianism, Buddhism, Daoism, Christianity and Chinese Culture. Springer Berlin Heidelberg. p. 242. ISBN 3662455331
  80. «Beauty | Definition of Beauty by Oxford Dictionary on Lexico.com also meaning of Beauty». Lexico Dictionaries | English. Retrieved August 1, 2020.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  81. «BEAUTY (noun) American English definition and synonyms | Macmillan Dictionary». www.macmillandictionary.com. Retrieved August 1, 2020.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  82. Artists’ Types of Beauty», The Strand Magazine. United Kingdom, G. Newnes, 1904. pp. 291–298.
  83. Chō, Kyō, and Kyoko Iriye Selden (2012). The Search for the Beautiful Woman: A Cultural History of Japanese and Chinese Beauty. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 100–102. ISBN 1442218959.
  84. 84.0 84.1 Langlois, Judith H.; Roggman, Lori A. (1990). «Attractive Faces Are Only Average». Psychological Science. 1 (2): 115–121. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.1990.tb00079.x. S2CID 18557871.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  85. 85.0 85.1 Strauss, Mark S. (1979). «Abstraction of prototypical information by adults and 10-month-old infants». Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory. American Psychological Association (APA). 5 (6): 618–632. doi:10.1037/0278-7393.5.6.618. ISSN 0096-1515. PMID 528918.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  86. Rhodes, Gillian; Tremewan, Tanya (1996). «Averageness, Exaggeration, and Facial Attractiveness». Psychological Science. SAGE Publications. 7 (2): 105–110. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.1996.tb00338.x. ISSN 0956-7976. S2CID 145245882.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  87. Valentine, Tim; Darling, Stephen; Donnelly, Mary (2004). «Why are average faces attractive? The effect of view and averageness on the attractiveness of female faces». Psychonomic Bulletin & Review. Springer Science and Business Media LLC. 11 (3): 482–487. doi:10.3758/bf03196599. ISSN 1069-9384. PMID 15376799. S2CID 25389002.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  88. «Langlois Social Development Lab – The University of Texas at Austin». homepage.psy.utexas.edu. Archived from the original on February 4, 2015. Retrieved May 1, 2018.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  89. Galton, Francis (1879). «Composite Portraits, Made by Combining Those of Many Different Persons Into a Single Resultant Figure». The Journal of the Anthropological Institute of Great Britain and Ireland. JSTOR. 8: 132–144. doi:10.2307/2841021. ISSN 0959-5295. JSTOR 2841021.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  90. Langlois, Judith H.; Roggman, Lori A.; Musselman, Lisa (1994). «What Is Average and What Is Not Average About Attractive Faces?». Psychological Science. SAGE Publications. 5 (4): 214–220. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.1994.tb00503.x. ISSN 0956-7976. S2CID 145147905.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  91. Koeslag, Johan H. (1990). «Koinophilia groups sexual creatures into species, promotes stasis, and stabilizes social behaviour». Journal of Theoretical Biology. Elsevier BV. 144 (1): 15–35. doi:10.1016/s0022-5193(05)80297-8. ISSN 0022-5193. PMID 2200930.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  92. Symons, D. (1979) The Evolution of Human Sexuality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  93. Highfield, Roger (May 7, 2008). «Why beauty is an advert for good genes». The Daily Telegraph. Telegraph Media Group Limited. Retrieved February 13, 2012.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  94. Slater, Alan; Von der Schulenburg, Charlotte; Brown, Elizabeth; Badenoch, Marion; Butterworth, George; Parsons, Sonia; Samuels, Curtis (1998). «Newborn infants prefer attractive faces». Infant Behavior and Development. Elsevier BV. 21 (2): 345–354. doi:10.1016/s0163-6383(98)90011-x. ISSN 0163-6383.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  95. Kramer, Steve; Zebrowitz, Leslie; Giovanni, Jean Paul San; Sherak, Barbara (February 21, 2019). «Infants’ Preferences for Attractiveness and Babyfaceness». Studies in Perception and Action III. Routledge. pp. 389–392. doi:10.4324/9781315789361-103. ISBN 978-1-315-78936-1.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  96. Rubenstein, Adam J.; Kalakanis, Lisa; Langlois, Judith H. (1999). «Infant preferences for attractive faces: A cognitive explanation». Developmental Psychology. American Psychological Association (APA). 35 (3): 848–855. doi:10.1037/0012-1649.35.3.848. ISSN 1939-0599. PMID 10380874.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  97. Langlois, Judith H.; Ritter, Jean M.; Roggman, Lori A.; Vaughn, Lesley S. (1991). «Facial diversity and infant preferences for attractive faces». Developmental Psychology. American Psychological Association (APA). 27 (1): 79–84. doi:10.1037/0012-1649.27.1.79. ISSN 1939-0599.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  98. Apicella, Coren L; Little, Anthony C; Marlowe, Frank W (2007). «Facial Averageness and Attractiveness in an Isolated Population of Hunter-Gatherers». Perception. SAGE Publications. 36 (12): 1813–1820. doi:10.1068/p5601. ISSN 0301-0066. PMID 18283931. S2CID 37353815.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  99. Rhodes, Gillian (2006). «The Evolutionary Psychology of Facial Beauty». Annual Review of Psychology. Annual Reviews. 57 (1): 199–226. doi:10.1146/annurev.psych.57.102904.190208. ISSN 0066-4308. PMID 16318594.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  100. «Hourglass figure fertility link». BBC News. May 4, 2004. Retrieved July 1, 2018.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  101. Bhattacharya, Shaoni (May 5, 2004). «Barbie-shaped women more fertile». New Scientist. Retrieved July 1, 2018.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  102. «Best Female Figure Not an Hourglass». Live Science. December 3, 2008. Retrieved July 1, 2018.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  103. Locke, Susannah (June 22, 2014). «Did evolution really make men prefer women with hourglass figures?». Vox. Retrieved July 1, 2018.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  104. Begley, Sharon. «Hourglass Figures: We Take It All Back». Sharon Begley. Retrieved July 1, 2018.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  105. Harper, Kathryn; Choma, Becky L. (October 5, 2018). «Internalised White Ideal, Skin Tone Surveillance, and Hair Surveillance Predict Skin and Hair Dissatisfaction and Skin Bleaching among African American and Indian Women». Sex Roles. 80 (11–12): 735–744. doi:10.1007/s11199-018-0966-9. ISSN 0360-0025. S2CID 150156045.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  106. Weedon, Chris (December 6, 2007). «Key Issues in Postcolonial Feminism: A Western Perspective». Gender Forum Electronic Journal.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  107. DoCarmo, Stephen. «Notes on the Black Cultural Movement». Bucks County Community College. Archived from the original on April 8, 2005. Retrieved November 27, 2007.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  108. «Media & Eating Disorders». National Eating Disorders Association. October 5, 2017. Retrieved November 27, 2018.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  109. «Model’s link to teenage anorexia». BBC News. May 30, 2000.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  110. Jade, Deanne. «National Centre for Eating Disorders — The Media & Eating Disorders». National Centre for Eating Disorders. Retrieved November 27, 2018.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  111. «The New (And Impossible) Standards of Male Beauty». Paging Dr. NerdLove. January 26, 2015. Retrieved November 27, 2018.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  112. West, Cornel (1994). Race Matters. Vintage.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  113. «Hey Girl, Am I More than My Hair?: African American Women and Their Struggles with Beauty, Body Image, and Hair — ProQuest». ProQuest 233235409. <templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  114. 114.0 114.1 Wong, Stephanie N.; Keum, Brian TaeHyuk; Caffarel, Daniel; Srinivasan, Ranjana; Morshedian, Negar; Capodilupo, Christina M.; Brewster, Melanie E. (December 2017). «Exploring the conceptualization of body image for Asian American women». Asian American Journal of Psychology. 8 (4): 296–307. doi:10.1037/aap0000077. ISSN 1948-1993. S2CID 151560804.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  115. 115.0 115.1 115.2 115.3 Le, C.N (June 4, 2014). «The Homogenization of Asian Beauty — The Society Pages». thesocietypages.org. Retrieved December 1, 2018.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  116. Dittmar, Helga; Halliwell, Emma; Ive, Suzanne (2006). «Does Barbie make girls want to be thin? The effect of experimental exposure to images of dolls on the body image of 5- to 8-year-old girls». Developmental Psychology. American Psychological Association (APA). 42 (2): 283–292. doi:10.1037/0012-1649.42.2.283. ISSN 1939-0599. PMID 16569167.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  117. Marco Tosa (1998). Barbie: Four Decades of Fashion, Fantasy, and Fun. H.N. Abrams. ISBN 978-0-8109-4008-6.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  118. «A Barbie for Everyone». Hispanic. 22 (1). February–March 2009.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  119. Sharon Begley (July 14, 2009). «The Link Between Beauty and Grades». Newsweek. Archived from the original on April 20, 2010. Retrieved May 31, 2010.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  120. Amina A Memon; Aldert Vrij; Ray Bull (October 31, 2003). Psychology and Law: Truthfulness, Accuracy and Credibility. John Wiley & Sons. pp. 46–47. ISBN 978-0-470-86835-5.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  121. «Image survey reveals «perception is reality» when it comes to teenagers». multivu.prnewswire.com. Archived from the original on July 10, 2012.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  122. Lorenz, K. (2005). «Do pretty people earn more?». CNN News. Time Warner. Cable News Network.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  123. Daniel Hamermesh; Stephen J. Dubner (January 30, 2014). «Reasons to not be ugly: full transcript». Freakonomics. Archived from the original on March 1, 2014. Retrieved March 4, 2014.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  124. Monk, Ellis P.; Esposito, Michael H.; Lee, Hedwig (2021). «Beholding Inequality: Race, Gender, and Returns to Physical Attractiveness in the United States». American Journal of Sociology. 127 (1): 194–241. doi:10.1086/715141. ISSN 0002-9602.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  125. Erdal Tekin; Stephen J. Dubner (January 30, 2014). «Reasons to not be ugly: full transcript». Freakonomics. Archived from the original on March 1, 2014. Retrieved March 4, 2014.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  126. Leo Gough (June 29, 2011). C. Northcote Parkinson’s Parkinson’s Law: A modern-day interpretation of a management classic. Infinite Ideas. p. 36. ISBN 978-1-908189-71-4.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>

External links

Wikimedia Commons has media related to Beauty.
Wikiquote has quotations related to: Beauty
Look up beauty or pretty in Wiktionary, the free dictionary.
  • Sartwell, Crispin. «Beauty». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.<templatestyles src=»Module:Citation/CS1/styles.css»></templatestyles>
  • Beauty at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project
  • BBC Radio 4’s In Our Time programme on Beauty (requires RealAudio)
  • Dictionary of the History of Ideas: Theories of Beauty to the Mid-Nineteenth Century
  • beautycheck.de/english Regensburg University – Characteristics of beautiful faces
  • Eli Siegel’s «Is Beauty the Making One of Opposites?»
  • Art and love in Renaissance Italy , Issued in connection with an exhibition held Nov. 11, 2008-Feb. 16, 2009, Metropolitan Museum of Art, New York (see Belle: Picturing Beautiful Women; pages 246–254).
  • Plato — Symposium in S. Marc Cohen, Patricia Curd, C. D. C. Reeve (ed.)

Beauty is commonly described as a feature of objects that makes these objects pleasurable to perceive. Such objects include landscapes, sunsets, humans and works of art. Beauty, together with art and taste, is the main subject of aesthetics, one of the major branches of philosophy. As a positive aesthetic value, it is contrasted with ugliness as its negative counterpart.

One difficulty in understanding beauty is because it has both objective and subjective aspects: it is seen as a property of things but also as depending on the emotional response of observers. Because of its subjective side, beauty is said to be «in the eye of the beholder».[2] It has been argued that the ability on the side of the subject needed to perceive and judge beauty, sometimes referred to as the «sense of taste», can be trained and that the verdicts of experts coincide in the long run. This would suggest that the standards of validity of judgments of beauty are intersubjective, i.e. dependent on a group of judges, rather than fully subjective or fully objective.

Conceptions of beauty aim to capture what is essential to all beautiful things. Classical conceptions define beauty in terms of the relation between the beautiful object as a whole and its parts: the parts should stand in the right proportion to each other and thus compose an integrated harmonious whole. Hedonist conceptions see a necessary connection between pleasure and beauty, e.g. that for an object to be beautiful is for it to cause disinterested pleasure. Other conceptions include defining beautiful objects in terms of their value, of a loving attitude towards them or of their function.

Overview

Beauty, together with art and taste, is the main subject of aesthetics, one of the major branches of philosophy.[3][4] Beauty is usually categorized as an aesthetic property besides other properties, like grace, elegance or the sublime.[5][6][7] As a positive aesthetic value, beauty is contrasted with ugliness as its negative counterpart. Beauty is often listed as one of the three fundamental concepts of human understanding besides truth and goodness.[5][8][6]

Objectivists or realists see beauty as an objective or mind-independent feature of beautiful things, which is denied by subjectivists.[3][9] The source of this debate is that judgments of beauty seem to be based on subjective grounds, namely our feelings, while claiming universal correctness at the same time.[10] This tension is sometimes referred to as the «antinomy of taste».[4] Adherents of both sides have suggested that a certain faculty, commonly called a sense of taste, is necessary for making reliable judgments about beauty.[3][10] David Hume, for example, suggests that this faculty can be trained and that the verdicts of experts coincide in the long run.[3][9]

Beauty is mainly discussed in relation to concrete objects accessible to sensory perception. It has been suggested that the beauty of a thing supervenes on the sensory features of this thing.[10] It has also been proposed that abstract objects like stories or mathematical proofs can be beautiful.[11] Beauty plays a central role in works of art and nature.[12][10]

An influential distinction among beautiful things, according to Immanuel Kant, is that between dependent and free beauty. A thing has dependent beauty if its beauty depends on the conception or function of this thing, unlike free or absolute beauty.[10] Examples of dependent beauty include an ox which is beautiful as an ox but not beautiful as a horse[3] or a photograph which is beautiful, because it depicts a beautiful building but that lacks beauty generally speaking because of its low quality.[9]

Objectivism and subjectivism

Judgments of beauty seem to occupy an intermediary position between objective judgments, e.g. concerning the mass and shape of a grapefruit, and subjective likes, e.g. concerning whether the grapefruit tastes good.[13][10][9] Judgments of beauty differ from the former because they are based on subjective feelings rather than objective perception. But they also differ from the latter because they lay claim on universal correctness.[10] This tension is also reflected in common language. On the one hand, we talk about beauty as an objective feature of the world that is ascribed, for example, to landscapes, paintings or humans.[14] The subjective side, on the other hand, is expressed in sayings like «beauty is in the eye of the beholder».[3]

These two positions are often referred to as objectivism (or realism) and subjectivism.[3] Objectivism is the traditional view, while subjectivism developed more recently in western philosophy. Objectivists hold that beauty is a mind-independent feature of things. On this account, the beauty of a landscape is independent of who perceives it or whether it is perceived at all.[3][9] Disagreements may be explained by an inability to perceive this feature, sometimes referred to as a «lack of taste».[15] Subjectivism, on the other hand, denies the mind-independent existence of beauty.[5][3][9] Influential for the development of this position was John Locke’s distinction between primary qualities, which the object has independent of the observer, and secondary qualities, which constitute powers in the object to produce certain ideas in the observer.[3][16][5] When applied to beauty, there is still a sense in which it depends on the object and its powers.[9] But this account makes the possibility of genuine disagreements about claims of beauty implausible, since the same object may produce very different ideas in distinct observers. The notion of «taste» can still be used to explain why different people disagree about what is beautiful, but there is no objectively right or wrong taste, there are just different tastes.[3]

The problem with both the objectivist and the subjectivist position in their extreme form is that each has to deny some intuitions about beauty. This issue is sometimes discussed under the label «antinomy of taste».[3][4] It has prompted various philosophers to seek a unified theory that can take all these intuitions into account. One promising route to solve this problem is to move from subjective to intersubjective theories, which hold that the standards of validity of judgments of taste are intersubjective or dependent on a group of judges rather than objective. This approach tries to explain how genuine disagreement about beauty is possible despite the fact that beauty is a mind-dependent property, dependent not on an individual but a group.[3][4] A closely related theory sees beauty as a secondary or response-dependent property.[9] On one such account, an object is beautiful «if it causes pleasure by virtue of its aesthetic properties».[5] The problem that different people respond differently can be addressed by combining response-dependence theories with so-called ideal-observer theories: it only matters how an ideal observer would respond.[10] There is no general agreement on how «ideal observers» are to be defined, but it is usually assumed that they are experienced judges of beauty with a fully developed sense of taste. This suggests an indirect way of solving the antinomy of taste: instead of looking for necessary and sufficient conditions of beauty itself, one can learn to identify the qualities of good critics and rely on their judgments.[3] This approach only works if unanimity among experts was ensured. But even experienced judges may disagree in their judgments, which threatens to undermine ideal-observer theories.[3][9]

Conceptions

Various conceptions of the essential features of beautiful things have been proposed but there is no consensus as to which is the right one.

Classical

The «classical conception»[further explanation needed] defines beauty in terms of the relation between the beautiful object as a whole and its parts: the parts should stand in the right proportion to each other and thus compose an integrated harmonious whole.[3][5][9] On this account, which found its most explicit articulation in the Italian Renaissance, the beauty of a human body, for example, depends, among other things, on the right proportion of the different parts of the body and on the overall symmetry.[3] One problem with this conception is that it is difficult to give a general and detailed description of what is meant by «harmony between parts» and raises the suspicion that defining beauty through harmony results in exchanging one unclear term for another one.[3] Some attempts have been made to dissolve this suspicion by searching for laws of beauty, like the golden ratio.

18th century philosopher Alexander Baumgarten, for example, saw laws of beauty in analogy with laws of nature and believed that they could be discovered through empirical research.[5] As of 2003, these attempts have failed to find a general definition of beauty and several authors take the opposite claim that such laws cannot be formulated, as part of their definition of beauty.[10]

Hedonism

A very common element in many conceptions of beauty is its relation to pleasure.[11][5] Hedonism makes this relation part of the definition of beauty by holding that there is a necessary connection between pleasure and beauty, e.g. that for an object to be beautiful is for it to cause pleasure or that the experience of beauty is always accompanied by pleasure.[12] This account is sometimes labeled as «aesthetic hedonism» in order to distinguish it from other forms of hedonism.[17][18] An influential articulation of this position comes from Thomas Aquinas, who treats beauty as «that which pleases in the very apprehension of it».[19] Immanuel Kant explains this pleasure through a harmonious interplay between the faculties of understanding and imagination.[11] A further question for hedonists is how to explain the relation between beauty and pleasure. This problem is akin to the Euthyphro dilemma: is something beautiful because we enjoy it or do we enjoy it because it is beautiful?[5] Identity theorists solve this problem by denying that there is a difference between beauty and pleasure: they identify beauty, or the appearance of it, with the experience of aesthetic pleasure.[11]

Hedonists usually restrict and specify the notion of pleasure in various ways in order to avoid obvious counterexamples. One important distinction in this context is the difference between pure and mixed pleasure.[11] Pure pleasure excludes any form of pain or unpleasant feeling while the experience of mixed pleasure can include unpleasant elements.[20] But beauty can involve mixed pleasure, for example, in the case of a beautifully tragic story, which is why mixed pleasure is usually allowed in hedonist conceptions of beauty.[11]

Another problem faced by hedonist theories is that we take pleasure from many things that are not beautiful. One way to address this issue is to associate beauty with a special type of pleasure: aesthetic or disinterested pleasure.[3][4][7] A pleasure is disinterested if it is indifferent to the existence of the beautiful object or if it did not arise owing to an antecedent desire through means-end reasoning.[21][11] For example, the joy of looking at a beautiful landscape would still be valuable if it turned out that this experience was an illusion, which would not be true if this joy was due to seeing the landscape as a valuable real estate opportunity.[3] Opponents of hedonism usually concede that many experiences of beauty are pleasurable but deny that this is true for all cases.[12] For example, a cold jaded critic may still be a good judge of beauty because of her years of experience but lack the joy that initially accompanied her work.[11] One way to avoid this objection is to allow responses to beautiful things to lack pleasure while insisting that all beautiful things merit pleasure, that aesthetic pleasure is the only appropriate response to them.[12]

Others

G. E. Moore explained beauty in regard to intrinsic value as «that of which the admiring contemplation is good in itself».[21][5] This definition connects beauty to experience while managing to avoid some of the problems usually associated with subjectivist positions since it allows that things may be beautiful even if they are never experienced.[21]

Another subjectivist theory of beauty comes from George Santayana, who suggested that we project pleasure onto the things we call «beautiful». So in a process akin to a category mistake, one treats one’s subjective pleasure as an objective property of the beautiful thing.[11][3][5] Other conceptions include defining beauty in terms of a loving or longing attitude towards the beautiful object or in terms of its usefulness or function.[3][22] In 1871, functionalist Charles Darwin explained beauty as result of accumulative sexual selection in «The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex».[5]

In philosophy

Greco-Roman tradition

The classical Greek noun that best translates to the English-language words «beauty» or «beautiful» was κάλλος, kallos, and the adjective was καλός, kalos. However, kalos may and is also translated as «good» or «of fine quality» and thus has a broader meaning than mere physical or material beauty. Similarly, kallos was used differently from the English word beauty in that it first and foremost applied to humans and bears an erotic connotation.[23] The Koine Greek word for beautiful was ὡραῖος, hōraios,[24] an adjective etymologically coming from the word ὥρα, hōra, meaning «hour». In Koine Greek, beauty was thus associated with «being of one’s hour».[25] Thus, a ripe fruit (of its time) was considered beautiful, whereas a young woman trying to appear older or an older woman trying to appear younger would not be considered beautiful. In Attic Greek, hōraios had many meanings, including «youthful» and «ripe old age».[25] Another classical term in use to describe beauty was pulchrum (Latin).[26]

Beauty for ancient thinkers existed both in form, which is the material world as it is, and as embodied in the spirit, which is the world of mental formations.[27] Greek mythology mentions Helen of Troy as the most beautiful woman.[28][29][30][31][32] Ancient Greek architecture is based on this view of symmetry and proportion.

Pre-Socratic

In one fragment of Heraclitus’s writings (Fragment 106) he mentions beauty, this reads: «To God all things are beautiful, good, right…»[33] The earliest Western theory of beauty can be found in the works of early Greek philosophers from the pre-Socratic period, such as Pythagoras, who conceived of beauty as useful for a moral education of the soul.[34] He wrote of how people experience pleasure when aware of a certain type of formal situation present in reality, perceivable by sight or through the ear[35] and discovered the underlying mathematical ratios in the harmonic scales in music.[34] The Pythagoreans conceived of the presence of beauty in universal terms, which is, as existing in a cosmological state, they observed beauty in the heavens.[27] They saw a strong connection between mathematics and beauty. In particular, they noted that objects proportioned according to the golden ratio seemed more attractive.[36]

Classical period

The classical concept of beauty is one that exhibits perfect proportion (Wolfflin).[37] In this context, the concept belonged often within the discipline of mathematics.[26] An idea of spiritual beauty emerged during the classical period,[27] beauty was something embodying divine goodness, while the demonstration of behaviour which might be classified as beautiful, from an inner state of morality which is aligned to the good.[38]

The writing of Xenophon shows a conversation between Socrates and Aristippus. Socrates discerned differences in the conception of the beautiful, for example, in inanimate objects, the effectiveness of execution of design was a deciding factor on the perception of beauty in something.[27] By the account of Xenophon, Socrates found beauty congruent with that to which was defined as the morally good, in short, he thought beauty coincident with the good.[39]

Beauty is a subject of Plato in his work Symposium.[34] In the work, the high priestess Diotima describes how beauty moves out from a core singular appreciation of the body to outer appreciations via loved ones, to the world in its state of culture and society (Wright).[35] In other words, Diotoma gives to Socrates an explanation of how love should begin with erotic attachment, and end with the transcending of the physical to an appreciation of beauty as a thing in itself. The ascent of love begins with one’s own body, then secondarily, in appreciating beauty in another’s body, thirdly beauty in the soul, which cognates to beauty in the mind in the modern sense, fourthly beauty in institutions, laws and activities, fifthly beauty in knowledge, the sciences, and finally to lastly love beauty itself, which translates to the original Greek language term as auto to kalon.[40] In the final state, auto to kalon and truth are united as one.[41] There is the sense in the text, concerning love and beauty they both co-exist but are still independent or, in other words, mutually exclusive, since love does not have beauty since it seeks beauty.[42] The work toward the end provides a description of beauty in a negative sense.[42]

Plato also discusses beauty in his work Phaedrus,[41] and identifies Alcibiades as beautiful in Parmenides.[43] He considered beauty to be the Idea (Form) above all other Ideas.[44] Platonic thought synthesized beauty with the divine.[35] Scruton (cited: Konstan) states Plato states of the idea of beauty, of it (the idea), being something inviting desirousness (c.f seducing), and, promotes an intellectual renunciation (c.f. denouncing) of desire.[45] For Alexander Nehamas, it is only the locating of desire to which the sense of beauty exists, in the considerations of Plato.[46]

Aristotle defines beauty in Metaphysics as having order, symmetry and definiteness which the mathematical sciences exhibit to a special degree.[37] He saw a relationship between the beautiful (to kalon) and virtue, arguing that «Virtue aims at the beautiful.»[47]

Roman

In De Natura Deorum Cicero wrote: «the splendour and beauty of creation», in respect to this, and all the facets of reality resulting from creation, he postulated these to be a reason to see the existence of a God as creator.[48]

Western Middle Ages

In the Middle Ages, Catholic philosophers like Thomas Aquinas included beauty among the transcendental attributes of being.[49] In his Summa Theologica, Aquinas described the three conditions of beauty as: integritas (wholeness), consonantia (harmony and proportion), and claritas (a radiance and clarity that makes the form of a thing apparent to the mind).[50]

In the Gothic Architecture of the High and Late Middle Ages, light was considered the most beautiful revelation of God, which was heralded in design.[1] Examples are the stained glass of Gothic Cathedrals including Notre-Dame de Paris and Chartres Cathedral.[51]

St. Augustine said of beauty «Beauty is indeed a good gift of God; but that the good may not think it a great good, God dispenses it even to the wicked.»[52]

Renaissance

Classical philosophy and sculptures of men and women produced according to the Greek philosophers’ tenets of ideal human beauty were rediscovered in Renaissance Europe, leading to a re-adoption of what became known as a «classical ideal». In terms of female human beauty, a woman whose appearance conforms to these tenets is still called a «classical beauty» or said to possess a «classical beauty», whilst the foundations laid by Greek and Roman artists have also supplied the standard for male beauty and female beauty in western civilization as seen, for example, in the Winged Victory of Samothrace. During the Gothic era, the classical aesthetical canon of beauty was rejected as sinful. Later, Renaissance and Humanist thinkers rejected this view, and considered beauty to be the product of rational order and harmonious proportions. Renaissance artists and architects (such as Giorgio Vasari in his «Lives of Artists») criticised the Gothic period as irrational and barbarian. This point of view of Gothic art lasted until Romanticism, in the 19th century. Vasari aligned himself to the classical notion and thought of beauty as defined as arising from proportion and order.[38]

Age of Reason

The Age of Reason saw a rise in an interest in beauty as a philosophical subject. For example, Scottish philosopher Francis Hutcheson argued that beauty is «unity in variety and variety in unity».[54] He wrote that beauty was neither purely subjective nor purely objective—it could be understood not as «any Quality suppos’d to be in the Object, which should of itself be beautiful, without relation to any Mind which perceives it: For Beauty, like other Names of sensible Ideas, properly denotes the Perception of some mind; … however we generally imagine that there is something in the Object just like our Perception.»[55]

Immanuel Kant believed that there could be no «universal criterion of the beautiful» and that the experience of beauty is subjective, but that an object is judged to be beautiful when it seems to display «purposiveness»; that is, when its form is perceived to have the character of a thing designed according to some principle and fitted for a purpose.[56] He distinguished «free beauty» from «merely dependent beauty», explaining that «the first presupposes no concept of what the object ought to be; the second does presuppose such a concept and the perfection of the object in accordance therewith.»[57] By this definition, free beauty is found in seashells and wordless music; dependent beauty in buildings and the human body.[57]

The Romantic poets, too, became highly concerned with the nature of beauty, with John Keats arguing in Ode on a Grecian Urn that:

Beauty is truth, truth beauty, —that is all
Ye know on earth, and all ye need to know.

Western 19th and 20th century

In the Romantic period, Edmund Burke postulated a difference between beauty in its classical meaning and the sublime.[58] The concept of the sublime, as explicated by Burke and Kant, suggested viewing Gothic art and architecture, though not in accordance with the classical standard of beauty, as sublime.[59]

The 20th century saw an increasing rejection of beauty by artists and philosophers alike, culminating in postmodernism’s anti-aesthetics.[60] This is despite beauty being a central concern of one of postmodernism’s main influences, Friedrich Nietzsche, who argued that the Will to Power was the Will to Beauty.[61]

In the aftermath of postmodernism’s rejection of beauty, thinkers have returned to beauty as an important value. American analytic philosopher Guy Sircello proposed his New Theory of Beauty as an effort to reaffirm the status of beauty as an important philosophical concept.[62][63] He rejected the subjectivism of Kant and sought to identify the properties inherent in an object that make it beautiful. He called qualities such as vividness, boldness, and subtlety «properties of qualitative degree» (PQDs) and stated that a PQD makes an object beautiful if it is not—and does not create the appearance of—»a property of deficiency, lack, or defect»; and if the PQD is strongly present in the object.[64]

Elaine Scarry argues that beauty is related to justice.[65]

Beauty is also studied by psychologists and neuroscientists in the field of experimental aesthetics and neuroesthetics respectively. Psychological theories see beauty as a form of pleasure.[66][67] Correlational findings support the view that more beautiful objects are also more pleasing.[68][69][70] Some studies suggest that higher experienced beauty is associated with activity in the medial orbitofrontal cortex.[71][72] This approach of localizing the processing of beauty in one brain region has received criticism within the field.[73]

Philosopher and novelist Umberto Eco wrote On Beauty: A History of a Western Idea (2004)[74] and On Ugliness (2007).[75] The narrator of his novel The Name of the Rose follows Aquinas in declaring: «three things concur in creating beauty: first of all integrity or perfection, and for this reason, we consider ugly all incomplete things; then proper proportion or consonance; and finally clarity and light», before going on to say «the sight of the beautiful implies peace».[76][77]

Chinese philosophy

Chinese philosophy has traditionally not made a separate discipline of the philosophy of beauty.[78] Confucius identified beauty with goodness, and considered a virtuous personality to be the greatest of beauties: In his philosophy, «a neighborhood with a ren man in it is a beautiful neighborhood.»[79] Confucius’s student Zeng Shen expressed a similar idea: «few men could see the beauty in some one whom they dislike.»[79] Mencius considered «complete truthfulness» to be beauty.[80] Zhu Xi said: «When one has strenuously implemented goodness until it is filled to completion and has accumulated truth, then the beauty will reside within it and will not depend on externals.»[80]

As an attribute to humans

The word «beauty» is often[how often?] used as a countable noun to describe a beautiful woman.[81][82]

The characterization of a person as «beautiful», whether on an individual basis or by community consensus, is often[how often?] based on some combination of inner beauty, which includes psychological factors such as personality, intelligence, grace, politeness, charisma, integrity, congruence and elegance, and outer beauty (i.e. physical attractiveness) which includes physical attributes which are valued on an aesthetic basis.[citation needed]

Standards of beauty have changed over time, based on changing cultural values. Historically, paintings show a wide range of different standards for beauty.[83][84] However, humans who are relatively young, with smooth skin, well-proportioned bodies, and regular features, have traditionally been considered the most beautiful throughout history.[citation needed]

A strong indicator of physical beauty is «averageness».[85][86][87][88][89] When images of human faces are averaged together to form a composite image, they become progressively closer to the «ideal» image and are perceived as more attractive. This was first noticed in 1883, when Francis Galton overlaid photographic composite images of the faces of vegetarians and criminals to see if there was a typical facial appearance for each. When doing this, he noticed that the composite images were more attractive compared to any of the individual images.[90] Researchers have replicated the result under more controlled conditions and found that the computer-generated, mathematical average of a series of faces is rated more favorably than individual faces.[91] It is argued that it is evolutionarily advantageous that sexual creatures are attracted to mates who possess predominantly common or average features, because it suggests the absence of genetic or acquired defects.[85][92][93][94]

Since the 1970’s there has been increasing evidence that a preference for beautiful faces emerges early in infancy, and is probably innate,[95][96][86][97][98]
and that the rules by which attractiveness is established are similar across different genders and cultures.[99][100]

A feature of beautiful women which has been explored by researchers is a waist–hip ratio of approximately 0.70. As of 2004, physiologists had shown that women with hourglass figures were more fertile than other women because of higher levels of certain female hormones, a fact that may subconsciously condition males choosing mates.[101][102] However, in 2008 other commentators have suggested that this preference may not be universal. For instance, in some non-Western cultures in which women have to do work such as finding food, men tend to have preferences for higher waist-hip ratios.[103][104][105]

Exposure to the thin ideal in mass media, such as fashion magazines, directly correlates with body dissatisfaction, low self-esteem, and the development of eating disorders among female viewers.[106][107] Further, the widening gap between individual body sizes and societal ideals continues to breed anxiety among young girls as they grow, highlighting the dangerous nature of beauty standards in society.[108]

Western concept

Beauty standards are rooted in cultural norms crafted by societies and media over centuries. As of 2018, it has been argued that the predominance of white women featured in movies and advertising leads to a Eurocentric concept of beauty, which assigns inferiority to women of color.[109] Thus, societies and cultures across the globe struggle to diminish the longstanding internalized racism.[110]

Eurocentric standards for men include tallness, leanness, and muscularity, which have been idolized through American media, such as in Hollywood films and magazine covers.[111]

The prevailing Eurocentric concept of beauty has varying effects on different cultures. Primarily, adherence to this standard among African American women has bred a lack of positive reification of African beauty, and philosopher Cornel West elaborates that, «much of black self-hatred and self-contempt has to do with the refusal of many black Americans to love their own black bodies-especially their black noses, hips, lips, and hair.»[112] These insecurities can be traced back to global idealization of women with light skin, green or blue eyes, and long straight or wavy hair in magazines and media that starkly contrast with the natural features of African women.[113]

Much criticism has been directed at models of beauty which depend solely upon Western ideals of beauty as seen for example in the Barbie model franchise. Criticisms of Barbie are often centered around concerns that children consider Barbie a role model of beauty and will attempt to emulate her. One of the most common criticisms of Barbie is that she promotes an unrealistic idea of body image for a young woman, leading to a risk that girls who attempt to emulate her will become anorexic.[114]

As of 1998, these criticisms, the lack of diversity in such franchises as the Barbie model of beauty in Western culture, had led to a dialogue to create non-exclusive models of Western ideals in body type and beauty.[115] Mattel responded to these criticisms. Starting in 1980, it produced Hispanic dolls, and later came models from across the globe. For example, in 2007, it introduced «Cinco de Mayo Barbie» wearing a ruffled red, white, and green dress (echoing the Mexican flag). Hispanic magazine reports that:

[O]ne of the most dramatic developments in Barbie’s history came when she embraced multi-culturalism and was released in a wide variety of native costumes, hair colors and skin tones to more closely resemble the girls who idolized her. Among these were Cinco De Mayo Barbie, Spanish Barbie, Peruvian Barbie, Mexican Barbie and Puerto Rican Barbie. She also has had close Hispanic friends, such as Teresa.[116]

Black concept

[icon]

This section needs expansion. You can help by adding to it. (November 2022)

In the 1960s the black is beautiful cultural movement sought to dispel the notion of a Eurocentric concept of beauty.[117]

Asian concept

An Indian woman in her traditional attire

In East Asian cultures, familial pressures and cultural norms shape beauty ideals; a 2017 experimental study concluded that expecting that men in Asian culture did not like women who look «fragile» was impacting Asian American women’s lifestyle, eating, and appearance choices.[118][119] In addition to the «male gaze», media portrayals of Asian women as petite and the portrayal of beautiful women in American media as fair complexioned and slim-figured have induced anxiety and depressive symptoms among Asian American women who do not fit either of these beauty ideals.[118][119] Further, the high status associated with fairer skin can be attributed to Asian societal history, as upper-class people hired workers to perform outdoor, manual labor, cultivating a visual divide over time between lighter complexioned, wealthier families and sun tanned, darker laborers.[119] This along with the Eurocentric beauty ideals embedded in Asian culture has made skin lightening creams, rhinoplasty, and blepharoplasty (an eyelid surgery meant to give Asians a more European, «double-eyelid» appearance) commonplace among Asian women, illuminating the insecurity that results from cultural beauty standards.[119]

In Japan, the concept of beauty in men is known as ‘bishōnen’. Bishōnen refers to males with distinctly feminine features, physical characteristics establishing the standard of beauty in Japan and typically exhibited in their pop culture idols. A multibillion-dollar industry of Japanese Aesthetic Salons exists for this reason.[citation needed]

Effects on society

Researchers have found that good-looking students get higher grades from their teachers than students with an ordinary appearance.[120] Some studies using mock criminal trials have shown that physically attractive «defendants» are less likely to be convicted—and if convicted are likely to receive lighter sentences—than less attractive ones (although the opposite effect was observed when the alleged crime was swindling, perhaps because jurors perceived the defendant’s attractiveness as facilitating the crime).[121] Studies among teens and young adults, such as those of psychiatrist and self-help author Eva Ritvo show that skin conditions have a profound effect on social behavior and opportunity.[122]

How much money a person earns may also be influenced by physical beauty. One study found that people low in physical attractiveness earn 5 to 10 percent less than ordinary-looking people, who in turn earn 3 to 8 percent less than those who are considered good-looking.[123] In the market for loans, the least attractive people are less likely to get approvals, although they are less likely to default. In the marriage market, women’s looks are at a premium, but men’s looks do not matter much.[124] The impact of physical attractiveness on earnings varies across races, with the largest beauty wage gap among black women and black men.[125]

Conversely, being very unattractive increases the individual’s propensity for criminal activity for a number of crimes ranging from burglary to theft to selling illicit drugs.[126]

Discrimination against others based on their appearance is known as lookism.[127]

See also

  • Adornment
  • Aesthetics
  • Beauty pageant
  • Body modification
  • Feminine beauty ideal
  • Glamour (presentation)
  • Masculine beauty ideal
  • Mathematical beauty
  • Processing fluency theory of aesthetic pleasure
  • Unattractiveness
  • Cosmetics

References

  1. ^ a b Stegers, Rudolf (2008). Sacred Buildings: A Design Manual. Berlin: De Gruyter. p. 60. ISBN 3764382767.
  2. ^ Gary Martin (2007). «Beauty is in the eye of the beholder». The Phrase Finder. Archived from the original on November 30, 2007. Retrieved December 4, 2007.
  3. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v Sartwell, Crispin (2017). «Beauty». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on February 26, 2022. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
  4. ^ a b c d e «Aesthetics». Encyclopedia Britannica. Archived from the original on February 28, 2022. Retrieved February 9, 2021.
  5. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l «Beauty and Ugliness». Encyclopedia.com. Archived from the original on December 24, 2021. Retrieved February 9, 2021.
  6. ^ a b «Beauty in Aesthetics». Encyclopedia.com. Archived from the original on January 13, 2022. Retrieved February 9, 2021.
  7. ^ a b Levinson, Jerrold (2003). «Philosophical Aesthetics: An Overview». The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics. Oxford University Press. pp. 3–24. Archived from the original on February 10, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
  8. ^ Kriegel, Uriah (2019). «The Value of Consciousness». Analysis. 79 (3): 503–520. doi:10.1093/analys/anz045. Archived from the original on January 11, 2022. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
  9. ^ a b c d e f g h i j De Clercq, Rafael (2013). «Beauty». The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics. Routledge. Archived from the original on January 13, 2022. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
  10. ^ a b c d e f g h i Zangwill, Nick (2003). «Beauty». In Levinson, Jerrold (ed.). Oxford Handbook to Aesthetics. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199279456.003.0018. Archived from the original on January 11, 2022. Retrieved February 16, 2021.
  11. ^ a b c d e f g h i De Clercq, Rafael (2019). «Aesthetic Pleasure Explained». Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism. 77 (2): 121–132. doi:10.1111/jaac.12636.
  12. ^ a b c d Gorodeisky, Keren (2019). «On Liking Aesthetic Value». Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 102 (2): 261–280. doi:10.1111/phpr.12641. S2CID 204522523.
  13. ^ Honderich, Ted (2005). «Aesthetic judgment». The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
  14. ^ Scruton, Roger (2011). Beauty: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press. p. 5. Archived from the original on March 10, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
  15. ^ Rogerson, Kenneth F. (1982). «The Meaning of Universal Validity in Kant’s Aesthetics». The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism. 40 (3): 304. doi:10.2307/429687. JSTOR 429687. Archived from the original on February 10, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
  16. ^ Uzgalis, William (2020). «John Locke». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on April 24, 2021. Retrieved February 9, 2021.
  17. ^ Berg, Servaas Van der (2020). «Aesthetic Hedonism and Its Critics». Philosophy Compass. 15 (1): e12645. doi:10.1111/phc3.12645. S2CID 213973255. Archived from the original on February 11, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
  18. ^ Matthen, Mohan; Weinstein, Zachary. «Aesthetic Hedonism». Oxford Bibliographies. Archived from the original on January 18, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
  19. ^ Honderich, Ted (2005). «Beauty». The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
  20. ^ Spicher, Michael R. «Aesthetic Taste». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on February 14, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
  21. ^ a b c Craig, Edward (1996). «Beauty». Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. Archived from the original on January 16, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
  22. ^ Hansson, Sven Ove (2005). «Aesthetic Functionalism». Contemporary Aesthetics. 3. Archived from the original on February 13, 2021. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
  23. ^ Konstan, David (2014). Beauty — The Fortunes of an Ancient Greek Idea. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 30–35. ISBN 978-0-19-992726-5.
  24. ^ Matthew 23:27, Acts 3:10, Flavius Josephus, 12.65
  25. ^ a b Euripides, Alcestis 515.
  26. ^ a b G Parsons (2008). Aesthetics and Nature. A&C Black. p. 7. ISBN 978-0826496768. Archived from the original on February 3, 2023. Retrieved May 11, 2015.
  27. ^ a b c d J. Harrell; C. Barrett; D. Petsch, eds. (2006). History of Aesthetics. A&C Black. p. 102. ISBN 0826488552. Archived from the original on February 3, 2023. Retrieved May 11, 2015.
  28. ^ P.T. Struck — The Trojan War Archived December 22, 2021, at the Wayback Machine Classics Department of University of Penn [Retrieved 2015-05-12]( < 1250> )
  29. ^ R Highfield — Scientists calculate the exact date of the Trojan horse using eclipse in Homer Archived December 24, 2021, at the Wayback Machine Telegraph Media Group Limited 24 Jun 2008 [Retrieved 2015-05-12]
  30. ^ Bronze Age first source C Freeman — Egypt, Greece, and Rome: Civilizations of the Ancient Mediterranean — p.116 Archived February 3, 2023, at the Wayback Machine, verified at A. F. Harding — European Societies in the Bronze Age — p.1 Archived February 3, 2023, at the Wayback Machine [Retrieved 2015-05-12]
  31. ^ Sources for War with Troy Archived December 8, 2015, at the Wayback Machine Cambridge University Classics Department [Retrieved 2015-05-12]( < 750, 850 > )
  32. ^ the most beautiful — C.Braider — The Cambridge History of Literary Criticism: Volume 3 Archived February 3, 2023, at the Wayback Machine, The Renaissance: Zeuxis portrait (p.174) ISBN 0521300088 — Ed. G.A. Kennedy, G.P. Norton & The British Museum — Helen runs off with Paris Archived October 11, 2015, at the Wayback Machine [Retrieved 2015-05-12]
  33. ^ W.W. Clohesy — The Strength of the Invisible: Reflections on Heraclitus (p.177) Archived August 12, 2017, at the Wayback Machine Auslegung Volume XIII ISSN 0733-4311 [Retrieved 2015-05-12]
  34. ^ a b c Fistioc, M.C. (December 5, 2002). The Beautiful Shape of the Good: Platonic and Pythagorean Themes in Kant’s Critique of the Power of Judgment. Review by S Naragon, Manchester College. Routledge, 2002 (University of Notre Dame philosophy reviews). Archived from the original on January 22, 2016. Retrieved May 11, 2015.
  35. ^ a b c J.L. Wright. Review of The Beautiful Shape of the Good:Platonic and Pythagorean Themes in Kant’s Critique of the Power of Judgment by M.C.Fistioc Volume 4 Issue 2 Medical Research Ethics. Pacific University Library. Archived from the original on March 4, 2016. Retrieved May 11, 2015.(ed. 4th paragraph — beauty and the divine)
  36. ^ Seife, Charles (2000). Zero: The Biography of a Dangerous Idea. Penguin. p. 32. ISBN 0-14-029647-6.
  37. ^ a b Sartwell, C. Edward N. Zalta (ed.). Beauty. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition). Archived from the original on January 18, 2021. Retrieved May 11, 2015.
  38. ^ a b L Cheney (2007). Giorgio Vasari’s Teachers: Sacred & Profane Art. Peter Lang. p. 118. ISBN 978-0820488134. Archived from the original on February 3, 2023. Retrieved May 11, 2015.
  39. ^ N Wilson — Encyclopedia of Ancient Greece (p.20) Routledge, 31 Oct 2013 ISBN 113678800X [Retrieved 2015-05-12]
  40. ^ K Urstad. Loving Socrates:The Individual and the Ladder of Love in Plato’s Symposium (PDF). Res Cogitans 2010 no.7, vol. 1. Archived from the original (PDF) on October 10, 2015. Retrieved May 11, 2015.
  41. ^ a b W. K. C. Guthrie; J. Warren (2012). The Greek Philosophers from Thales to Aristotle (p.112). Routledge. ISBN 978-0415522281. Retrieved May 12, 2015.
  42. ^ a b A Preus (1996). Notes on Greek Philosophy from Thales to Aristotle (parts 198 and 210). Global Academic Publishing. ISBN 1883058090. Retrieved May 12, 2015.
  43. ^ S Scolnicov (2003). Plato’s Parmenides. University of California Press. p. 21. ISBN 0520925114. Retrieved May 12, 2015.
  44. ^ Phaedrus
  45. ^ D. Konstan (2014). Beauty — The Fortunes of an Ancient Greek Idea. published by Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0199927265. Retrieved November 24, 2015.
  46. ^ F. McGhee — review of text written by David Konstan Archived March 10, 2021, at the Wayback Machine published by the Oxonian Review March 31, 2015 [Retrieved 2015-11-24](references not sources: Bryn Mawr Classical Review 2014.06.08 (Donald Sells) Archived November 26, 2014, at the Wayback Machine + DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199605507.001.0001 Archived July 16, 2020, at the Wayback Machine)
  47. ^ Nicomachean Ethics
  48. ^ M Garani (2007). Empedocles Redivivus: Poetry and Analogy in Lucretius. Routledge. ISBN 978-1135859831. Archived from the original on February 3, 2023. Retrieved May 12, 2015.
  49. ^ Eco, Umberto (1988). The Aesthetics of Thomas Aquinas. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard Univ. Press. p. 98. ISBN 0674006755.
  50. ^ McNamara, Denis Robert (2009). Catholic Church Architecture and the Spirit of the Liturgy. Hillenbrand Books. pp. 24–28. ISBN 1595250271.
  51. ^ Duiker, William J., and Spielvogel, Jackson J. (2019). World History. United States: Cengage Learning. p. 351. ISBN 1337401048
  52. ^ «NPNF1-02. St. Augustine’s City of God and Christian Doctrine — Christian Classics Ethereal Library». CCEL. Archived from the original on July 1, 2017. Retrieved May 1, 2018.
  53. ^ Ames-Lewis, Francis (2000), The Intellectual Life of the Early Renaissance Artist, New Haven, Connecticut: Yale University Press, p. 194, ISBN 0-300-09295-4
  54. ^ Francis Hutcheson (1726). An Inquiry Into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue: In Two Treatises. J. Darby. ISBN 9780598982698. Archived from the original on February 3, 2023. Retrieved June 14, 2020.
  55. ^ Kennick, William Elmer (1979). Art and Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics; 2nd ed. New York: St. Martin’s Press. p. 421. ISBN 0312053916.
  56. ^ Kennick, William Elmer (1979). Art and Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics; 2nd ed. New York: St. Martin’s Press. pp. 482–483. ISBN 0312053916.
  57. ^ a b Kennick, William Elmer (1979). Art and Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics; 2nd ed. New York: St. Martin’s Press. p. 517. ISBN 0312053916.
  58. ^ Doran, Robert (2017). The Theory of the Sublime from Longinus to Kant. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 144. ISBN 1107499151.
  59. ^ Monk, Samuel Holt (1960). The Sublime: A Study of Critical Theories in XVIII-century England. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. pp. 6–9, 141. OCLC 943884.
  60. ^ Hal Foster (1998). The Anti-aesthetic: Essays on Postmodern Culture. New Press. ISBN 978-1-56584-462-9.
  61. ^ Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche (1967). The Will To Power. Random House. ISBN 978-0-394-70437-1.
  62. ^ Guy Sircello, A New Theory of Beauty. Princeton Essays on the Arts, 1. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1975.
  63. ^ Love and Beauty. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989.
  64. ^ Kennick, William Elmer (1979). Art and Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics; 2nd ed. New York: St. Martin’s Press. pp. 535–537. ISBN 0312053916.
  65. ^ Elaine Scarry (November 4, 2001). On Beauty and Being Just. Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-08959-0.
  66. ^ Reber, Rolf; Schwarz, Norbert; Winkielman, Piotr (November 2004). «Processing Fluency and Aesthetic Pleasure: Is Beauty in the Perceiver’s Processing Experience?». Personality and Social Psychology Review. 8 (4): 364–382. doi:10.1207/s15327957pspr0804_3. hdl:1956/594. PMID 15582859. S2CID 1868463.
  67. ^ Armstrong, Thomas; Detweiler-Bedell, Brian (December 2008). «Beauty as an Emotion: The Exhilarating Prospect of Mastering a Challenging World». Review of General Psychology. 12 (4): 305–329. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.406.1825. doi:10.1037/a0012558. S2CID 8375375.
  68. ^ Vartanian, Oshin; Navarrete, Gorka; Chatterjee, Anjan; Fich, Lars Brorson; Leder, Helmut; Modroño, Cristián; Nadal, Marcos; Rostrup, Nicolai; Skov, Martin (June 18, 2013). «Impact of contour on aesthetic judgments and approach-avoidance decisions in architecture». Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 110 (Suppl 2): 10446–10453. doi:10.1073/pnas.1301227110. PMC 3690611. PMID 23754408.
  69. ^ Marin, Manuela M.; Lampatz, Allegra; Wandl, Michaela; Leder, Helmut (November 4, 2016). «Berlyne Revisited: Evidence for the Multifaceted Nature of Hedonic Tone in the Appreciation of Paintings and Music». Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. 10: 536. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2016.00536. PMC 5095118. PMID 27867350.
  70. ^ Brielmann, Aenne A.; Pelli, Denis G. (May 2017). «Beauty Requires Thought». Current Biology. 27 (10): 1506–1513.e3. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2017.04.018. PMC 6778408. PMID 28502660.
  71. ^ Kawabata, Hideaki; Zeki, Semir (April 2004). «Neural Correlates of Beauty». Journal of Neurophysiology. 91 (4): 1699–1705. doi:10.1152/jn.00696.2003. PMID 15010496.
  72. ^ Ishizu, Tomohiro; Zeki, Semir (July 6, 2011). «Toward A Brain-Based Theory of Beauty». PLOS ONE. 6 (7): e21852. Bibcode:2011PLoSO…621852I. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0021852. PMC 3130765. PMID 21755004.
  73. ^ Conway, Bevil R.; Rehding, Alexander (March 19, 2013). «Neuroaesthetics and the Trouble with Beauty». PLOS Biology. 11 (3): e1001504. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.1001504. PMC 3601993. PMID 23526878.
  74. ^ Eco, Umberto (2004). On Beauty: A historyof a western idea. London: Secker & Warburg. ISBN 978-0436205170.[non-primary source needed]
  75. ^ Eco, Umberto (2007). On Ugliness. London: Harvill Secker. ISBN 9781846551222.[non-primary source needed]
  76. ^ Eco, Umberto (1980). The Name of the Rose. London: Vintage. p. 65. ISBN 9780099466031.
  77. ^ Fasolini, Diego (2006). «The Intrusion of Laughter into the Abbey of Umberto Eco’s The Name of the Rose: The Christian paradox of Joy Mingling with Sorrow». Romance Notes. 46 (2): 119–129. JSTOR 43801801.
  78. ^ The Chinese Text: Studies in Comparative Literature (1986). Cocos (Keeling) Islands: Chinese University Press. p. 119. ISBN 962201318X.
  79. ^ a b Chang, Chi-yun (2013). Confucianism: A Modern Interpretation (2012 Edition). Singapore: World Scientific Publishing Company. p. 213. ISBN 9814439894
  80. ^ a b Tang, Yijie (2015). Confucianism, Buddhism, Daoism, Christianity and Chinese Culture. Springer Berlin Heidelberg. p. 242. ISBN 3662455331
  81. ^ «Beauty | Definition of Beauty by Oxford Dictionary on Lexico.com». Lexico Dictionaries | English. Archived from the original on August 9, 2020. Retrieved August 1, 2020.
  82. ^ «BEAUTY (noun) American English definition and synonyms | Macmillan Dictionary». Macmillan Dictionary. Archived from the original on July 9, 2017. Retrieved August 1, 2020.
  83. ^ Artists’ Types of Beauty Archived February 3, 2023, at the Wayback Machine», The Strand Magazine. United Kingdom, G. Newnes, 1904. pp. 291–298.
  84. ^ Chō, Kyō (2012). The Search for the Beautiful Woman: A Cultural History of Japanese and Chinese Beauty. Translated by Selden, Kyoko Iriye. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 100–102. ISBN 978-1442218956..
  85. ^ a b Langlois, Judith H.; Roggman, Lori A. (1990). «Attractive Faces Are Only Average». Psychological Science. 1 (2): 115–121. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.1990.tb00079.x. S2CID 18557871.
  86. ^ a b Strauss, Mark S. (1979). «Abstraction of prototypical information by adults and 10-month-old infants». Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory. 5 (6): 618–632. doi:10.1037/0278-7393.5.6.618. PMID 528918.
  87. ^ Rhodes, Gillian; Tremewan, Tanya (1996). «Averageness, Exaggeration, and Facial Attractiveness». Psychological Science. SAGE Publications. 7 (2): 105–110. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.1996.tb00338.x. S2CID 145245882.
  88. ^ Valentine, Tim; Darling, Stephen; Donnelly, Mary (2004). «Why are average faces attractive? The effect of view and averageness on the attractiveness of female faces». Psychonomic Bulletin & Review. Springer Science and Business Media LLC. 11 (3): 482–487. doi:10.3758/bf03196599. ISSN 1069-9384. PMID 15376799. S2CID 25389002.
  89. ^ «The Beauty of Averageness». Langlois Social Development Lab. Archived from the original on February 4, 2015. Retrieved May 1, 2018.
  90. ^ Galton, Francis (1879). «Composite Portraits, Made by Combining Those of Many Different Persons Into a Single Resultant Figure». The Journal of the Anthropological Institute of Great Britain and Ireland. JSTOR. 8: 132–144. doi:10.2307/2841021. ISSN 0959-5295. JSTOR 2841021. Archived from the original on July 26, 2020. Retrieved June 14, 2020.
  91. ^ Langlois, Judith H.; Roggman, Lori A.; Musselman, Lisa (1994). «What Is Average and What Is Not Average About Attractive Faces?». Psychological Science. SAGE Publications. 5 (4): 214–220. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.1994.tb00503.x. ISSN 0956-7976. S2CID 145147905.
  92. ^ Koeslag, Johan H. (1990). «Koinophilia groups sexual creatures into species, promotes stasis, and stabilizes social behaviour». Journal of Theoretical Biology. Elsevier BV. 144 (1): 15–35. Bibcode:1990JThBi.144…15K. doi:10.1016/s0022-5193(05)80297-8. ISSN 0022-5193. PMID 2200930.
  93. ^ Symons, D. (1979) The Evolution of Human Sexuality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  94. ^ Highfield, Roger (May 7, 2008). «Why beauty is an advert for good genes». The Daily Telegraph. Archived from the original on January 11, 2022. Retrieved February 13, 2012.
  95. ^ Slater, Alan; Von der Schulenburg, Charlotte; Brown, Elizabeth; Badenoch, Marion; Butterworth, George; Parsons, Sonia; Samuels, Curtis (1998). «Newborn infants prefer attractive faces». Infant Behavior and Development. Elsevier BV. 21 (2): 345–354. doi:10.1016/s0163-6383(98)90011-x. ISSN 0163-6383.
  96. ^ Kramer, Steve; Zebrowitz, Leslie; Giovanni, Jean Paul San; Sherak, Barbara (February 21, 2019). «Infants’ Preferences for Attractiveness and Babyfaceness». Studies in Perception and Action III. Routledge. pp. 389–392. doi:10.4324/9781315789361-103. ISBN 978-1-315-78936-1. S2CID 197734413.
  97. ^ Rubenstein, Adam J.; Kalakanis, Lisa; Langlois, Judith H. (1999). «Infant preferences for attractive faces: A cognitive explanation». Developmental Psychology. American Psychological Association (APA). 35 (3): 848–855. doi:10.1037/0012-1649.35.3.848. ISSN 1939-0599. PMID 10380874.
  98. ^ Langlois, Judith H.; Ritter, Jean M.; Roggman, Lori A.; Vaughn, Lesley S. (1991). «Facial diversity and infant preferences for attractive faces». Developmental Psychology. American Psychological Association (APA). 27 (1): 79–84. doi:10.1037/0012-1649.27.1.79. ISSN 1939-0599.
  99. ^ Apicella, Coren L; Little, Anthony C; Marlowe, Frank W (2007). «Facial Averageness and Attractiveness in an Isolated Population of Hunter-Gatherers». Perception. SAGE Publications. 36 (12): 1813–1820. doi:10.1068/p5601. ISSN 0301-0066. PMID 18283931. S2CID 37353815.
  100. ^ Rhodes, Gillian (2006). «The Evolutionary Psychology of Facial Beauty». Annual Review of Psychology. Annual Reviews. 57 (1): 199–226. doi:10.1146/annurev.psych.57.102904.190208. ISSN 0066-4308. PMID 16318594.
  101. ^ «Hourglass figure fertility link». BBC News. May 4, 2004. Archived from the original on October 11, 2011. Retrieved July 1, 2018.
  102. ^ Bhattacharya, Shaoni (May 5, 2004). «Barbie-shaped women more fertile». New Scientist. Archived from the original on July 10, 2018. Retrieved July 1, 2018.
  103. ^ «Best Female Figure Not an Hourglass». Live Science. December 3, 2008. Archived from the original on July 10, 2018. Retrieved July 1, 2018.
  104. ^ Locke, Susannah (June 22, 2014). «Did evolution really make men prefer women with hourglass figures?». Vox. Archived from the original on July 10, 2018. Retrieved July 1, 2018.
  105. ^ Begley, Sharon. «Hourglass Figures: We Take It All Back». Sharon Begley. Archived from the original on July 10, 2018. Retrieved July 1, 2018.
  106. ^ «Media & Eating Disorders». National Eating Disorders Association. October 5, 2017. Archived from the original on December 2, 2018. Retrieved November 27, 2018.
  107. ^ «Model’s link to teenage anorexia». BBC News. May 30, 2000. Archived from the original on April 13, 2020. Retrieved October 25, 2009.
  108. ^ Jade, Deanne. «National Centre for Eating Disorders — The Media & Eating Disorders». National Centre for Eating Disorders. Archived from the original on December 24, 2018. Retrieved November 27, 2018.
  109. ^ Harper, Kathryn; Choma, Becky L. (October 5, 2018). «Internalised White Ideal, Skin Tone Surveillance, and Hair Surveillance Predict Skin and Hair Dissatisfaction and Skin Bleaching among African American and Indian Women». Sex Roles. 80 (11–12): 735–744. doi:10.1007/s11199-018-0966-9. ISSN 0360-0025. S2CID 150156045.
  110. ^ Weedon, Chris (December 6, 2007). «Key Issues in Postcolonial Feminism: A Western Perspective». Gender Forum Electronic Journal.
  111. ^ «The New (And Impossible) Standards of Male Beauty». Paging Dr. NerdLove. January 26, 2015. Archived from the original on December 29, 2018. Retrieved November 27, 2018.
  112. ^ West, Cornel (1994). Race Matters. Vintage Books. ISBN 978-0-679-74986-8.[page needed]
  113. ^ Patton, Tracey Owens (July 2006). «Hey Girl, Am I More than My Hair?: African American Women and Their Struggles with Beauty, Body Image, and Hair». NWSA Journal. 18 (2): 24–51. JSTOR 4317206. Project MUSE 199496 ProQuest 233235409.
  114. ^ Dittmar, Helga; Halliwell, Emma; Ive, Suzanne (March 2006). «Does Barbie make girls want to be thin? The effect of experimental exposure to images of dolls on the body image of 5- to 8-year-old girls». Developmental Psychology. 42 (2): 283–292. doi:10.1037/0012-1649.42.2.283. PMID 16569167.
  115. ^ Marco Tosa (1998). Barbie: Four Decades of Fashion, Fantasy, and Fun. H.N. Abrams. ISBN 978-0-8109-4008-6.[page needed]
  116. ^ «A Barbie for Everyone». Hispanic. 22 (1). February–March 2009.
  117. ^ DoCarmo, Stephen. «Notes on the Black Cultural Movement». Bucks County Community College. Archived from the original on April 8, 2005. Retrieved November 27, 2007.
  118. ^ a b Wong, Stephanie N.; Keum, Brian TaeHyuk; Caffarel, Daniel; Srinivasan, Ranjana; Morshedian, Negar; Capodilupo, Christina M.; Brewster, Melanie E. (December 2017). «Exploring the conceptualization of body image for Asian American women». Asian American Journal of Psychology. 8 (4): 296–307. doi:10.1037/aap0000077. S2CID 151560804.
  119. ^ a b c d Le, C.N. (June 4, 2014). «The Homogenization of Asian Beauty». The Society Pages. Archived from the original on December 2, 2018. Retrieved December 1, 2018.[self-published source?]
  120. ^ Begley, Sharon (July 14, 2009). «The Link Between Beauty and Grades». Newsweek. Archived from the original on April 20, 2010. Retrieved May 31, 2010.
  121. ^ Amina A Memon; Aldert Vrij; Ray Bull (October 31, 2003). Psychology and Law: Truthfulness, Accuracy and Credibility. John Wiley & Sons. pp. 46–47. ISBN 978-0-470-86835-5.
  122. ^ «Image survey reveals «perception is reality» when it comes to teenagers» (Press release). multivu.prnewswire.com. Archived from the original on July 10, 2012.
  123. ^ Lorenz, K. (2005). «Do pretty people earn more?». CNN News. Time Warner. Cable News Network. Archived from the original on October 12, 2015. Retrieved January 31, 2007.
  124. ^ Daniel Hamermesh; Stephen J. Dubner (January 30, 2014). «Reasons to not be ugly: full transcript». Freakonomics. Archived from the original on March 1, 2014. Retrieved March 4, 2014.
  125. ^ Monk, Ellis P.; Esposito, Michael H.; Lee, Hedwig (July 1, 2021). «Beholding Inequality: Race, Gender, and Returns to Physical Attractiveness in the United States». American Journal of Sociology. 127 (1): 194–241. doi:10.1086/715141. S2CID 235473652.
  126. ^ Erdal Tekin; Stephen J. Dubner (January 30, 2014). «Reasons to not be ugly: full transcript». Freakonomics. Archived from the original on March 1, 2014. Retrieved March 4, 2014.
  127. ^ Leo Gough (June 29, 2011). C. Northcote Parkinson’s Parkinson’s Law: A modern-day interpretation of a management classic. Infinite Ideas. p. 36. ISBN 978-1-908189-71-4.

Further reading

  • Richard O. Prum (2018). The Evolution of Beauty: How Darwin’s Forgotten Theory of Mate Choice Shapes the Animal World — and Us. Anchor. ISBN 978-0345804570.
  • Liebelt, C. (2022), Beauty: What Makes Us Dream, What Haunts Us. Feminist Anthropology. https://doi.org/10.1002/fea2.12076

External links

Wikimedia Commons has media related to Beauty.

Wikiquote has quotations related to Beauty.

Look up beauty or pretty in Wiktionary, the free dictionary.

  • Sartwell, Crispin. «Beauty». In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Beauty at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project
  • BBC Radio 4’s In Our Time programme on Beauty (requires RealAudio)
  • Dictionary of the History of Ideas: Theories of Beauty to the Mid-Nineteenth Century
  • beautycheck.de/english Regensburg University – Characteristics of beautiful faces
  • Eli Siegel’s «Is Beauty the Making One of Opposites?»
  • Art and love in Renaissance Italy , Issued in connection with an exhibition held Nov. 11, 2008-Feb. 16, 2009, Metropolitan Museum of Art, New York (see Belle: Picturing Beautiful Women; pages 246–254).
  • Plato — Symposium in S. Marc Cohen, Patricia Curd, C. D. C. Reeve (ed.)

Find inspiration and words to describe beauty, with phrases that apply to both to people and places.

  • Beauty Adjectives
  • Beauty Nouns
  • Beauty Verbs
  • Beauty Quotes
  • Beauty Similes
  1. adorable
  2. aesthetic
  3. aesthetically pleasing
  4. aglow
  5. alluring
  6. angelic
  7. appealing
  8. artful
  9. attractive
  10. awe-inspiring
  11. beauteous
  12. beautiful
  13. becoming
  14. belle
  15. bewitching
  16. breathtaking
  17. brilliant
  18. captivating
  19. celebrated
  20. celestial
  21. classic
  22. consummate
  23. contoured
  24. coveted
  25. cute
  26. darling
  27. dazzling
  28. decorative
  29. delicate
  30. desirable
  1. harmonious
  2. head-turning
  3. heavenly
  4. hot
  5. hypnotic
  6. ideal
  7. impeccable
  8. inspirational
  9. inspiring
  10. intoxicating
  11. lovely
  12. luminous
  13. luscious
  14. magnificent
  15. majestic
  16. mesmerizing
  17. musical
  18. mystical
  19. one-of-a-kind
  20. peaceful
  21. perfect
  22. perfectly formed
  23. photogenic
  24. picturesque
  25. pleasing
  26. poetic
  27. prepossessing
  28. pretty
  29. pure
  30. radiant
  1. divine
  2. doll-like
  3. dreamy
  4. drop-dead gorgeous
  5. easy on the eyes
  6. elegant
  7. elevated
  8. enticing
  9. entrancing
  10. enviable
  11. errorless
  12. ethereal
  13. exemplary
  14. exotic
  15. exquisite
  16. fair
  17. fashionable
  18. feminine
  19. fetching
  20. fine
  21. fine-looking
  22. flawless
  23. foxy
  24. fragile
  25. free
  26. glamorous
  27. good-looking
  28. gorgeous
  29. graceful
  30. grand
  1. ravishing
  2. red hot
  3. refined
  4. resplendent
  5. sculptured
  6. sensuous
  7. sexy
  8. sightly
  9. sophisticated
  10. sparkling
  11. special
  12. splendorous
  13. statuesque
  14. streamlined
  15. striking
  16. stunning
  17. stylish
  18. sublime
  19. superb
  20. symmetrical
  21. taking
  22. tasteful
  23. timeless
  24. transcendent
  25. unforgettable
  26. unusual
  27. vibrant
  28. wanted
  29. well-formed
  30. winning

  1. a perfect 10
  2. a vision
  3. admirer
  4. allure
  5. amazement
  6. angel
  7. appeal
  8. appreciation
  9. art
  10. artistry
  11. artwork
  12. awe
  13. beautiful creature
  14. beauty
  15. charm
  16. charmer
  17. composition
  18. cutie pie
  1. infatuation
  2. inner beauty
  3. jewel
  4. knockout
  5. longing
  6. look
  7. looker
  8. loveliness
  9. marvel
  10. miracle
  11. natural beauty
  12. object of desire
  13. objet d’art
  14. perfection
  15. purity
  16. rarity
  17. reverence
  18. sculpture
  1. dish
  2. doll
  3. dream
  4. dream girl
  5. dream guy
  6. dreamboat
  7. elegance
  8. enchanter
  9. exotic beauty
  10. eye candy
  11. eyeful
  12. feast for the eyes
  13. femininity
  14. fox
  15. glorification
  16. good looks
  17. good-looking person
  18. grace
  1. sex appeal
  2. sex symbol
  3. sight
  4. sophistication
  5. stunner
  6. stupor
  7. treasure
  8. uncontested beauty
  9. universal beauty
  10. visual feast
  11. visual poetry
  12. visual treat
  13. wonder
  14. wonderment
  15. work of art
  16. worshiper
  17. wow factor

  1. admire
  2. adore
  3. appeal to
  4. appreciate
  5. astonish
  6. attract
  7. be awestruck
  8. be blown away by
  9. be drawn to
  10. be in awe of
  11. be mad for
  12. be smitten
  13. be taken with
  14. be turned on by
  15. become infatuated
  16. beguile
  17. behold
  18. bewitch
  19. blossom
  20. breath in
  21. captivate
  22. catch sight of
  23. charm
  24. cherish
  25. coax
  26. compare
  27. contemplate
  28. covet
  29. crave
  1. hook
  2. hunger for
  3. hypnotize
  4. idealize
  5. idolize
  6. infatuate
  7. intrigue
  8. knock dead
  9. know
  10. look
  11. look fine
  12. look one’s best
  13. love
  14. lure
  15. lust
  16. lust after
  17. luxuriate
  18. mesmerize
  19. not believe one’s eyes
  20. observe
  21. ogle
  22. persuade
  23. pine
  24. please
  25. please the eye
  26. pleasure
  27. pour over
  28. praise
  29. prize
  1. dazzle
  2. delight in
  3. derive pleasure
  4. desire
  5. draw
  6. dream of
  7. drink in
  8. enchant
  9. enhance
  10. enthrall
  11. entrance
  12. entrap
  13. esteem
  14. exalt
  15. experience
  16. extol
  17. eye
  18. fall for
  19. fancy
  20. fantasize
  21. fascinate
  22. flatter
  23. gawk
  24. gaze
  25. glance
  26. glorify
  27. glow
  28. go ga ga for
  29. grab
  1. recall
  2. regard
  3. rejoice
  4. relish
  5. revere
  6. rub one’s eyes
  7. savor
  8. seduce
  9. see
  10. set ships a sail
  11. stare
  12. strike
  13. study
  14. suck in
  15. sweep off one’s feet
  16. swoon over
  17. take by surprise
  18. take in
  19. tempt
  20. treasure
  21. turn heads
  22. value
  23. venerate
  24. view
  25. want
  26. witness
  27. worship
  28. wow
  29. yearn for

  1. A beauty is a woman you notice; a charmer is one who notices you. -Aldai Stevenson
  2. A fair face without a fair soul is like a glass eye that shines and sees nothing. -John Stuart Blackie
  3. A thing of beauty is a joy forever: its loveliness increases; it will never pass into nothingness. -John Keats
  4. A witty woman is a treasure; a witty beauty is a power. -George Meredith
  5. A woman whose smile is open and whose expression is glad has a kind of beauty no matter what she wears. -Anne Roiphe
  6. A women’s greatest asset is her beauty. -Alex Comfort
  7. Beauty and folly are old companions. -Benjamin Franklin
  8. Beauty awakens the soul to act. -Dante Alighieri
  9. Beauty doesn’t need ornaments. Softness can’t bear the weight of ornaments. -Munshi Premchand
  10. Beauty has a lot to do with character. -Kevyn Aucoin
  11. Beauty in a modest woman is like a distant fire or a sharp-edged sword: the one does not burn, the other does not cut, those who do not come near it. -Miguel de Cervantes
  12. Beauty in a woman’s face, like sweetness in a woman’s lips, is a matter of taste. -M. W. Little
  13. Beauty in things exists in the mind which contemplates them. -David Hume
  14. Beauty is a fragile gift. -Ovid
  15. Beauty is a manifestation of secret natural laws, which otherwise would have been hidden from us forever. -Johann Wolfgang von Goethe
  16. Beauty is all very well at first sight; but who ever looks at it when it has been in the house three days? -George Bernard Shaw
  1. Beauty is whatever gives joy. -Edna St. Vincent Millay
  2. Beauty is worse than wine, it intoxicates both the holder and beholder. -Aldous Huxley
  3. Beauty itself is but the sensible image of the Infinite. -Francis Bacon
  4. Beauty saves. Beauty heals. Beauty motivates. Beauty unites. Beauty returns us to our origins, and here lies the ultimate act of saving, of healing, of overcoming dualism. -Matthew Fox
  5. Beauty without grace is the hook without the bait. -Ralph Waldo Emerson
  6. Beauty without modesty is like a flower broken from its stem. -Anon
  7. Beauty without modesty is like a flower broken from its stem. -Unknown
  8. Beauty without virtue is a rose without fragrance. -German and Danish proverbs
  9. Beauty, like a lantern’s light, will shine outward from within him. -George Garrett
  10. Beauty, like supreme dominion, is best supported by opinion. -Jonathan Swift
  11. Beauty, like truth and justice, lives within us. -George Bancroft
  12. Beauty, like wit, to judges should be shown. -Lord Lyttleton
  13. Beauty…extraordinary, as if it were painted. -Anita Brookner
  14. Beauty: the power by which a woman charms a lover and terrifies a husband. -Ambrose Bierce
  15. Because beauty isn’t enough, there must be something more. -Eva Herzigova
  16. Dear God! how beauty varies in nature and art. In a woman the flesh must be like marble; in a statue the marble must be like flesh. -Victor Hugo
  1. Beauty is as summer fruits, which are easy to corrupt and that cannot last. -Francis Bacon
  2. Beauty is eternity gazing at itself in a mirror. -Khalil Gibran
  3. Beauty is everywhere a welcome guest. -Johann Wolfgang von Goethe
  4. Beauty is in the heart of the beholder. -H. G. Wells
  5. Beauty is less important than quality. -Eugene Ormandy
  6. Beauty is like an almanac; if it lasts a year, it is well. -Thomas Adam
  7. Beauty is like summer fruits which are easy to corrupt and cannot last. -Francis Bacon
  8. Beauty is not caused. It is. -Emily Dickinson
  9. Beauty is only temporary, but your mind lasts you a lifetime. -Alicia Machado
  10. Beauty is our weapon against nature; by it we make objects, giving them limit, symmetry, proportion. Beauty halts and freezes the melting flux of nature. -Camille Paglia
  11. Beauty is power; a smile is its sword. -John Ray
  12. Beauty is the first present nature gives to women and the first it takes away. -Fay Weldon
  13. Beauty is the promise of happiness. -Edmund Burke
  14. Beauty is the sole ambition, the exclusive goal of Taste. -Charles Baudelaire
  15. Beauty is the virtue of the body, as virtue is the beauty of the soul. -Ralph Waldo Emerson
  16. Beauty is unbearable, drives us to despair, offering us for a minute the glimpse of an eternity that we should like to stretch out over the whole of time. -Albert Camus
  1. Even in the centuries which appear to us to be the most monstrous and foolish, the immortal appetite for beauty has always found satisfaction. -Charles Baudelaire
  2. Every year of my life I grow more convinced that it is wisest and best to fix our attention on the beautiful and the good, and dwell as little as possible on the evil and the false. -Richard Cecil
  3. Everything has beauty, but not everyone sees it. -Confucius
  4. Flowers… are a proud assertion that a ray of beauty outvalues all the utilities of the world. -Ralph Waldo Emerson
  5. For me the greatest beauty always lies in the greatest clarity. -Gotthold Ephraim Lessing
  6. He was…all beauty, as the sun is all light. -Phyllis Bottome
  7. How goodness heightens beauty! -Milan Kundera
  8. Outstanding beauty, like outstanding gifts of any kind, tends to get in the way of normal emotional development, and thus of that particular success in life which we call happiness. -Milton R. Sapirstein
  9. She walks in beauty like the night. -Lord Byron
  10. She was as…beautiful as the devil, and twice as dangerous. -Dashiell Hammett
  11. The beauty of a lovely woman is like music. -George Eliot
  12. When a guy tells you that you’re hot; he is looking at your body. When a guy tells you that you’re pretty; he is looking at your face. When a guy tells you that you’re beautiful; he is looking at your heart. -Unknown
  13. Women’s beauty, like men’s wit, is generally fatal to the owners. -Lord Chesterfield
  14. You don’t love a woman because she is beautiful, she is beautiful because you love her. -Unknown

  1. as beautiful and dangerous as a shower of broken glass
  2. as beautiful and refreshing as the glimmering sea
  3. as beautiful as a fine violin
  4. as beautiful as a moonbeam
  5. as flawless and polished as a diamond
  6. as pretty and bright as a new dime
  7. as pretty and thin as a feather on the wind
  8. as pretty and welcoming as a summer breeze
  9. beautiful and bright as the full moon
  10. beautiful and unique as snowflake
  11. beautiful as a country meadow
  12. beautiful as a dream
  13. beautiful as a goddess
  1. beautiful as youth
  2. beautiful like a cloudless night
  3. beautiful like a piece of fine art
  4. beautiful like a statue
  5. beautiful like a tightened bow
  6. beauty as rare as a blue rose
  7. beauty as rare as a precious coin
  8. beauty like a perfume
  9. beauty like a sculpture in motion
  10. beauty like sunshine on a cloudy day
  11. beauty that maddened the soul like wine
  12. beauty that passes like a breath
  13. beauty that shines like a beacon
  1. beautiful as a porcelain doll come to life
  2. beautiful as a saint
  3. beautiful as a wedding cake
  4. beautiful as a woman’s blush
  5. beautiful as a young bride
  6. beautiful as an illusion
  7. beautiful as April rains
  8. beautiful as spring’s first rose
  9. beautiful as the day
  10. beautiful as the dream of youth
  11. beautiful as the evening moon
  12. beautiful as the first flush of dawn
  13. beautiful as the sun going into the sea
  1. beauty was like a light in a dark house
  2. fair as a lily
  3. fair as a star
  4. fair as any rose
  5. fair as marble
  6. fair is she as dreams of poets
  7. gorgeous as the hues of heaven
  8. graceful as a bough
  9. lovely as starry water
  10. pretty as a wax doll
  11. pure as a white dove
  12. pure as prayer
  13. pure as the naked heavens

Понравилась статья? Поделить с друзьями:
  • The word animal in other languages
  • The word animal in latin
  • The word angel means
  • The word and the void
  • The word and the sword