The origin of the word language

A mural in Teotihuacan, Mexico (c. 2nd century) depicting a person emitting a speech scroll from his mouth, symbolizing speech

Language is a structured system of communication that consists of grammar and vocabulary. It is the primary means by which humans convey meaning, both in spoken and written forms, and may also be conveyed through sign languages. The vast majority of human languages have developed writing systems that allow for the recording and preservation of the sounds or signs of language. Human language is characterized by its cultural and historical diversity, with significant variations observed between cultures and across time.[1] Human languages possess the properties of productivity and displacement, which enable the creation of an infinite number of sentences, and the ability to refer to objects, events, and ideas that are not immediately present in the discourse. The use of human language relies on social convention and is acquired through learning.

Estimates of the number of human languages in the world vary between 5,000 and 7,000. Precise estimates depend on an arbitrary distinction (dichotomy) established between languages and dialects.[2] Natural languages are spoken, signed, or both; however, any language can be encoded into secondary media using auditory, visual, or tactile stimuli – for example, writing, whistling, signing, or braille. In other words, human language is modality-independent, but written or signed language is the way to inscribe or encode the natural human speech or gestures.

Depending on philosophical perspectives regarding the definition of language and meaning, when used as a general concept, «language» may refer to the cognitive ability to learn and use systems of complex communication, or to describe the set of rules that makes up these systems, or the set of utterances that can be produced from those rules. All languages rely on the process of semiosis to relate signs to particular meanings. Oral, manual and tactile languages contain a phonological system that governs how symbols are used to form sequences known as words or morphemes, and a syntactic system that governs how words and morphemes are combined to form phrases and utterances.

The scientific study of language is called linguistics. Critical examinations of languages, such as philosophy of language, the relationships between language and thought, how words represent experience, etc., have been debated at least since Gorgias and Plato in ancient Greek civilization. Thinkers such as Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778) have argued that language originated from emotions, while others like Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) have argued that languages originated from rational and logical thought. Twentieth century philosophers such as Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951) argued that philosophy is really the study of language itself. Major figures in contemporary linguistics of these times include Ferdinand de Saussure and Noam Chomsky.

Language is thought to have gradually diverged from earlier primate communication systems when early hominins acquired the ability to form a theory of mind and shared intentionality.[3][4] This development is sometimes thought to have coincided with an increase in brain volume, and many linguists see the structures of language as having evolved to serve specific communicative and social functions. Language is processed in many different locations in the human brain, but especially in Broca’s and Wernicke’s areas. Humans acquire language through social interaction in early childhood, and children generally speak fluently by approximately three years old. Language and culture are codependent. Therefore, in addition to its strictly communicative uses, language has social uses such as signifying group identity, social stratification, as well as use for social grooming and entertainment.

Languages evolve and diversify over time, and the history of their evolution can be reconstructed by comparing modern languages to determine which traits their ancestral languages must have had in order for the later developmental stages to occur. A group of languages that descend from a common ancestor is known as a language family; in contrast, a language that has been demonstrated to not have any living or non-living relationship with another language is called a language isolate. There are also many unclassified languages whose relationships have not been established, and spurious languages may have not existed at all. Academic consensus holds that between 50% and 90% of languages spoken at the beginning of the 21st century will probably have become extinct by the year 2100.[5][6][7]

Definitions

The English word language derives ultimately from Proto-Indo-European *dn̥ǵʰwéh₂s «tongue, speech, language» through Latin lingua, «language; tongue», and Old French language.[8] The word is sometimes used to refer to codes, ciphers, and other kinds of artificially constructed communication systems such as formally defined computer languages used for computer programming. Unlike conventional human languages, a formal language in this sense is a system of signs for encoding and decoding information. This article specifically concerns the properties of natural human language as it is studied in the discipline of linguistics.

As an object of linguistic study, «language» has two primary meanings: an abstract concept, and a specific linguistic system, e.g. «French». The Swiss linguist Ferdinand de Saussure, who defined the modern discipline of linguistics, first explicitly formulated the distinction using the French word language for language as a concept, langue as a specific instance of a language system, and parole for the concrete usage of speech in a particular language.[9]

When speaking of language as a general concept, definitions can be used which stress different aspects of the phenomenon.[10] These definitions also entail different approaches and understandings of language, and they also inform different and often incompatible schools of linguistic theory.[11] Debates about the nature and origin of language go back to the ancient world. Greek philosophers such as Gorgias and Plato debated the relation between words, concepts and reality. Gorgias argued that language could represent neither the objective experience nor human experience, and that communication and truth were therefore impossible. Plato maintained that communication is possible because language represents ideas and concepts that exist independently of, and prior to, language.[12]

During the Enlightenment and its debates about human origins, it became fashionable to speculate about the origin of language. Thinkers such as Rousseau and Johann Gottfried Herder argued that language had originated in the instinctive expression of emotions, and that it was originally closer to music and poetry than to the logical expression of rational thought. Rationalist philosophers such as Kant and René Descartes held the opposite view. Around the turn of the 20th century, thinkers began to wonder about the role of language in shaping our experiences of the world – asking whether language simply reflects the objective structure of the world, or whether it creates concepts that in turn impose structure on our experience of the objective world. This led to the question of whether philosophical problems are really firstly linguistic problems. The resurgence of the view that language plays a significant role in the creation and circulation of concepts, and that the study of philosophy is essentially the study of language, is associated with what has been called the linguistic turn and philosophers such as Wittgenstein in 20th-century philosophy. These debates about language in relation to meaning and reference, cognition and consciousness remain active today.[13]

Mental faculty, organ or instinct

One definition sees language primarily as the mental faculty that allows humans to undertake linguistic behaviour: to learn languages and to produce and understand utterances. This definition stresses the universality of language to all humans, and it emphasizes the biological basis for the human capacity for language as a unique development of the human brain. Proponents of the view that the drive to language acquisition is innate in humans argue that this is supported by the fact that all cognitively normal children raised in an environment where language is accessible will acquire language without formal instruction. Languages may even develop spontaneously in environments where people live or grow up together without a common language; for example, creole languages and spontaneously developed sign languages such as Nicaraguan Sign Language. This view, which can be traced back to the philosophers Kant and Descartes, understands language to be largely innate, for example, in Chomsky’s theory of Universal Grammar, or American philosopher Jerry Fodor’s extreme innatist theory. These kinds of definitions are often applied in studies of language within a cognitive science framework and in neurolinguistics.[14][15]

Formal symbolic system

Another definition sees language as a formal system of signs governed by grammatical rules of combination to communicate meaning. This definition stresses that human languages can be described as closed structural systems consisting of rules that relate particular signs to particular meanings.[16] This structuralist view of language was first introduced by Ferdinand de Saussure,[17] and his structuralism remains foundational for many approaches to language.[18]

Some proponents of Saussure’s view of language have advocated a formal approach which studies language structure by identifying its basic elements and then by presenting a formal account of the rules according to which the elements combine in order to form words and sentences. The main proponent of such a theory is Noam Chomsky, the originator of the generative theory of grammar, who has defined language as the construction of sentences that can be generated using transformational grammars.[19] Chomsky considers these rules to be an innate feature of the human mind and to constitute the rudiments of what language is.[20] By way of contrast, such transformational grammars are also commonly used in formal logic, in formal linguistics, and in applied computational linguistics.[21][22] In the philosophy of language, the view of linguistic meaning as residing in the logical relations between propositions and reality was developed by philosophers such as Alfred Tarski, Bertrand Russell, and other formal logicians.

Tool for communication

Yet another definition sees language as a system of communication that enables humans to exchange verbal or symbolic utterances. This definition stresses the social functions of language and the fact that humans use it to express themselves and to manipulate objects in their environment. Functional theories of grammar explain grammatical structures by their communicative functions, and understand the grammatical structures of language to be the result of an adaptive process by which grammar was «tailored» to serve the communicative needs of its users.[23][24]

This view of language is associated with the study of language in pragmatic, cognitive, and interactive frameworks, as well as in sociolinguistics and linguistic anthropology. Functionalist theories tend to study grammar as dynamic phenomena, as structures that are always in the process of changing as they are employed by their speakers. This view places importance on the study of linguistic typology, or the classification of languages according to structural features, as it can be shown that processes of grammaticalization tend to follow trajectories that are partly dependent on typology.[22] In the philosophy of language, the view of pragmatics as being central to language and meaning is often associated with Wittgenstein’s later works and with ordinary language philosophers such as J.L. Austin, Paul Grice, John Searle, and W.O. Quine.[25]

Distinctive features of human language

A number of features, many of which were described by Charles Hockett and called design features[26] set human language apart from communication used by non-human animals.

Communication systems used by other animals such as bees or apes are closed systems that consist of a finite, usually very limited, number of possible ideas that can be expressed.[27] In contrast, human language is open-ended and productive, meaning that it allows humans to produce a vast range of utterances from a finite set of elements, and to create new words and sentences. This is possible because human language is based on a dual code, in which a finite number of elements which are meaningless in themselves (e.g. sounds, letters or gestures) can be combined to form an infinite number of larger units of meaning (words and sentences).[28] However, one study has demonstrated that an Australian bird, the chestnut-crowned babbler, is capable of using the same acoustic elements in different arrangements to create two functionally distinct vocalizations.[29] Additionally, pied babblers have demonstrated the ability to generate two functionally distinct vocalisations composed of the same sound type, which can only be distinguished by the number of repeated elements.[30]

Several species of animals have proved to be able to acquire forms of communication through social learning: for instance a bonobo named Kanzi learned to express itself using a set of symbolic lexigrams. Similarly, many species of birds and whales learn their songs by imitating other members of their species. However, while some animals may acquire large numbers of words and symbols,[note 1] none have been able to learn as many different signs as are generally known by an average 4 year old human, nor have any acquired anything resembling the complex grammar of human language.[32]

Human languages differ from animal communication systems in that they employ grammatical and semantic categories, such as noun and verb, present and past, which may be used to express exceedingly complex meanings.[32] It is distinguished by the property of recursivity: for example, a noun phrase can contain another noun phrase (as in «[[the chimpanzee]’s lips]») or a clause can contain another clause (as in «[I see [the dog is running]]»).[4] Human language is the only known natural communication system whose adaptability may be referred to as modality independent. This means that it can be used not only for communication through one channel or medium, but through several. For example, spoken language uses the auditive modality, whereas sign languages and writing use the visual modality, and braille writing uses the tactile modality.[33]

Human language is unusual in being able to refer to abstract concepts and to imagined or hypothetical events as well as events that took place in the past or may happen in the future. This ability to refer to events that are not at the same time or place as the speech event is called displacement, and while some animal communication systems can use displacement (such as the communication of bees that can communicate the location of sources of nectar that are out of sight), the degree to which it is used in human language is also considered unique.[28]

Origin

Theories about the origin of language differ in regard to their basic assumptions about what language is.[35] Some theories are based on the idea that language is so complex that one cannot imagine it simply appearing from nothing in its final form, but that it must have evolved from earlier pre-linguistic systems among our pre-human ancestors. These theories can be called continuity-based theories. The opposite viewpoint is that language is such a unique human trait that it cannot be compared to anything found among non-humans and that it must therefore have appeared suddenly in the transition from pre-hominids to early man. These theories can be defined as discontinuity-based. Similarly, theories based on the generative view of language pioneered by Noam Chomsky see language mostly as an innate faculty that is largely genetically encoded, whereas functionalist theories see it as a system that is largely cultural, learned through social interaction.[36]

Continuity-based theories are held by a majority of scholars, but they vary in how they envision this development. Those who see language as being mostly innate, such as psychologist Steven Pinker, hold the precedents to be animal cognition,[15] whereas those who see language as a socially learned tool of communication, such as psychologist Michael Tomasello, see it as having developed from animal communication in primates: either gestural or vocal communication to assist in cooperation.[37] Other continuity-based models see language as having developed from music, a view already espoused by Rousseau, Herder, Humboldt, and Charles Darwin. A prominent proponent of this view is archaeologist Steven Mithen.[38] Stephen Anderson states that the age of spoken languages is estimated at 60,000 to 100,000 years[39] and that:

Researchers on the evolutionary origin of language generally find it plausible to suggest that language was invented only once, and that all modern spoken languages are thus in some way related, even if that relation can no longer be recovered … because of limitations on the methods available for reconstruction.[40]

Because language emerged in the early prehistory of man, before the existence of any written records, its early development has left no historical traces, and it is believed that no comparable processes can be observed today. Theories that stress continuity often look at animals to see if, for example, primates display any traits that can be seen as analogous to what pre-human language must have been like. Early human fossils can be inspected for traces of physical adaptation to language use or pre-linguistic forms of symbolic behaviour. Among the signs in human fossils that may suggest linguistic abilities are: the size of the brain relative to body mass, the presence of a larynx capable of advanced sound production and the nature of tools and other manufactured artifacts.[41]

It was mostly undisputed that pre-human australopithecines did not have communication systems significantly different from those found in great apes in general. However, a 2017 study on Ardipithecus ramidus challenges this belief.[42] Scholarly opinions vary as to the developments since the appearance of the genus Homo some 2.5 million years ago. Some scholars assume the development of primitive language-like systems (proto-language) as early as Homo habilis (2.3 million years ago) while others place the development of primitive symbolic communication only with Homo erectus (1.8 million years ago) or Homo heidelbergensis (0.6 million years ago), and the development of language proper with anatomically modern Homo sapiens with the Upper Paleolithic revolution less than 100,000 years ago.[43][44]

Chomsky is one prominent proponent of a discontinuity-based theory of human language origins.[36] He suggests that for scholars interested in the nature of language, «talk about the evolution of the language capacity is beside the point.»[45] Chomsky proposes that perhaps «some random mutation took place […] and it reorganized the brain, implanting a language organ in an otherwise primate brain.»[46] Though cautioning against taking this story literally, Chomsky insists that «it may be closer to reality than many other fairy tales that are told about evolutionary processes, including language.»[46]

Study

The study of language, linguistics, has been developing into a science since the first grammatical descriptions of particular languages in India more than 2000 years ago, after the development of the Brahmi script. Modern linguistics is a science that concerns itself with all aspects of language, examining it from all of the theoretical viewpoints described above.[47]

Subdisciplines

The academic study of language is conducted within many different disciplinary areas and from different theoretical angles, all of which inform modern approaches to linguistics. For example, descriptive linguistics examines the grammar of single languages, theoretical linguistics develops theories on how best to conceptualize and define the nature of language based on data from the various extant human languages, sociolinguistics studies how languages are used for social purposes informing in turn the study of the social functions of language and grammatical description, neurolinguistics studies how language is processed in the human brain and allows the experimental testing of theories, computational linguistics builds on theoretical and descriptive linguistics to construct computational models of language often aimed at processing natural language or at testing linguistic hypotheses, and historical linguistics relies on grammatical and lexical descriptions of languages to trace their individual histories and reconstruct trees of language families by using the comparative method.[48]

Early history

The formal study of language is often considered to have started in India with Pāṇini, the 5th century BC grammarian who formulated 3,959 rules of Sanskrit morphology. However, Sumerian scribes already studied the differences between Sumerian and Akkadian grammar around 1900 BC. Subsequent grammatical traditions developed in all of the ancient cultures that adopted writing.[49]

In the 17th century AD, the French Port-Royal Grammarians developed the idea that the grammars of all languages were a reflection of the universal basics of thought, and therefore that grammar was universal. In the 18th century, the first use of the comparative method by British philologist and expert on ancient India William Jones sparked the rise of comparative linguistics.[50] The scientific study of language was broadened from Indo-European to language in general by Wilhelm von Humboldt. Early in the 20th century, Ferdinand de Saussure introduced the idea of language as a static system of interconnected units, defined through the oppositions between them.[17]

By introducing a distinction between diachronic and synchronic analyses of language, he laid the foundation of the modern discipline of linguistics. Saussure also introduced several basic dimensions of linguistic analysis that are still fundamental in many contemporary linguistic theories, such as the distinctions between syntagm and paradigm, and the Langue-parole distinction, distinguishing language as an abstract system (langue), from language as a concrete manifestation of this system (parole).[51]

Modern linguistics

Noam Chomsky is one of the most important linguistic theorists of the 20th century.

In the 1960s, Noam Chomsky formulated the generative theory of language. According to this theory, the most basic form of language is a set of syntactic rules that is universal for all humans and which underlies the grammars of all human languages. This set of rules is called Universal Grammar; for Chomsky, describing it is the primary objective of the discipline of linguistics. Thus, he considered that the grammars of individual languages are only of importance to linguistics insofar as they allow us to deduce the universal underlying rules from which the observable linguistic variability is generated.[52]

In opposition to the formal theories of the generative school, functional theories of language propose that since language is fundamentally a tool, its structures are best analyzed and understood by reference to their functions. Formal theories of grammar seek to define the different elements of language and describe the way they relate to each other as systems of formal rules or operations, while functional theories seek to define the functions performed by language and then relate them to the linguistic elements that carry them out.[22][note 2] The framework of cognitive linguistics interprets language in terms of the concepts (which are sometimes universal, and sometimes specific to a particular language) which underlie its forms. Cognitive linguistics is primarily concerned with how the mind creates meaning through language.[54]

Physiological and neural architecture of language and speech

Speaking is the default modality for language in all cultures. The production of spoken language depends on sophisticated capacities for controlling the lips, tongue and other components of the vocal apparatus, the ability to acoustically decode speech sounds, and the neurological apparatus required for acquiring and producing language.[55] The study of the genetic bases for human language is at an early stage: the only gene that has definitely been implicated in language production is FOXP2, which may cause a kind of congenital language disorder if affected by mutations.[56]

The brain

The brain is the coordinating center of all linguistic activity; it controls both the production of linguistic cognition and of meaning and the mechanics of speech production. Nonetheless, our knowledge of the neurological bases for language is quite limited, though it has advanced considerably with the use of modern imaging techniques. The discipline of linguistics dedicated to studying the neurological aspects of language is called neurolinguistics.[57]

Early work in neurolinguistics involved the study of language in people with brain lesions, to see how lesions in specific areas affect language and speech. In this way, neuroscientists in the 19th century discovered that two areas in the brain are crucially implicated in language processing. The first area is Wernicke’s area, which is in the posterior section of the superior temporal gyrus in the dominant cerebral hemisphere. People with a lesion in this area of the brain develop receptive aphasia, a condition in which there is a major impairment of language comprehension, while speech retains a natural-sounding rhythm and a relatively normal sentence structure. The second area is Broca’s area, in the posterior inferior frontal gyrus of the dominant hemisphere. People with a lesion to this area develop expressive aphasia, meaning that they know what they want to say, they just cannot get it out.[58] They are typically able to understand what is being said to them, but unable to speak fluently. Other symptoms that may be present in expressive aphasia include problems with word repetition. The condition affects both spoken and written language. Those with this aphasia also exhibit ungrammatical speech and show inability to use syntactic information to determine the meaning of sentences. Both expressive and receptive aphasia also affect the use of sign language, in analogous ways to how they affect speech, with expressive aphasia causing signers to sign slowly and with incorrect grammar, whereas a signer with receptive aphasia will sign fluently, but make little sense to others and have difficulties comprehending others’ signs. This shows that the impairment is specific to the ability to use language, not to the physiology used for speech production.[59][60]

With technological advances in the late 20th century, neurolinguists have also incorporated non-invasive techniques such as functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) and electrophysiology to study language processing in individuals without impairments.[57]

Anatomy of speech

The human vocal tract

Spectrogram of American English vowels [i, u, ɑ] showing the formants f1 and f2

Real time MRI scan of a person speaking in Mandarin Chinese

Spoken language relies on human physical ability to produce sound, which is a longitudinal wave propagated through the air at a frequency capable of vibrating the ear drum. This ability depends on the physiology of the human speech organs. These organs consist of the lungs, the voice box (larynx), and the upper vocal tract – the throat, the mouth, and the nose. By controlling the different parts of the speech apparatus, the airstream can be manipulated to produce different speech sounds.[61]

The sound of speech can be analyzed into a combination of segmental and suprasegmental elements. The segmental elements are those that follow each other in sequences, which are usually represented by distinct letters in alphabetic scripts, such as the Roman script. In free flowing speech, there are no clear boundaries between one segment and the next, nor usually are there any audible pauses between them. Segments therefore are distinguished by their distinct sounds which are a result of their different articulations, and can be either vowels or consonants. Suprasegmental phenomena encompass such elements as stress, phonation type, voice timbre, and prosody or intonation, all of which may have effects across multiple segments.[62]

Consonants and vowel segments combine to form syllables, which in turn combine to form utterances; these can be distinguished phonetically as the space between two inhalations. Acoustically, these different segments are characterized by different formant structures, that are visible in a spectrogram of the recorded sound wave. Formants are the amplitude peaks in the frequency spectrum of a specific sound.[62][63]

Vowels are those sounds that have no audible friction caused by the narrowing or obstruction of some part of the upper vocal tract. They vary in quality according to the degree of lip aperture and the placement of the tongue within the oral cavity.[62] Vowels are called close when the lips are relatively closed, as in the pronunciation of the vowel [i] (English «ee»), or open when the lips are relatively open, as in the vowel [a] (English «ah»). If the tongue is located towards the back of the mouth, the quality changes, creating vowels such as [u] (English «oo»). The quality also changes depending on whether the lips are rounded as opposed to unrounded, creating distinctions such as that between [i] (unrounded front vowel such as English «ee») and [y] (rounded front vowel such as German «ü»).[64]

Consonants are those sounds that have audible friction or closure at some point within the upper vocal tract. Consonant sounds vary by place of articulation, i.e. the place in the vocal tract where the airflow is obstructed, commonly at the lips, teeth, alveolar ridge, palate, velum, uvula, or glottis. Each place of articulation produces a different set of consonant sounds, which are further distinguished by manner of articulation, or the kind of friction, whether full closure, in which case the consonant is called occlusive or stop, or different degrees of aperture creating fricatives and approximants. Consonants can also be either voiced or unvoiced, depending on whether the vocal cords are set in vibration by airflow during the production of the sound. Voicing is what separates English [s] in bus (unvoiced sibilant) from [z] in buzz (voiced sibilant).[65]

Some speech sounds, both vowels and consonants, involve release of air flow through the nasal cavity, and these are called nasals or nasalized sounds. Other sounds are defined by the way the tongue moves within the mouth such as the l-sounds (called laterals, because the air flows along both sides of the tongue), and the r-sounds (called rhotics).[63]

By using these speech organs, humans can produce hundreds of distinct sounds: some appear very often in the world’s languages, whereas others are much more common in certain language families, language areas, or even specific to a single language.[66]

Modality

Human languages display considerable plasticity [1] in their deployment of two fundamental modes: oral (speech and mouthing) and manual (sign and gesture).[note 3] For example, it is common for oral language to be accompanied by gesture, and for sign language to be accompanied by mouthing. In addition, some language communities use both modes to convey lexical or grammatical meaning, each mode complementing the other. Such bimodal use of language is especially common in genres such as story-telling (with Plains Indian Sign Language and Australian Aboriginal sign languages used alongside oral language, for example), but also occurs in mundane conversation. For instance, many Australian languages have a rich set of case suffixes that provide details about the instrument used to perform an action. Others lack such grammatical precision in the oral mode, but supplement it with gesture to convey that information in the sign mode. In Iwaidja, for example, ‘he went out for fish using a torch’ is spoken as simply «he-hunted fish torch», but the word for ‘torch’ is accompanied by a gesture indicating that it was held. In another example, the ritual language Damin had a heavily reduced oral vocabulary of only a few hundred words, each of which was very general in meaning, but which were supplemented by gesture for greater precision (e.g., the single word for fish, l*i, was accompanied by a gesture to indicate the kind of fish).[67]

Secondary modes of language, by which a fundamental mode is conveyed in a different medium, include writing (including braille), sign (in manually coded language), whistling and drumming. Tertiary modes – such as semaphore, Morse code and spelling alphabets – convey the secondary mode of writing in a different medium. For some extinct languages that are maintained for ritual or liturgical purposes, writing may be the primary mode, with speech secondary.

Structure

When described as a system of symbolic communication, language is traditionally seen as consisting of three parts: signs, meanings, and a code connecting signs with their meanings. The study of the process of semiosis, how signs and meanings are combined, used, and interpreted is called semiotics. Signs can be composed of sounds, gestures, letters, or symbols, depending on whether the language is spoken, signed, or written, and they can be combined into complex signs, such as words and phrases. When used in communication, a sign is encoded and transmitted by a sender through a channel to a receiver who decodes it.[68]

Some of the properties that define human language as opposed to other communication systems are: the arbitrariness of the linguistic sign, meaning that there is no predictable connection between a linguistic sign and its meaning; the duality of the linguistic system, meaning that linguistic structures are built by combining elements into larger structures that can be seen as layered, e.g. how sounds build words and words build phrases; the discreteness of the elements of language, meaning that the elements out of which linguistic signs are constructed are discrete units, e.g. sounds and words, that can be distinguished from each other and rearranged in different patterns; and the productivity of the linguistic system, meaning that the finite number of linguistic elements can be combined into a theoretically infinite number of combinations.[68]

The rules by which signs can be combined to form words and phrases are called syntax or grammar. The meaning that is connected to individual signs, morphemes, words, phrases, and texts is called semantics.[69] The division of language into separate but connected systems of sign and meaning goes back to the first linguistic studies of de Saussure and is now used in almost all branches of linguistics.[70]

Semantics

Languages express meaning by relating a sign form to a meaning, or its content. Sign forms must be something that can be perceived, for example, in sounds, images, or gestures, and then related to a specific meaning by social convention. Because the basic relation of meaning for most linguistic signs is based on social convention, linguistic signs can be considered arbitrary, in the sense that the convention is established socially and historically, rather than by means of a natural relation between a specific sign form and its meaning.[17]

Thus, languages must have a vocabulary of signs related to specific meaning. The English sign «dog» denotes, for example, a member of the species Canis familiaris. In a language, the array of arbitrary signs connected to specific meanings is called the lexicon, and a single sign connected to a meaning is called a lexeme. Not all meanings in a language are represented by single words. Often, semantic concepts are embedded in the morphology or syntax of the language in the form of grammatical categories.[71]

All languages contain the semantic structure of predication: a structure that predicates a property, state, or action. Traditionally, semantics has been understood to be the study of how speakers and interpreters assign truth values to statements, so that meaning is understood to be the process by which a predicate can be said to be true or false about an entity, e.g. «[x [is y]]» or «[x [does y]]». Recently, this model of semantics has been complemented with more dynamic models of meaning that incorporate shared knowledge about the context in which a sign is interpreted into the production of meaning. Such models of meaning are explored in the field of pragmatics.[71]

Sounds and symbols

A spectrogram showing the sound of the spoken English word «man», which is written phonetically as [mæn]. In flowing speech, there is no clear division between segments, only a smooth transition as the vocal apparatus moves.

The syllable «wi» in the Hangul script

Depending on modality, language structure can be based on systems of sounds (speech), gestures (sign languages), or graphic or tactile symbols (writing). The ways in which languages use sounds or signs to construct meaning are studied in phonology.[72]

Sounds as part of a linguistic system are called phonemes.[73] Phonemes are abstract units of sound, defined as the smallest units in a language that can serve to distinguish between the meaning of a pair of minimally different words, a so-called minimal pair. In English, for example, the words bat [bæt] and pat [pʰæt] form a minimal pair, in which the distinction between /b/ and /p/ differentiates the two words, which have different meanings. However, each language contrasts sounds in different ways. For example, in a language that does not distinguish between voiced and unvoiced consonants, the sounds [p] and [b] (if they both occur) could be considered a single phoneme, and consequently, the two pronunciations would have the same meaning. Similarly, the English language does not distinguish phonemically between aspirated and non-aspirated pronunciations of consonants, as many other languages like Korean and Hindi do: the unaspirated /p/ in spin [spɪn] and the aspirated /p/ in pin [pʰɪn] are considered to be merely different ways of pronouncing the same phoneme (such variants of a single phoneme are called allophones), whereas in Mandarin Chinese, the same difference in pronunciation distinguishes between the words [pʰá] ‘crouch’ and [pá] ‘eight’ (the accent above the á means that the vowel is pronounced with a high tone).[74]

All spoken languages have phonemes of at least two different categories, vowels and consonants, that can be combined to form syllables.[62] As well as segments such as consonants and vowels, some languages also use sound in other ways to convey meaning. Many languages, for example, use stress, pitch, duration, and tone to distinguish meaning. Because these phenomena operate outside of the level of single segments, they are called suprasegmental.[75] Some languages have only a few phonemes, for example, Rotokas and Pirahã language with 11 and 10 phonemes respectively, whereas languages like Taa may have as many as 141 phonemes.[74] In sign languages, the equivalent to phonemes (formerly called cheremes) are defined by the basic elements of gestures, such as hand shape, orientation, location, and motion, which correspond to manners of articulation in spoken language.[76][77][78]

Writing systems represent language using visual symbols, which may or may not correspond to the sounds of spoken language. The Latin alphabet (and those on which it is based or that have been derived from it) was originally based on the representation of single sounds, so that words were constructed from letters that generally denote a single consonant or vowel in the structure of the word. In syllabic scripts, such as the Inuktitut syllabary, each sign represents a whole syllable. In logographic scripts, each sign represents an entire word,[79] and will generally bear no relation to the sound of that word in spoken language.

Because all languages have a very large number of words, no purely logographic scripts are known to exist. Written language represents the way spoken sounds and words follow one after another by arranging symbols according to a pattern that follows a certain direction. The direction used in a writing system is entirely arbitrary and established by convention. Some writing systems use the horizontal axis (left to right as the Latin script or right to left as the Arabic script), while others such as traditional Chinese writing use the vertical dimension (from top to bottom). A few writing systems use opposite directions for alternating lines, and others, such as the ancient Maya script, can be written in either direction and rely on graphic cues to show the reader the direction of reading.[80]

In order to represent the sounds of the world’s languages in writing, linguists have developed the International Phonetic Alphabet, designed to represent all of the discrete sounds that are known to contribute to meaning in human languages.[81]

Grammar

Grammar is the study of how meaningful elements called morphemes within a language can be combined into utterances. Morphemes can either be free or bound. If they are free to be moved around within an utterance, they are usually called words, and if they are bound to other words or morphemes, they are called affixes. The way in which meaningful elements can be combined within a language is governed by rules. The study of the rules for the internal structure of words are called morphology. The rules of the internal structure of phrases and sentences are called syntax.[82]

Grammatical categories

Grammar can be described as a system of categories and a set of rules that determine how categories combine to form different aspects of meaning.[83] Languages differ widely in whether they are encoded through the use of categories or lexical units. However, several categories are so common as to be nearly universal. Such universal categories include the encoding of the grammatical relations of participants and predicates by grammatically distinguishing between their relations to a predicate, the encoding of temporal and spatial relations on predicates, and a system of grammatical person governing reference to and distinction between speakers and addressees and those about whom they are speaking.[84]

Word classes

Languages organize their parts of speech into classes according to their functions and positions relative to other parts. All languages, for instance, make a basic distinction between a group of words that prototypically denotes things and concepts and a group of words that prototypically denotes actions and events. The first group, which includes English words such as «dog» and «song», are usually called nouns. The second, which includes «think» and «sing», are called verbs. Another common category is the adjective: words that describe properties or qualities of nouns, such as «red» or «big». Word classes can be «open» if new words can continuously be added to the class, or relatively «closed» if there is a fixed number of words in a class. In English, the class of pronouns is closed, whereas the class of adjectives is open, since an infinite number of adjectives can be constructed from verbs (e.g. «saddened») or nouns (e.g. with the -like suffix, as in «noun-like»). In other languages such as Korean, the situation is the opposite, and new pronouns can be constructed, whereas the number of adjectives is fixed.[85]

Word classes also carry out differing functions in grammar. Prototypically, verbs are used to construct predicates, while nouns are used as arguments of predicates. In a sentence such as «Sally runs», the predicate is «runs», because it is the word that predicates a specific state about its argument «Sally». Some verbs such as «curse» can take two arguments, e.g. «Sally cursed John». A predicate that can only take a single argument is called intransitive, while a predicate that can take two arguments is called transitive.[86]

Many other word classes exist in different languages, such as conjunctions like «and» that serve to join two sentences, articles that introduce a noun, interjections such as «wow!», or ideophones like «splash» that mimic the sound of some event. Some languages have positionals that describe the spatial position of an event or entity. Many languages have classifiers that identify countable nouns as belonging to a particular type or having a particular shape. For instance, in Japanese, the general noun classifier for humans is nin (人), and it is used for counting humans, whatever they are called:[87]

san-nin no gakusei (三人の学生) lit. «3 human-classifier of student» — three students

For trees, it would be:

san-bon no ki (三本の木) lit. «3 classifier-for-long-objects of tree» — three trees

Morphology

In linguistics, the study of the internal structure of complex words and the processes by which words are formed is called morphology. In most languages, it is possible to construct complex words that are built of several morphemes. For instance, the English word «unexpected» can be analyzed as being composed of the three morphemes «un-«, «expect» and «-ed».[88]

Morphemes can be classified according to whether they are independent morphemes, so-called roots, or whether they can only co-occur attached to other morphemes. These bound morphemes or affixes can be classified according to their position in relation to the root: prefixes precede the root, suffixes follow the root, and infixes are inserted in the middle of a root. Affixes serve to modify or elaborate the meaning of the root. Some languages change the meaning of words by changing the phonological structure of a word, for example, the English word «run», which in the past tense is «ran». This process is called ablaut. Furthermore, morphology distinguishes between the process of inflection, which modifies or elaborates on a word, and the process of derivation, which creates a new word from an existing one. In English, the verb «sing» has the inflectional forms «singing» and «sung», which are both verbs, and the derivational form «singer», which is a noun derived from the verb with the agentive suffix «-er».[89]

Languages differ widely in how much they rely on morphological processes of word formation. In some languages, for example, Chinese, there are no morphological processes, and all grammatical information is encoded syntactically by forming strings of single words. This type of morpho-syntax is often called isolating, or analytic, because there is almost a full correspondence between a single word and a single aspect of meaning. Most languages have words consisting of several morphemes, but they vary in the degree to which morphemes are discrete units. In many languages, notably in most Indo-European languages, single morphemes may have several distinct meanings that cannot be analyzed into smaller segments. For example, in Latin, the word bonus, or «good», consists of the root bon-, meaning «good», and the suffix —us, which indicates masculine gender, singular number, and nominative case. These languages are called fusional languages, because several meanings may be fused into a single morpheme. The opposite of fusional languages are agglutinative languages which construct words by stringing morphemes together in chains, but with each morpheme as a discrete semantic unit. An example of such a language is Turkish, where for example, the word evlerinizden, or «from your houses», consists of the morphemes, ev-ler-iniz-den with the meanings house-plural-your-from. The languages that rely on morphology to the greatest extent are traditionally called polysynthetic languages. They may express the equivalent of an entire English sentence in a single word. For example, in Persian the single word nafahmidamesh means I didn’t understand it consisting of morphemes na-fahm-id-am-esh with the meanings, «negation.understand.past.I.it». As another example with more complexity, in the Yupik word tuntussuqatarniksatengqiggtuq, which means «He had not yet said again that he was going to hunt reindeer», the word consists of the morphemes tuntu-ssur-qatar-ni-ksaite-ngqiggte-uq with the meanings, «reindeer-hunt-future-say-negation-again-third.person.singular.indicative», and except for the morpheme tuntu («reindeer») none of the other morphemes can appear in isolation.[90]

Many languages use morphology to cross-reference words within a sentence. This is sometimes called agreement. For example, in many Indo-European languages, adjectives must cross-reference the noun they modify in terms of number, case, and gender, so that the Latin adjective bonus, or «good», is inflected to agree with a noun that is masculine gender, singular number, and nominative case. In many polysynthetic languages, verbs cross-reference their subjects and objects. In these types of languages, a single verb may include information that would require an entire sentence in English. For example, in the Basque phrase ikusi nauzu, or «you saw me», the past tense auxiliary verb n-au-zu (similar to English «do») agrees with both the subject (you) expressed by the n— prefix, and with the object (me) expressed by the – zu suffix. The sentence could be directly transliterated as «see you-did-me»[91]

Syntax

In addition to word classes, a sentence can be analyzed in terms of grammatical functions: «The cat» is the subject of the phrase, «on the mat» is a locative phrase, and «sat» is the core of the predicate.

Another way in which languages convey meaning is through the order of words within a sentence. The grammatical rules for how to produce new sentences from words that are already known is called syntax. The syntactical rules of a language determine why a sentence in English such as «I love you» is meaningful, but «*love you I» is not.[note 4] Syntactical rules determine how word order and sentence structure is constrained, and how those constraints contribute to meaning.[93] For example, in English, the two sentences «the slaves were cursing the master» and «the master was cursing the slaves» mean different things, because the role of the grammatical subject is encoded by the noun being in front of the verb, and the role of object is encoded by the noun appearing after the verb. Conversely, in Latin, both Dominus servos vituperabat and Servos vituperabat dominus mean «the master was reprimanding the slaves», because servos, or «slaves», is in the accusative case, showing that they are the grammatical object of the sentence, and dominus, or «master», is in the nominative case, showing that he is the subject.[94]

Latin uses morphology to express the distinction between subject and object, whereas English uses word order. Another example of how syntactic rules contribute to meaning is the rule of inverse word order in questions, which exists in many languages. This rule explains why when in English, the phrase «John is talking to Lucy» is turned into a question, it becomes «Who is John talking to?», and not «John is talking to who?». The latter example may be used as a way of placing special emphasis on «who», thereby slightly altering the meaning of the question. Syntax also includes the rules for how complex sentences are structured by grouping words together in units, called phrases, that can occupy different places in a larger syntactic structure. Sentences can be described as consisting of phrases connected in a tree structure, connecting the phrases to each other at different levels.[95] To the right is a graphic representation of the syntactic analysis of the English sentence «the cat sat on the mat». The sentence is analyzed as being constituted by a noun phrase, a verb, and a prepositional phrase; the prepositional phrase is further divided into a preposition and a noun phrase, and the noun phrases consist of an article and a noun.[96]

The reason sentences can be seen as being composed of phrases is because each phrase would be moved around as a single element if syntactic operations were carried out. For example, «the cat» is one phrase, and «on the mat» is another, because they would be treated as single units if a decision was made to emphasize the location by moving forward the prepositional phrase: «[And] on the mat, the cat sat».[96] There are many different formalist and functionalist frameworks that propose theories for describing syntactic structures, based on different assumptions about what language is and how it should be described. Each of them would analyze a sentence such as this in a different manner.[22]

Typology and universals

Languages can be classified in relation to their grammatical types. Languages that belong to different families nonetheless often have features in common, and these shared features tend to correlate.[97] For example, languages can be classified on the basis of their basic word order, the relative order of the verb, and its constituents in a normal indicative sentence. In English, the basic order is SVO (subject–verb–object): «The snake(S) bit(V) the man(O)», whereas for example, the corresponding sentence in the Australian language Gamilaraay would be d̪uyugu n̪ama d̪ayn yiːy (snake man bit), SOV.[98] Word order type is relevant as a typological parameter, because basic word order type corresponds with other syntactic parameters, such as the relative order of nouns and adjectives, or of the use of prepositions or postpositions. Such correlations are called implicational universals.[99] For example, most (but not all) languages that are of the SOV type have postpositions rather than prepositions, and have adjectives before nouns.[100]

All languages structure sentences into Subject, Verb, and Object, but languages differ in the way they classify the relations between actors and actions. English uses the nominative-accusative word typology: in English transitive clauses, the subjects of both intransitive sentences («I run») and transitive sentences («I love you») are treated in the same way, shown here by the nominative pronoun I. Some languages, called ergative, Gamilaraay among them, distinguish instead between Agents and Patients. In ergative languages, the single participant in an intransitive sentence, such as «I run», is treated the same as the patient in a transitive sentence, giving the equivalent of «me run». Only in transitive sentences would the equivalent of the pronoun «I» be used.[98] In this way the semantic roles can map onto the grammatical relations in different ways, grouping an intransitive subject either with Agents (accusative type) or Patients (ergative type) or even making each of the three roles differently, which is called the tripartite type.[101]

The shared features of languages which belong to the same typological class type may have arisen completely independently. Their co-occurrence might be due to universal laws governing the structure of natural languages, «language universals», or they might be the result of languages evolving convergent solutions to the recurring communicative problems that humans use language to solve.[23]

Social contexts of use and transmission

Wall of Love on Montmartre in Paris: «I love you» in 250 languages, by calligraphist Fédéric Baron and artist Claire Kito (2000)

While humans have the ability to learn any language, they only do so if they grow up in an environment in which language exists and is used by others. Language is therefore dependent on communities of speakers in which children learn language from their elders and peers and themselves transmit language to their own children. Languages are used by those who speak them to communicate and to solve a plethora of social tasks. Many aspects of language use can be seen to be adapted specifically to these purposes.[23] Owing to the way in which language is transmitted between generations and within communities, language perpetually changes, diversifying into new languages or converging due to language contact. The process is similar to the process of evolution, where the process of descent with modification leads to the formation of a phylogenetic tree.[102]

However, languages differ from biological organisms in that they readily incorporate elements from other languages through the process of diffusion, as speakers of different languages come into contact. Humans also frequently speak more than one language, acquiring their first language or languages as children, or learning new languages as they grow up. Because of the increased language contact in the globalizing world, many small languages are becoming endangered as their speakers shift to other languages that afford the possibility to participate in larger and more influential speech communities.[6]

Usage and meaning

When studying the way in which words and signs are used, it is often the case that words have different meanings, depending on the social context of use. An important example of this is the process called deixis, which describes the way in which certain words refer to entities through their relation between a specific point in time and space when the word is uttered. Such words are, for example, the word, «I» (which designates the person speaking), «now» (which designates the moment of speaking), and «here» (which designates the position of speaking). Signs also change their meanings over time, as the conventions governing their usage gradually change. The study of how the meaning of linguistic expressions changes depending on context is called pragmatics. Deixis is an important part of the way that we use language to point out entities in the world.[103] Pragmatics is concerned with the ways in which language use is patterned and how these patterns contribute to meaning. For example, in all languages, linguistic expressions can be used not just to transmit information, but to perform actions. Certain actions are made only through language, but nonetheless have tangible effects, e.g. the act of «naming», which creates a new name for some entity, or the act of «pronouncing someone man and wife», which creates a social contract of marriage. These types of acts are called speech acts, although they can also be carried out through writing or hand signing.[104]

The form of linguistic expression often does not correspond to the meaning that it actually has in a social context. For example, if at a dinner table a person asks, «Can you reach the salt?», that is, in fact, not a question about the length of the arms of the one being addressed, but a request to pass the salt across the table. This meaning is implied by the context in which it is spoken; these kinds of effects of meaning are called conversational implicatures. These social rules for which ways of using language are considered appropriate in certain situations and how utterances are to be understood in relation to their context vary between communities, and learning them is a large part of acquiring communicative competence in a language.[105]

Acquisition

All healthy, normally developing human beings learn to use language. Children acquire the language or languages used around them: whichever languages they receive sufficient exposure to during childhood. The development is essentially the same for children acquiring sign or oral languages.[106] This learning process is referred to as first-language acquisition, since unlike many other kinds of learning, it requires no direct teaching or specialized study. In The Descent of Man, naturalist Charles Darwin called this process «an instinctive tendency to acquire an art».[15]

First language acquisition proceeds in a fairly regular sequence, though there is a wide degree of variation in the timing of particular stages among normally developing infants. Studies published in 2013 have indicated that unborn fetuses are capable of language acquisition to some degree.[107][108] From birth, newborns respond more readily to human speech than to other sounds. Around one month of age, babies appear to be able to distinguish between different speech sounds. Around six months of age, a child will begin babbling, producing the speech sounds or handshapes of the languages used around them. Words appear around the age of 12 to 18 months; the average vocabulary of an eighteen-month-old child is around 50 words. A child’s first utterances are holophrases (literally «whole-sentences»), utterances that use just one word to communicate some idea. Several months after a child begins producing words, he or she will produce two-word utterances, and within a few more months will begin to produce telegraphic speech, or short sentences that are less grammatically complex than adult speech, but that do show regular syntactic structure. From roughly the age of three to five years, a child’s ability to speak or sign is refined to the point that it resembles adult language.[109][110]

Acquisition of second and additional languages can come at any age, through exposure in daily life or courses. Children learning a second language are more likely to achieve native-like fluency than adults, but in general, it is very rare for someone speaking a second language to pass completely for a native speaker. An important difference between first language acquisition and additional language acquisition is that the process of additional language acquisition is influenced by languages that the learner already knows.[111]

Culture

Languages, understood as the particular set of speech norms of a particular community, are also a part of the larger culture of the community that speaks them. Languages differ not only in pronunciation, vocabulary, and grammar, but also through having different «cultures of speaking.» Humans use language as a way of signalling identity with one cultural group as well as difference from others. Even among speakers of one language, several different ways of using the language exist, and each is used to signal affiliation with particular subgroups within a larger culture. Linguists and anthropologists, particularly sociolinguists, ethnolinguists, and linguistic anthropologists have specialized in studying how ways of speaking vary between speech communities.[112]

Linguists use the term «varieties» to refer to the different ways of speaking a language. This term includes geographically or socioculturally defined dialects as well as the jargons or styles of subcultures. Linguistic anthropologists and sociologists of language define communicative style as the ways that language is used and understood within a particular culture.[113]

Because norms for language use are shared by members of a specific group, communicative style also becomes a way of displaying and constructing group identity. Linguistic differences may become salient markers of divisions between social groups, for example, speaking a language with a particular accent may imply membership of an ethnic minority or social class, one’s area of origin, or status as a second language speaker. These kinds of differences are not part of the linguistic system, but are an important part of how people use language as a social tool for constructing groups.[114]

However, many languages also have grammatical conventions that signal the social position of the speaker in relation to others through the use of registers that are related to social hierarchies or divisions. In many languages, there are stylistic or even grammatical differences between the ways men and women speak, between age groups, or between social classes, just as some languages employ different words depending on who is listening. For example, in the Australian language Dyirbal, a married man must use a special set of words to refer to everyday items when speaking in the presence of his mother-in-law.[115] Some cultures, for example, have elaborate systems of «social deixis», or systems of signalling social distance through linguistic means.[116] In English, social deixis is shown mostly through distinguishing between addressing some people by first name and others by surname, and in titles such as «Mrs.», «boy», «Doctor», or «Your Honor», but in other languages, such systems may be highly complex and codified in the entire grammar and vocabulary of the language. For instance, in languages of east Asia such as Thai, Burmese, and Javanese, different words are used according to whether a speaker is addressing someone of higher or lower rank than oneself in a ranking system with animals and children ranking the lowest and gods and members of royalty as the highest.[116]

Writing, literacy and technology

Throughout history a number of different ways of representing language in graphic media have been invented. These are called writing systems.

The use of writing has made language even more useful to humans. It makes it possible to store large amounts of information outside of the human body and retrieve it again, and it allows communication across physical distances and timespans that would otherwise be impossible. Many languages conventionally employ different genres, styles, and registers in written and spoken language, and in some communities, writing traditionally takes place in an entirely different language than the one spoken. There is some evidence that the use of writing also has effects on the cognitive development of humans, perhaps because acquiring literacy generally requires explicit and formal education.[117]

The invention of the first writing systems is roughly contemporary with the beginning of the Bronze Age in the late 4th millennium BC. The Sumerian archaic cuneiform script and the Egyptian hieroglyphs are generally considered to be the earliest writing systems, both emerging out of their ancestral proto-literate symbol systems from 3400 to 3200 BC with the earliest coherent texts from about 2600 BC. It is generally agreed that Sumerian writing was an independent invention; however, it is debated whether Egyptian writing was developed completely independently of Sumerian, or was a case of cultural diffusion. A similar debate exists for the Chinese script, which developed around 1200 BC. The pre-Columbian Mesoamerican writing systems (including among others Olmec and Maya scripts) are generally believed to have had independent origins.[80]

Change

The first page of the poem Beowulf, written in Old English in the early medieval period (800–1100 AD). Although Old English is the direct ancestor of modern English, it is unintelligible to contemporary English speakers.

All languages change as speakers adopt or invent new ways of speaking and pass them on to other members of their speech community. Language change happens at all levels from the phonological level to the levels of vocabulary, morphology, syntax, and discourse. Even though language change is often initially evaluated negatively by speakers of the language who often consider changes to be «decay» or a sign of slipping norms of language usage, it is natural and inevitable.[118]

Changes may affect specific sounds or the entire phonological system. Sound change can consist of the replacement of one speech sound or phonetic feature by another, the complete loss of the affected sound, or even the introduction of a new sound in a place where there had been none. Sound changes can be conditioned in which case a sound is changed only if it occurs in the vicinity of certain other sounds. Sound change is usually assumed to be regular, which means that it is expected to apply mechanically whenever its structural conditions are met, irrespective of any non-phonological factors. On the other hand, sound changes can sometimes be sporadic, affecting only one particular word or a few words, without any seeming regularity. Sometimes a simple change triggers a chain shift in which the entire phonological system is affected. This happened in the Germanic languages when the sound change known as Grimm’s law affected all the stop consonants in the system. The original consonant * became /b/ in the Germanic languages, the previous *b in turn became /p/, and the previous *p became /f/. The same process applied to all stop consonants and explains why Italic languages such as Latin have p in words like pater and pisces, whereas Germanic languages, like English, have father and fish.[119]

Another example is the Great Vowel Shift in English, which is the reason that the spelling of English vowels do not correspond well to their current pronunciation. This is because the vowel shift brought the already established orthography out of synchronization with pronunciation. Another source of sound change is the erosion of words as pronunciation gradually becomes increasingly indistinct and shortens words, leaving out syllables or sounds. This kind of change caused Latin mea domina to eventually become the French madame and American English ma’am.[120]

Change also happens in the grammar of languages as discourse patterns such as idioms or particular constructions become grammaticalized. This frequently happens when words or morphemes erode and the grammatical system is unconsciously rearranged to compensate for the lost element. For example, in some varieties of Caribbean Spanish the final /s/ has eroded away. Since Standard Spanish uses final /s/ in the morpheme marking the second person subject «you» in verbs, the Caribbean varieties now have to express the second person using the pronoun . This means that the sentence «what’s your name» is ¿como te llamas? [ˈkomo te ˈjamas] in Standard Spanish, but [ˈkomo ˈtu te ˈjama] in Caribbean Spanish. The simple sound change has affected both morphology and syntax.[121] Another common cause of grammatical change is the gradual petrification of idioms into new grammatical forms, for example, the way the English «going to» construction lost its aspect of movement and in some varieties of English has almost become a full-fledged future tense (e.g. I’m gonna).

Language change may be motivated by «language internal» factors, such as changes in pronunciation motivated by certain sounds being difficult to distinguish aurally or to produce, or through patterns of change that cause some rare types of constructions to drift towards more common types.[122] Other causes of language change are social, such as when certain pronunciations become emblematic of membership in certain groups, such as social classes, or with ideologies, and therefore are adopted by those who wish to identify with those groups or ideas. In this way, issues of identity and politics can have profound effects on language structure.[123]

Contact

One important source of language change is contact and resulting diffusion of linguistic traits between languages. Language contact occurs when speakers of two or more languages or varieties interact on a regular basis.[124] Multilingualism is likely to have been the norm throughout human history and most people in the modern world are multilingual. Before the rise of the concept of the ethno-national state, monolingualism was characteristic mainly of populations inhabiting small islands. But with the ideology that made one people, one state, and one language the most desirable political arrangement, monolingualism started to spread throughout the world. Nonetheless, there are only 250 countries in the world corresponding to some 6000 languages, which means that most countries are multilingual and most languages therefore exist in close contact with other languages.[125]

When speakers of different languages interact closely, it is typical for their languages to influence each other. Through sustained language contact over long periods, linguistic traits diffuse between languages, and languages belonging to different families may converge to become more similar. In areas where many languages are in close contact, this may lead to the formation of language areas in which unrelated languages share a number of linguistic features. A number of such language areas have been documented, among them, the Balkan language area, the Mesoamerican language area, and the Ethiopian language area. Also, larger areas such as South Asia, Europe, and Southeast Asia have sometimes been considered language areas, because of widespread diffusion of specific areal features.[126][127]

Language contact may also lead to a variety of other linguistic phenomena, including language convergence, borrowing, and relexification (replacement of much of the native vocabulary with that of another language). In situations of extreme and sustained language contact, it may lead to the formation of new mixed languages that cannot be considered to belong to a single language family. One type of mixed language called pidgins occurs when adult speakers of two different languages interact on a regular basis, but in a situation where neither group learns to speak the language of the other group fluently. In such a case, they will often construct a communication form that has traits of both languages, but which has a simplified grammatical and phonological structure. The language comes to contain mostly the grammatical and phonological categories that exist in both languages. Pidgin languages are defined by not having any native speakers, but only being spoken by people who have another language as their first language. But if a Pidgin language becomes the main language of a speech community, then eventually children will grow up learning the pidgin as their first language. As the generation of child learners grow up, the pidgin will often be seen to change its structure and acquire a greater degree of complexity. This type of language is generally called a creole language. An example of such mixed languages is Tok Pisin, the official language of Papua New-Guinea, which originally arose as a Pidgin based on English and Austronesian languages; others are Kreyòl ayisyen, the French-based creole language spoken in Haiti, and Michif, a mixed language of Canada, based on the Native American language Cree and French.[128]

Linguistic diversity

Language Native speakers
(millions)[129]
Mandarin 848
Spanish 329 [note 5]
English 328
Portuguese 250
Arabic 221
Hindi 182
Bengali 181
Russian 144
Japanese 122
Javanese 84.3

SIL Ethnologue defines a «living language» as «one that has at least one speaker for whom it is their first language». The exact number of known living languages varies from 6,000 to 7,000, depending on the precision of one’s definition of «language», and in particular, on how one defines the distinction between a «language» and a «dialect». As of 2016, Ethnologue cataloged 7,097 living human languages.[131] The Ethnologue establishes linguistic groups based on studies of mutual intelligibility, and therefore often includes more categories than more conservative classifications. For example, the Danish language that most scholars consider a single language with several dialects is classified as two distinct languages (Danish and Jutish) by the Ethnologue.[129]

According to the Ethnologue, 389 languages (nearly 6%) have more than a million speakers. These languages together account for 94% of the world’s population, whereas 94% of the world’s languages account for the remaining 6% of the global population.

Languages and dialects

There is no clear distinction between a language and a dialect, notwithstanding a famous aphorism attributed to linguist Max Weinreich that «a language is a dialect with an army and navy».[132] For example, national boundaries frequently override linguistic difference in determining whether two linguistic varieties are languages or dialects. Hakka, Cantonese and Mandarin are, for example, often classified as «dialects» of Chinese, even though they are more different from each other than Swedish is from Norwegian. Before the Yugoslav Wars, Serbo-Croatian was generally considered a single language with two normative variants, but due to sociopolitical reasons, Croatian and Serbian are now often treated as separate languages and employ different writing systems. In other words, the distinction may hinge on political considerations as much as on cultural differences, distinctive writing systems, or degree of mutual intelligibility.[133]

Language families of the world

The world’s languages can be grouped into language families consisting of languages that can be shown to have common ancestry. Linguists recognize many hundreds of language families, although some of them can possibly be grouped into larger units as more evidence becomes available and in-depth studies are carried out. At present, there are also dozens of language isolates: languages that cannot be shown to be related to any other languages in the world. Among them are Basque, spoken in Europe, Zuni of New Mexico, Purépecha of Mexico, Ainu of Japan, Burushaski of Pakistan, and many others.[134]

The language family of the world that has the most speakers is the Indo-European languages, spoken by 46% of the world’s population.[135] This family includes major world languages like English, Spanish, French, German, Russian, and Hindustani (Hindi/Urdu). The Indo-European family achieved prevalence first during the Eurasian Migration Period (c. 400–800 AD),[citation needed] and subsequently through the European colonial expansion, which brought the Indo-European languages to a politically and often numerically dominant position in the Americas and much of Africa. The Sino-Tibetan languages are spoken by 20%[135] of the world’s population and include many of the languages of East Asia, including Hakka, Mandarin Chinese, Cantonese, and hundreds of smaller languages.[136]

Africa is home to a large number of language families, the largest of which is the Niger-Congo language family, which includes such languages as Swahili, Shona, and Yoruba. Speakers of the Niger-Congo languages account for 6.9% of the world’s population.[135] A similar number of people speak the Afroasiatic languages, which include the populous Semitic languages such as Arabic, Hebrew language, and the languages of the Sahara region, such as the Berber languages and Hausa.[136]

The Austronesian languages are spoken by 5.5% of the world’s population and stretch from Madagascar to maritime Southeast Asia all the way to Oceania.[135] It includes such languages as Malagasy, Māori, Samoan, and many of the indigenous languages of Indonesia and Taiwan. The Austronesian languages are considered to have originated in Taiwan around 3000 BC and spread through the Oceanic region through island-hopping, based on an advanced nautical technology. Other populous language families are the Dravidian languages of South Asia (among them Kannada, Tamil, and Telugu), the Turkic languages of Central Asia (such as Turkish), the Austroasiatic (among them Khmer), and Tai–Kadai languages of Southeast Asia (including Thai).[136]

The areas of the world in which there is the greatest linguistic diversity, such as the Americas, Papua New Guinea, West Africa, and South-Asia, contain hundreds of small language families. These areas together account for the majority of the world’s languages, though not the majority of speakers. In the Americas, some of the largest language families include the Quechumaran, Arawak, and Tupi-Guarani families of South America, the Uto-Aztecan, Oto-Manguean, and Mayan of Mesoamerica, and the Na-Dene, Iroquoian, and Algonquian language families of North America. In Australia, most indigenous languages belong to the Pama-Nyungan family, whereas New Guinea is home to a large number of small families and isolates, as well as a number of Austronesian languages.[134] Due to its remoteness and geographical fragmentation, Papua New Guinea emerges in fact as the leading location worldwide for both species (8% of world total) and linguistic richness — with 830 living tongues (12% of world total).[137]

Language endangerment

  Together, these eight countries contain more than 50% of the world’s languages.

  These areas are the most linguistically diverse in the world, and the locations of most of the world’s endangered languages.

Language endangerment occurs when a language is at risk of falling out of use as its speakers die out or shift to speaking another language. Language loss occurs when the language has no more native speakers, and becomes a dead language. If eventually no one speaks the language at all, it becomes an extinct language. While languages have always gone extinct throughout human history, they have been disappearing at an accelerated rate in the 20th and 21st centuries due to the processes of globalization and neo-colonialism, where the economically powerful languages dominate other languages.[6]

The more commonly spoken languages dominate the less commonly spoken languages, so the less commonly spoken languages eventually disappear from populations. Of the between 6,000[5] and 7,000 languages spoken as of 2010, between 50 and 90% of those are expected to have become extinct by the year 2100.[6] The top 20 languages, those spoken by more than 50 million speakers each, are spoken by 50% of the world’s population, whereas many of the other languages are spoken by small communities, most of them with less than 10,000 speakers.[6]

UNESCO’s five levels of language endangerment

The United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO) operates with five levels of language endangerment: «safe», «vulnerable» (not spoken by children outside the home), «definitely endangered» (not spoken by children), «severely endangered» (only spoken by the oldest generations), and «critically endangered» (spoken by few members of the oldest generation, often semi-speakers). Notwithstanding claims that the world would be better off if most adopted a single common lingua franca, such as English or Esperanto, there is a consensus that the loss of languages harms the cultural diversity of the world. It is a common belief, going back to the biblical narrative of the tower of Babel in the Old Testament, that linguistic diversity causes political conflict,[34] but this is contradicted by the fact that many of the world’s major episodes of violence have taken place in situations with low linguistic diversity, such as the Yugoslav and American Civil War, or the genocide of Rwanda, whereas many of the most stable political units have been highly multilingual.[138]

Many projects aim to prevent or slow this loss by revitalizing endangered languages and promoting education and literacy in minority languages. Across the world, many countries have enacted specific legislation to protect and stabilize the language of indigenous speech communities. A minority of linguists have argued that language loss is a natural process that should not be counteracted, and that documenting endangered languages for posterity is sufficient.[139]

The University of Waikato are using the Welsh language as a model for their Māori language revitalisation programme as they deem Welsh to be the world’s leading example for the survival of languages.[140][141] In 2019 a Hawaiian TV company Oiwi visited a Welsh language centre in Nant Gwrtheyrn, North Wales to help find ways of preserving their Ōlelo Hawaiʻi language.[142]

See also

  • Father Tongue hypothesis
  • Human communication
    • Attitude (psychology)
    • Body language (approachable)
    • Humor
    • Listening
    • Reading
    • Speaking
    • Social skills
  • International auxiliary language
  • List of language regulators
  • Lists of languages
  • List of official languages
  • Outline of linguistics
  • Problem of religious language
  • Psycholinguistics
  • Speech–language pathology

Notes

  1. ^ The gorilla Koko reportedly used as many as 1000 words in American Sign Language, and understands 2000 words of spoken English. There are some doubts about whether her use of signs is based on complex understanding or simple conditioning.[31]
  2. ^ «Functional grammar analyzes grammatical structure, as do formal and structural grammar; but it also analyzes the entire communicative situation: the purpose of the speech event, its participants, its discourse context. Functionalists maintain that the communicative situation motivates, constrains, explains, or otherwise determines grammatical structure, and that a structural or formal approach is not merely limited to an artificially restricted data base, but is inadequate even as a structural account. Functional grammar, then, differs from formal and structural grammar in that it purports not to model but to explain; and the explanation is grounded in the communicative situation».[53]
  3. ^ While sign is usually a visual medium, there is also tactile signing; and while oral speech is usually an aural medium, there is also lipreading and tadoma.
  4. ^ The prefixed asterisk * conventionally indicates that the sentence is ungrammatical, i.e. syntactically incorrect.[92]
  5. ^ Ethnologue’s figure is based on numbers from before 1995. A more recent figure is 420 million.[130]

References

  1. ^ a b Nicholas Evans & Stephen Levinson (2009) ‘The Myth of Language Universals: Language Diversity and Its Importance for Cognitive Science’. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32, 429–492.
  2. ^ Kamusella, Tomasz (2016). «The History of the Normative Opposition of ‘Language versus Dialect’: From Its Graeco-Latin Origin to Central Europe’s Ethnolinguistic Nation-States». Colloquia Humanistica. 5 (5): 189–198. doi:10.11649/ch.2016.011. Archived from the original on 26 February 2020. Retrieved 9 February 2020.
  3. ^ Tomasello (1996)
  4. ^ a b Hauser, Chomsky & Fitch (2002)
  5. ^ a b Moseley (2010): «Statistics Archived 12 August 2014 at the Wayback Machine»
  6. ^ a b c d e Austin & Sallabank (2011)
  7. ^ Graddol, David (27 February 2004). «The Future of Language». Science. 303 (5662): 1329–1331. Bibcode:2004Sci…303.1329G. doi:10.1126/science.1096546. ISSN 0036-8075. PMID 14988552. S2CID 35904484. Archived from the original on 31 March 2021. Retrieved 15 September 2020.
  8. ^ «language». The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language (3rd ed.). Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company. 1992.
  9. ^ Lyons (1981:2)
  10. ^ Lyons (1981:1–8)
  11. ^ Trask (2007:129–31)
  12. ^ Bett 2010.
  13. ^ Devitt & Sterelny 1999.
  14. ^ Hauser & Fitch (2003)
  15. ^ a b c Pinker (1994)
  16. ^ Trask 2007, p. 93.
  17. ^ a b c Saussure (1983)
  18. ^ Campbell (2001:96)
  19. ^ Trask 2007, p. 130.
  20. ^ Chomsky (1957)
  21. ^ Trask (2007:93, 130)
  22. ^ a b c d Newmeyer (1998:3–6)
  23. ^ a b c Evans & Levinson (2009)
  24. ^ Van Valin (2001)
  25. ^ Nerlich 2010, p. 192.
  26. ^ Hockett, Charles F. (1966). «The Problem of Universals in Language». Archived from the original on 10 November 2012. Retrieved 11 May 2013.
  27. ^ Hockett (1960); Deacon (1997)
  28. ^ a b Trask (1999:1–5)
  29. ^ Engesser, Sabrina; Crane, Jodie M. S.; Savage, James L.; Russel, Andrew F.; Townsend, Simon W. (29 June 2015). «Experimental Evidence for Phonemic Contrasts in a Nonhuman Vocal System». PLOS Biology. 13 (6): e1002171. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.1002171. PMC 4488142. PMID 26121619.
  30. ^ Engesser, Sabrina; Ridley, Amanda R.; Townsend, Simon W. (20 July 2017). «Element repetition rates encode functionally distinct information in pied babbler ‘clucks’ and ‘purrs’» (PDF). Animal Cognition. 20 (5): 953–60. doi:10.1007/s10071-017-1114-6. PMID 28730513. S2CID 21470061. Archived (PDF) from the original on 28 April 2019. Retrieved 9 November 2018.
  31. ^ Candland (1993)
  32. ^ a b Deacon (1997)
  33. ^ Trask (2007:165–66)
  34. ^ a b Haugen (1973)
  35. ^ Shanahan, D. (2011). Language, feeling, and the brain: The evocative vector. Transaction Publishers.
  36. ^ a b Ulbaek (1998)
  37. ^ Tomasello (2008)
  38. ^ Fitch 2010, pp. 466–507.
  39. ^ Anderson (2012:107)
  40. ^ Anderson (2012:104)
  41. ^ Fitch 2010, pp. 250–92.
  42. ^ Clark, Gary; Henneberg, Maciej (2017). «Ardipithecus ramidus and the evolution of language and singing: An early origin for hominin vocal capability». HOMO. 68 (2): 101–21. doi:10.1016/j.jchb.2017.03.001. PMID 28363458.
  43. ^ Foley 1997, pp. 70–74.
  44. ^ Fitch 2010, pp. 292–93.
  45. ^ Chomsky 1972, p. 86.
  46. ^ a b Chomsky 2000, p. 4.
  47. ^ Newmeyer (2005)
  48. ^ Trask (2007)
  49. ^ Campbell (2001:82–83)
  50. ^ Bloomfield 1914, p. 310
  51. ^ Clarke (1990:143–44)
  52. ^ Foley (1997:82–83)
  53. ^ Nichols (1984)
  54. ^ Croft & Cruse (2004:1–4)
  55. ^ Trask (1999:11–14, 105–13)
  56. ^ Fisher, Lai & Monaco (2003)
  57. ^ a b Lesser (1989:205–06)
  58. ^ Trask (1999:105–07)
  59. ^ Trask (1999:108)
  60. ^ Sandler & Lillo-Martin (2001:554)
  61. ^ MacMahon (1989:2)
  62. ^ a b c d MacMahon (1989:3)
  63. ^ a b International Phonetic Association (1999:3–8)
  64. ^ MacMahon (1989:11–15)
  65. ^ MacMahon (1989:6–11)
  66. ^ Ladefoged & Maddieson (1996)
  67. ^ Nicholas Evans (2017) Listening Here: Ngûrrahmalkwonawoniyan. Humanities Australia, Journal of the Australian Academy of the Humanities, vol 8, p 39.
  68. ^ a b Lyons (1981:17–24)
  69. ^ Trask (1999:35)
  70. ^ Lyons (1981:218–24)
  71. ^ a b Levinson (1983)
  72. ^ Goldsmith (1995)
  73. ^ International Phonetic Association (1999:27)
  74. ^ a b Trask (2007:214)
  75. ^ International Phonetic Association (1999:4)
  76. ^ Stokoe, William C. (1960). Sign Language Structure: An Outline of the Visual Communication Systems of the American Deaf, Studies in linguistics: Occasional papers (No. 8). Buffalo: Dept. of Anthropology and Linguistics, University of Buffalo.
  77. ^ Stokoe, William C.; Dorothy C. Casterline; Carl G. Croneberg (1965). A dictionary of American sign languages on linguistic principles. Washington, D.C.: Gallaudet College Press
  78. ^ Sandler & Lillo-Martin (2001:539–40)
  79. ^ Trask (2007:326)
  80. ^ a b Coulmas (2002)
  81. ^ Trask (2007:123)
  82. ^ Lyons (1981:103)
  83. ^ Allerton (1989)
  84. ^ Payne (1997)
  85. ^ Trask (2007:208)
  86. ^ Trask (2007:305)
  87. ^ Senft (2008)
  88. ^ Aronoff & Fudeman (2011:1–2)
  89. ^ Bauer (2003); Haspelmath (2002)
  90. ^ Payne (1997:28–29)
  91. ^ Trask (2007:11)
  92. ^ Denham, Kristin; Lobeck, Anne (6 March 2009). Linguistics for Everyone: An Introduction. Cengage Learning. p. 9. ISBN 978-1-4130-1589-8. Archived from the original on 22 May 2020. Retrieved 16 April 2020. An ungrammatical sentence is one that is impossible in a given language, one that a native speaker of that variety would never utter naturally. (Remember that ungrammatical sentences are marked with an asterisk, *.
  93. ^ Baker (2001:265)
  94. ^ Trask (2007:179)
  95. ^ Baker 2001, pp. 269–70.
  96. ^ a b Trask (2007:218–19)
  97. ^ Nichols (1992);Comrie (1989)
  98. ^ a b Croft (2001:340)
  99. ^ Greenberg (1966)
  100. ^ Comrie (2009:45); McMahon (1994:156)
  101. ^ Croft (2001:355)
  102. ^ Campbell (2004)
  103. ^ Levinson (1983:54–96)
  104. ^ Levinson (1983:226–78)
  105. ^ Levinson (1983:100–69)
  106. ^ Bonvillian, John D.; Michael D. Orlansky; Leslie Lazin Novack (December 1983). «Developmental milestones: Sign language acquisition and motor development». Child Development. 54 (6): 1435–45. doi:10.2307/1129806. JSTOR 1129806. PMID 6661942.
  107. ^ Scientific American (2015:24)
  108. ^ «Babies Learn to Recognize Words in the Womb». www.science.org. Retrieved 3 February 2023.
  109. ^ O’Grady, William; Cho, Sook Whan (2001). «First language acquisition». Contemporary Linguistics: An Introduction (fourth ed.). Boston: Bedford St. Martin’s.
  110. ^ Kennison (2013)
  111. ^ Macaro (2010:137–57)
  112. ^ Duranti (2003)
  113. ^ Foley (1997)
  114. ^ Agha (2006)
  115. ^ Dixon (1972:32–34)
  116. ^ a b Foley (1997:311–28)
  117. ^ Olson (1996)
  118. ^ Aitchison (2001); Trask (1999:70)
  119. ^ Clackson (2007:27–33)
  120. ^ Aitchison (2001:112)
  121. ^ Zentella (2002:178)
  122. ^ Labov (1994)
  123. ^ Labov (2001)
  124. ^ Thomason (2001:1)
  125. ^ Romaine (2001:513)
  126. ^ Campbell (2002)
  127. ^ Aikhenvald (2001)
  128. ^ Thomason & Kaufman (1988); Thomason (2001); Matras & Bakker (2003)
  129. ^ a b Lewis (2009)
  130. ^ «Primer estudio conjunto del Instituto Cervantes y el British Council sobre el peso internacional del español y del inglés». Instituto Cervantes (www.cervantes.es). Archived from the original on 16 September 2017. Retrieved 17 September 2012.
  131. ^ «Ethnologue statistics». Summary by world area | Ethnologue. SIL. Archived from the original on 8 January 2016. Retrieved 11 September 2014.
  132. ^ Rickerson, E.M. «What’s the difference between dialect and language?». The Five Minute Linguist. College of Charleston. Archived from the original on 19 December 2010. Retrieved 17 July 2011.
  133. ^ Lyons (1981:26)
  134. ^ a b Katzner (1999)
  135. ^ a b c d Lewis (2009), «Summary by language family Archived 1 January 2016 at the Wayback Machine»
  136. ^ a b c Comrie (2009); Brown & Ogilvie (2008)
  137. ^ Briand, Frederic (February 2013). «Silent Plains … the Fading Sounds of Native Languages». National Geographic.
  138. ^ Austin & Sallabank (2011:10–11)
  139. ^ Ladefoged (1992)
  140. ^ «University of Waikato Launches a Strategic Partnership with Cardiff University in Wales» (Press release). University of Waikato. 10 November 2021. Archived from the original on 24 November 2021. Retrieved 21 December 2021 – via Scoop News.
  141. ^ Rhiannon James (10 November 2021). «Council investing £6.4m in the future of the Welsh language». Nation Cymru. Archived from the original on 11 November 2021. Retrieved 21 December 2021.
  142. ^ «Hawaiian TV company seeks help to promote language». Cambrian News. 20 August 2019. Archived from the original on 5 December 2021. Retrieved 21 August 2021.

Works cited

  • Agha, Asif (2006). Language and Social Relations. Cambridge University Press.
  • Aikhenvald, Alexandra (2001). «Introduction». In Alexandra Y. Aikhenvald; R.M.W. Dixon (eds.). Areal diffusion and genetic inheritance: problems in comparative linguistics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 1–26.
  • Aitchison, Jean (2001). Language Change: Progress or Decay? (3rd (1st edition 1981) ed.). Cambridge, New York, Melbourne: Cambridge University Press.
  • Allerton, D.J. (1989). «Language as Form and Pattern: Grammar and its Categories». In Collinge, N.E. (ed.). An Encyclopedia of Language. London:NewYork: Routledge.
  • Anderson, Stephen (2012). Languages: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-959059-9.
  • Aronoff, Mark; Fudeman, Kirsten (2011). What is Morphology. John Wiley & Sons.
  • Austin, Peter K; Sallabank, Julia (2011). «Introduction». In Austin, Peter K; Sallabank, Julia (eds.). Cambridge Handbook of Endangered Languages. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-88215-6.
  • Baker, Mark C. (2001). «Syntax». In Mark Aronoff; Janie Rees-Miller (eds.). The Handbook of Linguistics. Blackwell. pp. 265–95.
  • Bauer, Laurie (2003). Introducing linguistic morphology (2nd ed.). Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press. ISBN 978-0-87840-343-1.
  • Bett, R. (2010). «Plato and his Predecessors». In Alex Barber; Robert J Stainton (eds.). Concise Encyclopedia of Philosophy of Language and Linguistics. Elsevier. pp. 569–70.
  • Bloomfield, Leonard (1914). An introduction to the study of language. New York: Henry Holt and Company.
  • Brown, Keith; Ogilvie, Sarah, eds. (2008). Concise Encyclopedia of Languages of the World. Elsevier Science. ISBN 978-0-08-087774-7.
  • Clackson, James (2007). Indo-European Linguistics: An Introduction. Cambridge University press.
  • Campbell, Lyle (2002). «Areal linguistics». In Bernard Comrie, Neil J. Smelser and Paul B. Balte (ed.). International Encyclopedia of Social and Behavioral Sciences. Oxford: Pergamon. pp. 729–33.
  • Campbell, Lyle (2004). Historical Linguistics: an Introduction (2nd ed.). Edinburgh and Cambridge, MA: Edinburgh University Press and MIT Press.
  • Campbell, Lyle (2001). «The History of Linguistics». In Mark Aronoff; Janie Rees-Miller (eds.). The Handbook of Linguistics. Blackwell. pp. 81–105.
  • Candland, Douglas Keith (1993). Feral Children and Clever Animals: Reflections on Human Nature. Oxford University Press US. pp. 293–301. ISBN 978-0-19-510284-0. koko gorilla operant conditioning.
  • Chomsky, Noam (1957). Syntactic Structures. The Hague: Mouton.
  • Chomsky, Noam (1972). Language and Mind. Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. ISBN 978-0-15-549257-8.
  • Chomsky, Noam (2000). The Architecture of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Clarke, David S. (1990). Sources of semiotic: readings with commentary from antiquity to the present. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.
  • Comrie, Bernard (1989). Language universals and linguistic typology: Syntax and morphology (2nd ed.). Oxford: Blackwell. ISBN 978-0-226-11433-0.
  • Comrie, Bernard, ed. (2009). The World’s Major Languages. New York: Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-35339-7.
  • Coulmas, Florian (2002). Writing Systems: An Introduction to Their Linguistic Analysis. Cambridge University Press.
  • Croft, William; Cruse, D. Alan (2004). Cognitive Linguistics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Croft, William (2001). «Typology». In Mark Aronoff; Janie Rees-Miller (eds.). The Handbook of Linguistics. Blackwell. pp. 81–105.
  • Deacon, Terrence (1997). The Symbolic Species: The Co-evolution of Language and the Brain. New York: W.W. Norton & Company. ISBN 978-0-393-31754-1.
  • Devitt, Michael; Sterelny, Kim (1999). Language and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Language. Boston: MIT Press.
  • Dixon, Robert M.W. (1972). The Dyirbal Language of North Queensland. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-08510-6.
  • Duranti, Alessandro (2003). «Language as Culture in U.S. Anthropology: Three Paradigms». Current Anthropology. 44 (3): 323–48. doi:10.1086/368118. S2CID 148075449.
  • Evans, Nicholas; Levinson, Stephen C. (2009). «The myth of language universals: Language diversity and its importance for cognitive science». Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 32 (5): 429–92. doi:10.1017/s0140525x0999094x. PMID 19857320.
  • «First Impressions: We start to pick up words, food preferences and hand-eye coordination long before being born». Scientific American. Vol. 313, no. 1. July 2015. p. 24.
  • Fisher, Simon E.; Lai, Cecilia S.L.; Monaco, Anthony P. (2003). «Deciphering the Genetic Basis of Speech and Language Disorders». Annual Review of Neuroscience. 26: 57–80. doi:10.1146/annurev.neuro.26.041002.131144. hdl:11858/00-001M-0000-0012-CB7D-6. PMID 12524432.
  • Fitch, W. Tecumseh (2010). The Evolution of Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Foley, William A. (1997). Anthropological Linguistics: An Introduction. Blackwell.
  • Goldsmith, John A (1995). «Phonological Theory». In John A. Goldsmith (ed.). The Handbook of Phonological Theory. Blackwell Handbooks in Linguistics. Blackwell Publishers. ISBN 978-1-4051-5768-1.
  • Greenberg, Joseph (1966). Language Universals: With Special Reference to Feature Hierarchies. The Hague: Mouton & Co.
  • Haspelmath, Martin (2002). Understanding morphology. London: Arnold, Oxford University Press. (pbk)
  • Haugen, Einar (1973). «The Curse of Babel». Daedalus. 102 (3, Language as a Human Problem): 47–57.
  • Hauser, Marc D.; Chomsky, Noam; Fitch, W. Tecumseh (2002). «The Faculty of Language: What Is It, Who Has It, and How Did It Evolve?». Science. 298 (5598): 1569–79. doi:10.1126/science.298.5598.1569. PMID 12446899.
  • Hauser, Marc D.; Fitch, W. Tecumseh (2003). «What are the uniquely human components of the language faculty?» (PDF). In M.H. Christiansen; S. Kirby (eds.). Language Evolution: The States of the Art. Oxford University Press. Archived from the original (PDF) on 8 August 2014.
  • Hockett, Charles F. (1960). «Logical considerations in the study of animal communication». In W. E. Lanyon; W. N. Tavolga (eds.). Animals sounds and animal communication. pp. 392–430.
  • International Phonetic Association (1999). Handbook of the International Phonetic Association: A guide to the use of the International Phonetic Alphabet. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-65236-0.
  • Katzner, Kenneth (1999). The Languages of the World. New York: Routledge.
  • Kennison, Shelia (2013). Introduction to Language Development. SAGE.
  • Labov, William (1994). Principles of Linguistic Change vol.I Internal Factors. Blackwell.
  • Labov, William (2001). Principles of Linguistic Change vol.II Social Factors. Blackwell.
  • Ladefoged, Peter (1992). «Another view of endangered languages». Language. 68 (4): 809–11. doi:10.1353/lan.1992.0013. S2CID 144984900.
  • Ladefoged, Peter; Maddieson, Ian (1996). The sounds of the world’s languages. Oxford: Blackwell. pp. 329–30. ISBN 978-0-631-19815-4.
  • Lesser, Ruth (1989). «Language in the Brain: Neurolinguistics». In Collinge, N.E. (ed.). An Encyclopedia of Language. London:NewYork: Routledge.
  • Levinson, Stephen C. (1983). Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Lewis, M. Paul, ed. (2009). «Ethnologue: Languages of the World, Sixteenth edition». Dallas, Tex.: SIL International. Archived from the original on 4 April 2012. Retrieved 25 August 2012.
  • Lyons, John (1981). Language and Linguistics. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-29775-2.
  • Macaro, Ernesto, ed. (2010). Continuum companion to second language acquisition. London: Continuum. pp. 137–57. ISBN 978-1-4411-9922-5.
  • McMahon, April M.S. (1994). Understanding Language Change. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-44119-3.
  • MacMahon, M.K.C. (1989). «Language as available sound:Phonetics». In Collinge, N.E. (ed.). An Encyclopedia of Language. London:NewYork: Routledge.
  • Matras, Yaron; Bakker, Peter, eds. (2003). The Mixed Language Debate: Theoretical and Empirical Advances. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-017776-3.
  • Moseley, Christopher, ed. (2010). Atlas of the World’s Languages in Danger, 3rd edition. Paris: UNESCO Publishing. Archived from the original on 20 August 2014. Retrieved 7 August 2012.
  • Nerlich, Brigitte (2010). «History of pragmatics». In Cummings, Louise (ed.). The Pragmatics Encyclopedia. London/New York: Routledge. pp. 192–93.
  • Newmeyer, Frederick J. (2005). The History of Linguistics. Linguistic Society of America. ISBN 978-0-415-11553-7. Archived from the original on 31 December 2014. Retrieved 18 September 2014.
  • Newmeyer, Frederick J. (1998). Language Form and Language Function (PDF). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Archived from the original (PDF) on 16 December 2011. Retrieved 29 August 2012.
  • Nichols, Johanna (1992). Linguistic diversity in space and time. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-58057-9.
  • Nichols, Johanna (1984). «Functional Theories of Grammar». Annual Review of Anthropology. 13: 97–117. doi:10.1146/annurev.an.13.100184.000525.
  • Olson, David R. (1996). «Language and Literacy: what writing does to Language and Mind». Annual Review of Applied Linguistics. 16: 3–13. doi:10.1017/S0267190500001392. S2CID 145677801.
  • Payne, Thomas Edward (1997). Describing morphosyntax: a guide for field linguists. Cambridge University Press. pp. 238–41. ISBN 978-0-521-58805-8. Archived from the original on 31 March 2021. Retrieved 14 November 2020.
  • Pinker, Steven (1994). The Language Instinct: How the Mind Creates Language. Perennial.
  • Romaine, Suzanne (2001). «Multilingualism». In Mark Aronoff; Janie Rees-Miller (eds.). The Handbook of Linguistics. Blackwell. pp. 512–33.
  • Sandler, Wendy; Lillo-Martin, Diane (2001). «Natural Sign Languages». In Mark Aronoff; Janie Rees-Miller (eds.). The Handbook of Linguistics. Blackwell. pp. 533–63.
  • Saussure, Ferdinand de (1983) [1913]. Bally, Charles; Sechehaye, Albert (eds.). Course in General Linguistics. Translated by Roy Harris. La Salle, Illinois: Open Court. ISBN 978-0-8126-9023-1.
  • Senft, Gunter, ed. (2008). Systems of Nominal Classification. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-06523-8.
  • Tomasello, Michael (1996). «The Cultural Roots of Language». In B. Velichkovsky and D. Rumbaugh (ed.). Communicating Meaning: The Evolution and Development of Language. Psychology Press. pp. 275–308. ISBN 978-0-8058-2118-5.
  • Tomasello, Michael (2008). Origin of Human Communication. MIT Press.
  • Thomason, Sarah G.; Kaufman, Terrence (1988). Language Contact, Creolization and Genetic Linguistics. University of California Press.
  • Thomason, Sarah G. (2001). Language Contact – An Introduction. Edinburgh University Press.
  • Trask, Robert Lawrence (1999). Language: The Basics (2nd ed.). Psychology Press.
  • Trask, Robert Lawrence (2007). Stockwell, Peter (ed.). Language and Linguistics: The Key Concepts (2nd ed.). Routledge.
  • Ulbaek, Ib (1998). «The Origin of Language and Cognition». In J. R. Hurford & C. Knight (ed.). Approaches to the evolution of language. Cambridge University Press. pp. 30–43.
  • Van Valin, jr, Robert D. (2001). «Functional Linguistics». In Mark Aronoff; Janie Rees-Miller (eds.). The Handbook of Linguistics. Blackwell. pp. 319–37.
  • Zentella, Ana Celia (2002). «Spanish in New York». In García, Ofelia; Fishman, Joshua (eds.). The Multilingual Apple: Languages in New York City. Walter de Gruyter.

Further reading

  • Crystal, David (1997). The Cambridge Encyclopedia of Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Cysouw, Michael; Good, Jeff (2013). «Languoid, doculect and glossonym: Formalizing the notion ‘language’«. Language Documentation and Conservation. 7: 331–59. hdl:10125/4606.
  • Swadesh, Morris (1934). «The phonemic principle». Language. 10 (2): 117–29. doi:10.2307/409603. JSTOR 409603.

External links

Spoken Wikipedia icon

This audio file was created from a revision of this article dated 19 July 2005, and does not reflect subsequent edits.

  • World Atlas of Language Structures: a large database of structural (phonological, grammatical, lexical) properties of languages
  • Ethnologue: Languages of the World is a comprehensive catalog of all of the world’s known living languages

“In the beginning was the Word,” reads the Gospel of John 1:1. But what was this word? And where was it spoken? And how did humans come to speak it? Indeed, the origin of language is one of the greatest mysteries in human science, if not the greatest. 

Scholars and scientists have been arguing for centuries about the origins of language and all the questions that tie into this. The Linguistic Society of Paris – an organisation dedicated to the study of languages – actually banned any debate on the issue in 1886 and did not retract it for several years. But why is it such a topic of debate?

Perhaps it’s because language is such a unique and complex skill. It is something that only humans are able to do. Over the years there have been numerous attempts to teach apes to speak, and in particular chimpanzees – which are human’s closest living relative. However, no other animal has the vocal pathology necessary to speak the way we do. Even attempting to teach chimps sign language has proven fruitless, with no animal demonstrating skill above the level of a two-year-old human. It seems the three things a creature needs to speak like a human is a human’s brain, a human’s vocal cords and a human’s intelligence.

Numerous attempts have been made to teach chimpanzees to speak
Numerous attempts have been made to teach chimpanzees to speak

Continuity or Discontinuity

Prior to the Linguistic Society of Paris’ ban on discussing it, the theories of how human language evolved were humorous to say the least. However, modern theories sit in one of two camps; Continuity or Discontinuity. Continuity theories of language evolution hold that it must have developed gradually, starting among the earliest ancestors of humans, with different features developing at different stages until people’s speech resembled what we have today. Meanwhile, Discontinuity Theory suggests that because there is nothing even remotely similar to compare human language to, and it is likely to have appeared suddenly within human history. This may have been as a result of a genetic mutation within one individual, which was passed on through their ancestors and eventually became a dominant ability.

Before we explore these theories in more detail, let’s look at some of the earliest ideas in the study of language origin.

No other animals on earth can communicate like humans do

From Bow-wow to Ta-ta

The early theories of the origin of language all focus on where the first words came from that developed into the rich vocabularies spoken today. They are certainly imaginative – and all have whimsical names to match. Max Müller, a philologist and linguist, published a list of these theories in the mid-19th century:

  • Bow-wow
  • Ding-Dong
  • Pooh-pooh
  • Yo-he-ho

Bow-wow was the theory that, much like the lyrebird, humans started out mimicking the noises and animal calls around them. From these noises, words developed. The Ding-dong theory is based on the idea of sound symbolism, and that small or sharp objects are named with words with high front vowels, compared to large or circular objects that have a round vowel at the end of the word. Pooh-pooh holds that the first words evolved from the natural verbal interjections humans make, such as exclaiming when surprised or yelping in pain. If Ye-he-ho makes you think of the Seven Dwarfs working in the gem mine, you’re not far off; it’s the theory that language started with the rhythmic noises made when doing manual labour, which allow muscle effort to synchronise.

Another early theory, albeit one not to appear on Müller’s list, was Ta-ta. This was the idea that primitive people used their tongues to mimic hand gestures and the words came from there. So, a person might wave their hand up and down to say good-bye and making the same movement with the tongue results in a “ta-ta” sound.

These are all fun theories, but each of them has been almost entirely discounted by today’s linguists and anthropologists.

In the beginning was the Word - Genesis
“In the beginning was the Word”

In the beginning was the Word

Of course, the other earliest theory of language evolution is that it is a God-given ability. Genesis states that Adam and Eve, the first man and woman, were immediately able to understand what God said to them and could communicate with each other in this same language. According to Christianity, all of mankind spoke this one same language for generations more until the rebellion of Babel.

According to the Book of Genesis, as the waters of the Great Flood receded, humankind came together in Shinar. Here, they took advantage of the fact they all spoke one language by banding together to build a huge tower that would let them reach God in heaven. Seeing this, He confounded their speech by giving them different languages and then scattered them across the Earth. As a result, they were unable to work together to complete the tower.

As a nod to the story of the Tower of Babel, Douglas Adams’ The Hitchhiker’s Guide to the Galaxy includes a creature called the Babel fish. The yellow leech-like animal is able to act as a universal translator to enable creatures to communicate with one another.

No animal can speak, nor will they ever be able to

If we could talk to the animals

What makes human speech even more miraculous is the fact that no other creature in history – that we know of – has evolved the skill. Not only do chimpanzees – our closest relatives – not speak now, but they may never speak as their vocal anatomy is so different to our own it would not facilitate human-like speech.

It’s not only our physical makeup that means we can talk and apes can’t but also our intelligence. In the 1960s, Project Washoe attempted to prove whether a chimpanzee could learn language. Washoe was a female common chimpanzee who was raised in a human family and taught American Sign Language. Not only did she learn 350 words, but she also taught some of it to her adopted son Loulis. A later experiment, Project Nim, attempted to go even further by getting more secure results proving that apes had linguistic abilities. Nim was named Nim Chimpsky in honour of Noam Chomsky, who conversely believes that only humans have the ability to develop speech. Ultimately, Project Nim ended up being less regimented than Project Washoe and the man leading it, Herbert S Terrace, abandoned it. He concluded that chimpanzees’ use of language was pragmatic and that they never developed the ability to use the signs syntactically.

Terrace not only abandoned his own research but also discredited other ape language studies, including Washoe. He said that the apes were using the signs to prompt the outcome they wanted and that a certain degree of mimicking was also occurring. He cited the case of Clever Hans; where large crowds would gather to watch a horse apparently correctly answer mathematical questions. It later transpired the horse was able to pick up and react to facial cues and body language his owner did not even realise he was making. If Terrace is right, it suggests apes and other animals do not have the brain function necessary to learn speech.

Did a genetic mutation allow our ancestors to learn language?
Did a genetic mutation allow our ancestors to learn language?

Is it all in the genes?

Noam Chomsky is among the world’s leading linguists and acknowledges that his field of expertise is home to some seemingly unsolvable mysteries; namely, where language came from and how. His theory is that a possible genetic mutation in one of our human ancestors gave them the ability to speak and understand language, which was passed on to their offspring. Because of the usefulness of this ability, Darwinist evolution meant that it became a dominant feature throughout humanity.

A UCLA/Emory study published in the journal Nature in 2009 seems to back up the theory. It revealed FOXP2, the gene essential to the development of language and speech, differs significantly depending on whether it is human or chimpanzee. Not only might this explain why the mutation of this gene results in language being disrupted, but also how we can talk and animals can’t. Dr Daniel Geschwind of the David Geffen School of Medicine at UCLA said: “Earlier research suggests that the amino-acid composition of human FOXP2 changed rapidly around the same time that language emerged in modern humans.” The scientists discovered that the gene functioned and looked different in humans and chimps, and this difference meant a human brain was wired for language and a chimp’s was not. Could it be that an early mutation of this single gene is what ultimately separates us from all other life on Earth?

Another theory put forward by anthropologist Robin Dunbar is that as the human communities grew larger, people needed to find a more efficient form of grooming in order to keep their peers on their side. As a result, a type of vocal grooming developed – and it is likely these very early conversations would have been similar to the gossip we still indulge in today.

Of course, Chomsky’s theory is not the only possible answer to how language evolved. Many more experts follow the Continuity Theory that it evolved among human ancestors from pre-linguistic sounds. There are so many ideas within this field we don’t have time to list them all, but among them is the ‘putting the baby down’ hypothesis. Anthropologist Dean Falk suggests that as early humans lost their fur, it became more difficult for mothers to carry their babies on their backs as they gathered food and foraged. To reassure the baby she had not abandoned them, the mother would call to it and use facial expressions, body language and tactile communication like tickling. From this, Falk theorises language evolved.

So what’s the answer?

Unfortunately, it seems the answer to the question of where and how human language evolved is that we may never have an answer. However, it remains a problem we will never get tired of trying to resolve.

This article is about the origin of natural languages. For the origin of programming languages, see History of programming languages.

The origin of language (spoken and signed, as well as language-related technological systems such as writing), its relationship with human evolution, and its consequences have been subjects of study for centuries. Scholars wishing to study the origins of language must draw inferences from evidence such as the fossil record, archaeological evidence, contemporary language diversity, studies of language acquisition, and comparisons between human language and systems of communication existing among animals (particularly other primates). Many argue that the origins of language probably relate closely to the origins of modern human behavior, but there is little agreement about the facts and implications of this connection.

The shortage of direct, empirical evidence has caused many scholars to regard the entire topic as unsuitable for serious study; in 1866, the Linguistic Society of Paris banned any existing or future debates on the subject, a prohibition which remained influential across much of the Western world until late in the twentieth century.[1][2] Various hypotheses have been developed about how, why, when, and where language might have emerged.[3] Still, little more has been universally agreed upon today (as of 1996) than over a century and a half ago, when Charles Darwin’s theory of evolution by natural selection provoked a surge of speculation on the topic.[4] Since the early 1990s, however, a number of linguists, archaeologists, psychologists, anthropologists, and others have attempted to address this issue with new, modern methods.[5]

ApproachesEdit

The origin of language can be sub-divided according to some underlying assumptions:[6]

  • «Continuity theories» build on the idea that language exhibits so much complexity that one cannot imagine it simply appearing from nothing in its final form; therefore it must have evolved from earlier pre-linguistic systems among humans’ primate ancestors.
  • «Discontinuity theories» take the opposite approach—that language, as a unique trait which cannot be compared to anything found among non-humans, must have appeared fairly suddenly during the course of human evolution.
  • Some theories consider language mostly as an innate faculty—largely genetically encoded.
  • Other theories regard language as a mainly cultural system—learned through social interaction.

A majority of linguistic scholars as of 2023 favour continuity-based theories, but they vary in how they hypothesize language development. Among those who consider language as mostly innate, some avoid speculating about specific precursors in nonhuman primates, stressing simply that the language faculty must have evolved in the usual gradual way.[7] Others in this intellectual camp—notably Ib Ulbæk[6]—hold that language evolved not from primate communication but from primate cognition, which is significantly more complex.

Those who consider language as learned socially, such as Michael Tomasello, consider it developing from the cognitively controlled aspects of primate communication, these being mostly gestural as opposed to vocal.[8][9] Where vocal precursors are concerned, many continuity theorists envisage language evolving from early human capacities for song.[10][11][12][13][14]

Noam Chomsky, a proponent of discontinuity theory, argues that a single chance mutation occurred in one individual in the order of 100,000 years ago, installing the language faculty (a hypothetical component of the mid-brain) in «perfect» or «near-perfect» form.[15]

Transcending the continuity-versus-discontinuity divide, some scholars view the emergence of language as the consequence of some kind of social transformation[16] that, by generating unprecedented levels of public trust, liberated a genetic potential for linguistic creativity that had previously lain dormant.[17][18][19] «Ritual/speech coevolution theory» exemplifies this approach.[20][21] Scholars in this intellectual camp point to the fact that even chimpanzees and bonobos have latent symbolic capacities that they rarely—if ever—use in the wild.[22] Objecting to the sudden mutation idea, these authors argue that even if a chance mutation were to install a language organ in an evolving bipedal primate, it would be adaptively useless under all known primate social conditions. A very specific social structure—one capable of upholding unusually high levels of public accountability and trust—must have evolved before or concurrently with language to make reliance on «cheap signals» (words) an evolutionarily stable strategy.

Since the emergence of language lies so far back in human prehistory, the relevant developments have left no direct historical traces; neither can comparable processes be observed today. Despite this, the emergence of new sign languages in modern times—Nicaraguan Sign Language, for example—may potentially offer insights into the developmental stages and creative processes necessarily involved.[23] Another approach inspects early human fossils, looking for traces of physical adaptation to language use.[24][25] In some cases, when the DNA of extinct humans can be recovered, the presence or absence of genes considered to be language-relevant—FOXP2, for example—may prove informative.[26] Another approach, this time archaeological, involves invoking symbolic behavior (such as repeated ritual activity) that may leave an archaeological trace—such as mining and modifying ochre pigments for body-painting—while developing theoretical arguments to justify inferences from symbolism in general to language in particular.[27][28][29]

The time range for the evolution of language or its anatomical prerequisites extends, at least in principle, from the phylogenetic divergence of Homo (2.3 to 2.4 million years ago) from Pan (5 to 6 million years ago) to the emergence of full behavioral modernity some 50,000–150,000 years ago. Few dispute that Australopithecus probably lacked vocal communication significantly more sophisticated than that of great apes in general,[30] but scholarly opinions vary as to the developments since the appearance of Homo some 2.5 million years ago. Some scholars assume the development of primitive language-like systems (proto-language) as early as Homo habilis, while others place the development of symbolic communication only with Homo erectus (1.8 million years ago) or with Homo heidelbergensis (0.6 million years ago) and the development of language proper with Homo sapiens, currently estimated at less than 200,000 years ago.

Using statistical methods to estimate the time required to achieve the current spread and diversity in modern languages, Johanna Nichols—a linguist at the University of California, Berkeley—argued in 1998 that vocal languages must have begun diversifying in the human species at least 100,000 years ago.[31] A further study by Q. D. Atkinson[11] suggests that successive population bottlenecks occurred as human African ancestors migrated to other areas, leading to a decrease in genetic and phenotypic diversity. Atkinson argues that these bottlenecks also affected culture and language, suggesting that the farther away a particular language is from Africa, the fewer phonemes it contains. By way of evidence, Atkinson claims that today’s African languages tend to have relatively large numbers of phonemes, whereas languages of Oceania (the last region to be populated by humans) have relatively few. Relying heavily on Atkinson’s work, a subsequent study has explored the rate at which phonemes develop naturally, comparing this rate to some of Africa’s oldest languages. The results suggest that language first evolved around 50,000–150,000 years ago, which is around the time when modern Homo sapiens evolved.[32] Estimates of this kind are not universally accepted, but jointly considering genetic, archaeological, palaeontological, and much other evidence indicates that language probably emerged somewhere in sub-Saharan Africa during the Middle Stone Age, roughly contemporaneous with the speciation of Homo sapiens.[33]

Language origin hypothesesEdit

Early speculationsEdit

I cannot doubt that language owes its origin to the imitation and modification, aided by signs and gestures, of various natural sounds, the voices of other animals, and man’s own instinctive cries.

— Charles Darwin, 1871. The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex[34]

In 1861, historical linguist Max Müller published a list of speculative theories concerning the origins of spoken language:[35]

  • Bow-wow. The bow-wow or cuckoo theory, which Müller attributed to the German philosopher Johann Gottfried Herder, saw early words as imitations of the cries of beasts and birds.
  • Pooh-pooh. The pooh-pooh theory saw the first words as emotional interjections and exclamations triggered by pain, pleasure, surprise, etc.
  • Ding-dong. Müller suggested what he called the ding-dong theory, which states that all things have a vibrating natural resonance, echoed somehow by man in his earliest words.
  • Yo-he-ho. The yo-he-ho theory claims language emerged from collective rhythmic labor, the attempt to synchronize muscular effort resulting in sounds such as heave alternating with sounds such as ho.
  • Ta-ta. This did not feature in Max Müller’s list, having been proposed in 1930 by Sir Richard Paget.[36] According to the ta-ta theory, humans made the earliest words by tongue movements that mimicked manual gestures, rendering them audible.

Most scholars today consider all such theories not so much wrong—they occasionally offer peripheral insights—as naïve and irrelevant.[37][38] The problem with these theories is that they are so narrowly mechanistic.[citation needed] They assume that once human ancestors had discovered the appropriate ingenious mechanism for linking sounds with meanings, language automatically evolved.

Medieval Muslim scholars also developed theories on the origin of language.[39][40] Their theories were of five general types:[41]

  1. Naturalist: There is a natural relation between expressions and the things they signify. Language thus emerged from a natural human inclination to imitate the sounds of nature.
  2. Conventionalist: Language is a social convention. The names of things are arbitrary inventions of humans.
  3. Revelationist: Language was gifted to humans by God, and it was thus God—and not humans—who named everything.
  4. Revelationist-Conventionalist: God revealed to humans a core base of language—enabling humans to communicate with each other—and then humans invented the rest of language.
  5. Non-Committal: The view that conventionalist and revelationist theories are equally plausible.

Problems of reliability and deceptionEdit

From the perspective of signalling theory, the main obstacle to the evolution of language-like communication in nature is not a mechanistic one. Rather, it is the fact that symbols—arbitrary associations of sounds or other perceptible forms with corresponding meanings—are unreliable and may well be false.[42][43] As the saying goes, «words are cheap».[44] The problem of reliability was not recognized at all by Darwin, Müller or the other early evolutionary theorists.

Animal vocal signals are, for the most part, intrinsically reliable. When a cat purrs, the signal constitutes direct evidence of the animal’s contented state. The signal is trusted, not because the cat is inclined to be honest, but because it just cannot fake that sound. Primate vocal calls may be slightly more manipulable, but they remain reliable for the same reason—because they are hard to fake.[45] Primate social intelligence is «Machiavellian»—self-serving and unconstrained by moral scruples. Monkeys and apes often attempt to deceive each other, while at the same time remaining constantly on guard against falling victim to deception themselves.[46][47] Paradoxically, it is theorized that primates’ resistance to deception is what blocks the evolution of their signalling systems along language-like lines. Language is ruled out because the best way to guard against being deceived is to ignore all signals except those that are instantly verifiable. Words automatically fail this test.[20]

Words are easy to fake. Should they turn out to be lies, listeners will adapt by ignoring them in favor of hard-to-fake indices or cues. For language to work, then, listeners must be confident that those with whom they are on speaking terms are generally likely to be honest.[48] A peculiar feature of language is «displaced reference», which means reference to topics outside the currently perceptible situation. This property prevents utterances from being corroborated in the immediate «here» and «now». For this reason, language presupposes relatively high levels of mutual trust in order to become established over time as an evolutionarily stable strategy. This stability is born of a longstanding mutual trust and is what grants language its authority. A theory of the origins of language must therefore explain why humans could begin trusting cheap signals in ways that other animals apparently cannot (see signalling theory).

The «mother tongues» hypothesisEdit

The «mother tongues» hypothesis was proposed in 2004 as a possible solution to this problem.[49] W. Tecumseh Fitch suggested that the Darwinian principle of «kin selection»[50]—the convergence of genetic interests between relatives—might be part of the answer. Fitch suggests that languages were originally «mother tongues». If language evolved initially for communication between mothers and their own biological offspring, extending later to include adult relatives as well, the interests of speakers and listeners would have tended to coincide. Fitch argues that shared genetic interests would have led to sufficient trust and cooperation for intrinsically unreliable signals—words—to become accepted as trustworthy and so begin evolving for the first time.[51]

Critics of this theory point out that kin selection is not unique to humans.[52] So even if one accepts Fitch’s initial premises, the extension of the posited «mother tongue» networks from close relatives to more distant relatives remains unexplained.[52] Fitch argues, however, that the extended period of physical immaturity of human infants and the postnatal growth of the human brain give the human-infant relationship a different and more extended period of intergenerational dependency than that found in any other species.[49]

The «obligatory reciprocal altruism» hypothesisEdit

Ib Ulbæk[6] invokes another standard Darwinian principle—»reciprocal altruism»[53]—to explain the unusually high levels of intentional honesty necessary for language to evolve. «Reciprocal altruism» can be expressed as the principle that if you scratch my back, I’ll scratch yours. In linguistic terms, it would mean that if you speak truthfully to me, I’ll speak truthfully to you. Ordinary Darwinian reciprocal altruism, Ulbæk points out, is a relationship established between frequently interacting individuals. For language to prevail across an entire community, however, the necessary reciprocity would have needed to be enforced universally instead of being left to individual choice. Ulbæk concludes that for language to evolve, society as a whole must have been subject to moral regulation.

Critics point out that this theory fails to explain when, how, why or by whom «obligatory reciprocal altruism» could possibly have been enforced.[21] Various proposals have been offered to remedy this defect.[21] A further criticism is that language does not work on the basis of reciprocal altruism anyway. Humans in conversational groups do not withhold information to all except listeners likely to offer valuable information in return. On the contrary, they seem to want to advertise to the world their access to socially relevant information, broadcasting that information without expectation of reciprocity to anyone who will listen.[54]

The gossip and grooming hypothesisEdit

Gossip, according to Robin Dunbar in his book Grooming, Gossip and the Evolution of Language, does for group-living humans what manual grooming does for other primates—it allows individuals to service their relationships and so maintain their alliances on the basis of the principle: if you scratch my back, I’ll scratch yours. Dunbar argues that as humans began living in increasingly larger social groups, the task of manually grooming all one’s friends and acquaintances became so time-consuming as to be unaffordable.[55] In response to this problem, humans developed «a cheap and ultra-efficient form of grooming»—vocal grooming. To keep allies happy, one now needs only to «groom» them with low-cost vocal sounds, servicing multiple allies simultaneously while keeping both hands free for other tasks. Vocal grooming then evolved gradually into vocal language—initially in the form of «gossip».[55] Dunbar’s hypothesis seems to be supported by the fact that the structure of language shows adaptations to the function of narration in general.[56]

Critics of this theory point out that the very efficiency of «vocal grooming»—the fact that words are so cheap—would have undermined its capacity to signal commitment of the kind conveyed by time-consuming and costly manual grooming.[57] A further criticism is that the theory does nothing to explain the crucial transition from vocal grooming—the production of pleasing but meaningless sounds—to the cognitive complexities of syntactical speech.

Ritual/speech coevolutionEdit

The ritual/speech coevolution theory was originally proposed by social anthropologist Roy Rappaport[17] before being elaborated by anthropologists such as Chris Knight,[20] Jerome Lewis,[58] Nick Enfield,[59] Camilla Power[48] and Ian Watts.[29] Cognitive scientist and robotics engineer Luc Steels[60] is another prominent supporter of this general approach, as is biological anthropologist and neuroscientist Terrence Deacon.[61]

These scholars argue that there can be no such thing as a «theory of the origins of language». This is because language is not a separate adaptation but an internal aspect of something much wider—namely, human symbolic culture as a whole.[19] Attempts to explain language independently of this wider context have failed, say these scientists, because they are addressing a problem with no solution. Language would not work outside a specific array of social mechanisms and institutions. For example, it would not work for a nonhuman ape communicating with others in the wild. Not even the cleverest nonhuman ape could make language work under such conditions.

Lie and alternative, inherent in language … pose problems to any society whose structure is founded on language, which is to say all human societies. I have therefore argued that if there are to be words at all it is necessary to establish The Word, and that The Word is established by the invariance of liturgy.

— Roy Rappaport[62]

Advocates of this school of thought point out that words are cheap. Should an especially clever nonhuman ape, or even a group of articulate nonhuman apes, try to use words in the wild, they would carry no conviction. The primate vocalizations that do carry conviction—those they actually use—are unlike words, in that they are emotionally expressive, intrinsically meaningful, and reliable because they are relatively costly and hard to fake.

Language consists of contrasts whose cost is essentially zero. As pure social conventions, signals of this kind cannot evolve in a Darwinian social world—they are a theoretical impossibility.[42] Being intrinsically unreliable, language works only if one can build up a reputation for trustworthiness within a certain kind of society—namely, one where symbolic cultural facts (sometimes called «institutional facts») can be established and maintained through collective social endorsement.[63] In any hunter-gatherer society, the basic mechanism for establishing trust in symbolic cultural facts is collective ritual.[64] Therefore, the task facing researchers into the origins of language is more multidisciplinary than is usually supposed. It involves addressing the evolutionary emergence of human symbolic culture as a whole, with language an important but subsidiary component.

Critics of the theory include Noam Chomsky, who terms it the «non-existence» hypothesis—a denial of the very existence of language as an object of study for natural science.[65] Chomsky’s own theory is that language emerged in an instant and in perfect form,[66] prompting his critics in turn, to retort that only something that does not exist—a theoretical construct or convenient scientific fiction—could possibly emerge in such a miraculous way.[18] The controversy remains unresolved.

Tool resiliency, grammar and language productionEdit

Acheulean tool use began during the Lower Paleolithic approximately 1.75 million years ago. Studies focusing on the lateralization of Acheulean tool production and language production have noted similar areas of blood flow when engaging in these activities separately; this theory suggests that the brain functions needed for the production of tools across generations is consistent with the brain systems required for producing language. Researchers used functional transcranial Doppler ultrasonography (fTDC) and had participants perform activities related to the creation of tools using the same methods during the Lower Paleolithic as well as a task designed specifically for word generation.[67] The purpose of this test was to focus on the planning aspect of Acheulean tool making and cued word generation in language (an example of cued word generation would be someone giving you a random letter and then you list all words beginning with that letter that you can think of). Theories of language developing alongside tool use has been theorized by multiple individuals,[68][69][70] however until recently there has been little empirical data to support these hypotheses. Focusing on the results of the study performed by Uomini et al. evidence for the usage of the same brain areas has been found when looking at cued word generation and Achuelean tool use. The relationship between tool use and language production is found in working and planning memory respectively and was found to be similar across a variety of participants furthering evidence that these areas of the brain are shared.[67] This evidence lends credibility to the theory that language developed alongside tool use in the Lower Paleolithic.

Humanistic theoryEdit

The humanistic tradition considers language as a human invention. Renaissance philosopher Antoine Arnauld gave a detailed description of his idea of the origin of language in Port-Royal Grammar. According to Arnauld, people are social and rational by nature, and this urged them to create language as a means to communicate their ideas to others. Language construction would have occurred through a slow and gradual process.[71] In later theory, especially in functional linguistics, the primacy of communication is emphasised over psychological needs.[72]

The exact way language evolved is however not considered as vital to the study of languages. Structural linguist Ferdinand de Saussure abandoned evolutionary linguistics after having come to the firm conclusion that it would not be able to provide any further revolutionary insight after the completion of the major works in historical linguistics by the end of the 19th century. Saussure was particularly sceptical of the attempts of August Schleicher and other Darwinian linguists to access prehistorical languages through series of reconstructions of proto-languages.[73]

Saussure’s solution to the problem of language evolution involves dividing theoretical linguistics in two. Evolutionary and historical linguistics are renamed as diachronic linguistics. It is the study of language change, but it has only limited explanatory power due to the inadequacy of all of the reliable research material that could ever be made available. Synchronic linguistics, in contrast, aims to widen scientists’ understanding of language through a study of a given contemporary or historical language stage as a system in its own right.[74]

Although Saussure paid much focus to diachronic linguistics, later structuralists who equated structuralism with the synchronic analysis were sometimes criticised of ahistoricism. According to structural anthropologist Claude Lévi-Strauss, language and meaning—in opposition to «knowledge, which develops slowly and progressively»—must have appeared in an instant.[75]

Structuralism, as first introduced to sociology by Émile Durkheim, is nonetheless a type of humanistic evolutionary theory which explains diversification as necessitated by growing complexity.[76] There was a shift of focus to functional explanation after Saussure’s death. Functional structuralists including the Prague Circle linguists and André Martinet explained the growth and maintenance of structures as being necessitated by their functions.[72] For example, novel technologies make it necessary for people to invent new words, but these may lose their function and be forgotten as the technologies are eventually replaced by more modern ones.

Chomsky’s single-step theoryEdit

According to Noam Chomsky’s single-mutation theory, the emergence of language resembled the formation of a crystal; with digital infinity as the seed crystal in a super-saturated primate brain, on the verge of blossoming into the human mind, by physical law, once evolution added a single small but crucial keystone.[77][66] Thus, in this theory, language appeared rather suddenly within the history of human evolution. Chomsky, writing with computational linguist and computer scientist Robert C. Berwick, suggests that this scenario is completely compatible with modern biology. They note that «none of the recent accounts of human language evolution seem to have completely grasped the shift from conventional Darwinism to its fully stochastic modern version—specifically, that there are stochastic effects not only due to sampling like directionless drift, but also due to directed stochastic variation in fitness, migration, and heritability—indeed, all the «forces» that affect individual or gene frequencies … All this can affect evolutionary outcomes—outcomes that as far as we can make out are not brought out in recent books on the evolution of language, yet would arise immediately in the case of any new genetic or individual innovation, precisely the kind of scenario likely to be in play when talking about language’s emergence.»

Citing evolutionary geneticist Svante Pääbo, they concur that a substantial difference must have occurred to differentiate Homo sapiens from Neanderthals to «prompt the relentless spread of our species, who had never crossed open water, up and out of Africa and then on across the entire planet in just a few tens of thousands of years. … What we do not see is any kind of ‘gradualism’ in new tool technologies or innovations like fire, shelters, or figurative art.» Berwick and Chomsky therefore suggest language emerged approximately between 200,000 years ago and 60,000 years ago (between the appearance of the first anatomically modern humans in southern Africa and the last exodus from Africa respectively). «That leaves us with about 130,000 years, or approximately 5,000–6,000 generations of time for evolutionary change. This is not ‘overnight in one generation’ as some have (incorrectly) inferred—but neither is it on the scale of geological eons. It’s time enough—within the ballpark for what Nilsson and Pelger (1994) estimated as the time required for the full evolution of a vertebrate eye from a single cell, even without the invocation of any ‘evo-devo’ effects.»[78]

The single-mutation theory of language evolution has been directly questioned on different grounds. A formal analysis of the probability of such a mutation taking place and going to fixation in the species has concluded that such a scenario is unlikely, with multiple mutations with more moderate fitness effects being more probable.[79] Another criticism has questioned the logic of the argument for single mutation and puts forward that from the formal simplicity of Merge, the capacity Berwick and Chomsky deem the core property of human language that emerged suddenly, one cannot derive the (number of) evolutionary steps that led to it.[80]

The Romulus and Remus hypothesisEdit

The Romulus and Remus hypothesis, proposed by neuroscientist Andrey Vyshedskiy, seeks to address the question as to why the modern speech apparatus originated over 500,000 years before the earliest signs of modern human imagination. This hypothesis proposes that there were two phases that led to modern recursive language. The phenomenon of recursion occurs across multiple linguistic domains, arguably most prominently in syntax and morphology. Thus, by nesting a structure such as a sentence or a word within themselves, it enables the generation of potentially (countably) infinite new variations of that structure. For example, the base sentence [Peter likes apples.] can be nested in irrealis clauses to produce [[Mary said [Peter likes apples.]], [Paul believed [Mary said [Peter likes apples.]]] and so forth.[81]

The first phase includes the slow development of non-recursive language with a large vocabulary along with the modern speech apparatus, which includes changes to the hyoid bone, increased voluntary control of the muscles of the diaphragm, the evolution of the FOXP2 gene, as well as other changes by 600,000 years ago.[82] Then, the second phase was a rapid Chomskian single step, consisting of three distinct events that happened in quick succession around 70,000 years ago and allowed the shift from non-recursive to recursive language in early hominins.

  1. A genetic mutation that slowed down the prefrontal synthesis (PFS) critical period of at least two children that lived together.
  2. This allowed these children to create recursive elements of language such as spatial prepositions.
  3. Then this merged with their parents’ non-recursive language to create recursive language.[83]

It is not enough for children to have a modern prefrontal cortex (PFC) to allow the development of PFS; the children must also be mentally stimulated and have recursive elements already in their language to acquire PFS. Since their parents would not have invented these elements yet, the children would have had to do it themselves, which is a common occurrence among young children that live together, in a process called cryptophasia.[84] This means that delayed PFC development would have allowed more time to acquire PFS and develop recursive elements.

Delayed PFC development also comes with negative consequences, such as a longer period of reliance on one’s parents to survive and lower survival rates. For modern language to have occurred, PFC delay had to have an immense survival benefit in later life, such as PFS ability. This suggests that the mutation that caused PFC delay and the development of recursive language and PFS occurred simultaneously, which lines up with evidence of a genetic bottleneck around 70,000 years ago.[85] This could have been the result of a few individuals who developed PFS and recursive language which gave them significant competitive advantage over all other humans at the time.[83]

Gestural theoryEdit

The gestural theory states that human language developed from gestures that were used for simple communication.

Two types of evidence support this theory.

  1. Gestural language and vocal language depend on similar neural systems. The regions on the cortex that are responsible for mouth and hand movements border each other.
  2. Nonhuman primates can use gestures or symbols for at least primitive communication, and some of their gestures resemble those of humans, such as the «begging posture», with the hands stretched out, which humans share with chimpanzees.[86][87]

Research has found strong support for the idea that verbal language and sign language depend on similar neural structures. Patients who used sign language, and who suffered from a left-hemisphere lesion, showed the same disorders with their sign language as vocal patients did with their oral language.[88] Other researchers found that the same left-hemisphere brain regions were active during sign language as during the use of vocal or written language.[89]

Primate gesture is at least partially genetic: different nonhuman apes will perform gestures characteristic of their species, even if they have never seen another ape perform that gesture. For example, gorillas beat their breasts. This shows that gestures are an intrinsic and important part of primate communication, which supports the idea that language evolved from gesture.[90]

Further evidence suggests that gesture and language are linked. In humans, manually gesturing has an effect on concurrent vocalizations, thus creating certain natural vocal associations of manual efforts. Chimpanzees move their mouths when performing fine motor tasks. These mechanisms may have played an evolutionary role in enabling the development of intentional vocal communication as a supplement to gestural communication. Voice modulation could have been prompted by preexisting manual actions.[90]

From infancy, gestures both supplement and predict speech.[91][92] This addresses the idea that gestures quickly change in humans from a sole means of communication (from a very young age) to a supplemental and predictive behavior that is used despite the ability to communicate verbally. This too serves as a parallel to the idea that gestures developed first and language subsequently built upon it.

Two possible scenarios have been proposed for the development of language,[93] one of which supports the gestural theory:

  1. Language developed from the calls of human ancestors.
  2. Language was derived from gesture.

The first perspective that language evolved from the calls of human ancestors seems logical because both humans and animals make sounds or cries. One evolutionary reason to refute this is that, anatomically, the centre that controls calls in monkeys and other animals is located in a completely different part of the brain than in humans. In monkeys, this centre is located in the depths of the brain related to emotions. In the human system, it is located in an area unrelated to emotion. Humans can communicate simply to communicate—without emotions. So, anatomically, this scenario does not work.[93] This suggests that language was derived from gesture[94](humans communicated by gesture first and sound was attached later).

The important question for gestural theories is why there was a shift to vocalization. Various explanations have been proposed:

  1. Human ancestors started to use more and more tools, meaning that their hands were occupied and could no longer be used for gesturing.[95]
  2. Manual gesturing requires that speakers and listeners be visible to one another. In many situations, they might need to communicate, even without visual contact—for example after nightfall or when foliage obstructs visibility.
  3. A composite hypothesis holds that early language took the form of part gestural and part vocal mimesis (imitative ‘song-and-dance’), combining modalities because all signals (like those of nonhuman apes and monkeys) still needed to be costly in order to be intrinsically convincing. In that event, each multi-media display would have needed not just to disambiguate an intended meaning but also to inspire confidence in the signal’s reliability. The suggestion is that only once community-wide contractual understandings had come into force[96] could trust in communicative intentions be automatically assumed, at last allowing Homo sapiens to shift to a more efficient default format. Since vocal distinctive features (sound contrasts) are ideal for this purpose, it was only at this point—when intrinsically persuasive body-language was no longer required to convey each message—that the decisive shift from manual gesture to the current primary reliance on spoken language occurred.[18][20][97]

A comparable hypothesis states that in ‘articulate’ language, gesture and vocalisation are intrinsically linked, as language evolved from equally intrinsically linked dance and song.[14]

Humans still use manual and facial gestures when they speak, especially when people meet who have no language in common.[98] There are also a great number of sign languages still in existence, commonly associated with deaf communities. These sign languages are equal in complexity, sophistication, and expressive power, to any oral language.[99] The cognitive functions are similar and the parts of the brain used are similar. The main difference is that the «phonemes» are produced on the outside of the body, articulated with hands, body, and facial expression, rather than inside the body articulated with tongue, teeth, lips, and breathing.[100] (Compare the motor theory of speech perception.)

It is suggested that nature has allotted psychological representations to all gestures, including vocal gestures. Animals have no intellectual purpose. Hence animals of the same species from different continents can communicate psychologically without learning any sign language. In the case of humans, in addition to the gestures, the vocal gestures are arbitrarily converted into the intellectual sense. This arbitrariness depends on biological, psychological, and intellectual needs and capabilities, which differ from place to place, creating language differences.[101]

Critics of gestural theory note that it is difficult to name serious reasons why the initial pitch-based vocal communication (which is present in primates) would be abandoned in favor of the much less effective non-vocal, gestural communication.[102] However, Michael Corballis has pointed out that it is supposed that primate vocal communication (such as alarm calls) cannot be controlled consciously, unlike hand movement, and thus it is not credible as precursor to human language; primate vocalization is rather homologous to and continued in involuntary reflexes (connected with basic human emotions) such as screams or laughter (the fact that these can be faked does not disprove the fact that genuine involuntary responses to fear or surprise exist).[94] Also, gesture is not generally less effective, and depending on the situation can even be advantageous, for example in a loud environment or where it is important to be silent, such as on a hunt. Other challenges to the «gesture-first» theory have been presented by researchers in psycholinguistics, including David McNeill.[103]

Tool-use associated sound in the evolution of languageEdit

Proponents of the motor theory of language evolution have primarily focused on the visual domain and communication through observation of movements. The Tool-use sound hypothesis suggests that the production and perception of sound also contributed substantially, particularly incidental sound of locomotion (ISOL) and tool-use sound (TUS). Human bipedalism resulted in rhythmic and more predictable ISOL. That may have stimulated the evolution of musical abilities, auditory working memory, and abilities to produce complex vocalizations, and to mimic natural sounds.[105] Since the human brain proficiently extracts information about objects and events from the sounds they produce, TUS, and mimicry of TUS, might have achieved an iconic function. The prevalence of sound symbolism in many extant languages supports this idea. Self-produced TUS activates multimodal brain processing (motor neurons, hearing, proprioception, touch, vision), and TUS stimulates primate audiovisual mirror neurons, which is likely to stimulate the development of association chains. Tool use and auditory gestures involve motor-processing of the forelimbs, which is associated with the evolution of vertebrate vocal communication. The production, perception, and mimicry of TUS may have resulted in a limited number of vocalizations or protowords that were associated with tool use. A new way to communicate about tools, especially when out of sight, would have had selective advantage. A gradual change in acoustic properties, meaning, or both could have resulted in arbitrariness and an expanded repertoire of words. Humans have been increasingly exposed to TUS over millions of years, coinciding with the period during which spoken language evolved.

Mirror neurons and language originsEdit

In humans, functional MRI studies have reported finding areas homologous to the monkey mirror neuron system in the inferior frontal cortex, close to Broca’s area, one of the language regions of the brain. This has led to suggestions that human language evolved from a gesture performance/understanding system implemented in mirror neurons. Mirror neurons have been said to have the potential to provide a mechanism for action-understanding, imitation-learning, and the simulation of other people’s behavior.[106] This hypothesis is supported by some cytoarchitectonic homologies between monkey premotor area F5 and human Broca’s area.[107]

Rates of vocabulary expansion link to the ability of children to vocally mirror non-words and so to acquire the new word pronunciations. Such speech repetition occurs automatically, quickly[108] and separately in the brain to speech perception.[109][110] Moreover, such vocal imitation can occur without comprehension such as in speech shadowing[111] and echolalia.[107][112] Further evidence for this link comes from a recent study in which the brain activity of two participants was measured using fMRI while they were gesturing words to each other using hand gestures with a game of charades—a modality that some have suggested might represent the evolutionary precursor of human language. Analysis of the data using Granger Causality revealed that the mirror-neuron system of the observer indeed reflects the pattern of activity of in the motor system of the sender, supporting the idea that the motor concept associated with the words is indeed transmitted from one brain to another using the mirror system.[113]

Not all linguists agree with the above arguments, however. In particular, supporters of Noam Chomsky argue against the possibility that the mirror neuron system can play any role in the hierarchical recursive structures essential to syntax.[114]

Putting-down-the-baby theoryEdit

According to Dean Falk’s «putting-down-the-baby» theory, vocal interactions between early hominid mothers and infants began a sequence of events that led, eventually, to human ancestors’ earliest words.[115] The basic idea is that evolving human mothers, unlike their counterparts in other primates, could not move around and forage with their infants clinging onto their backs. Loss of fur in the human case left infants with no means of clinging on. Frequently, therefore, mothers had to put their babies down. As a result, these babies needed to be reassured that they were not being abandoned. Mothers responded by developing ‘motherese’—an infant-directed communicative system embracing facial expressions, body language, touching, patting, caressing, laughter, tickling and emotionally expressive contact calls. The argument is that language developed out of this interaction.[115]

In The Mental and Social Life of Babies, psychologist Kenneth Kaye noted that no usable adult language could have evolved without interactive communication between very young children and adults. «No symbolic system could have survived from one generation to the next if it could not have been easily acquired by young children under their normal conditions of social life.»[116]

From-where-to-what theoryEdit

An illustration of the «from where to what» model of language evolution

The «from where to what» model is a language evolution model that is derived primarily from the organization of language processing in the brain into two structures: the auditory dorsal stream and the auditory ventral stream.[117][118] It hypothesizes seven stages of language evolution (see illustration). Speech originated for the purpose of exchanging contact calls between mothers and their offspring to find one another in the event they became separated (illustration part 1). The contact calls could be modified with intonations in order to express either a higher or lower level of distress (illustration part 2). The use of two types of contact calls enabled the first question-answer conversation. In this scenario, the child would emit a low-level distress call to express a desire to interact with an object, and the mother would respond with either another low-level distress call (to express approval of the interaction) or a high-level distress call (to express disapproval) (illustration part 3). Over time, the improved use of intonations and vocal control led to the invention of unique calls (phonemes) associated with distinct objects (illustration part 4). At first, children learned the calls (phonemes) from their parents by imitating their lip-movements (illustration part 5). Eventually, infants were able to encode into long-term memory all the calls (phonemes). Consequentially, mimicry via lip-reading was limited to infancy and older children learned new calls through mimicry without lip-reading (illustration part 6). Once individuals became capable of producing a sequence of calls, this allowed multi-syllabic words, which increased the size of their vocabulary (illustration part 7). The use of words, composed of sequences of syllables, provided the infra structure for communicating with sequences of words (i.e., sentences).

The theory’s name is derived from the two auditory streams, which are both found in the brains of humans and other primates. The auditory ventral stream is responsible for sound recognition, and so it is referred to as the auditory what stream.[119][120][121] In primates, the auditory dorsal stream is responsible for sound localization, and thus it is called the auditory where stream. Only in humans (in the left hemisphere), is it also responsible for other processes associated with language use and acquisition, such as speech repetition and production, integration of phonemes with their lip movements, perception and production of intonations, phonological long-term memory (long-term memory storage of the sounds of words), and phonological working memory (the temporary storage of the sounds of words).[122][123][124][125][126][127][128][129] Some evidence also indicates a role in recognising others by their voices.[130][131] The emergence of each of these functions in the auditory dorsal stream represents an intermediate stage in the evolution of language.

A contact call origin for human language is consistent with animal studies, as like human language, contact call discrimination in monkeys is lateralised to the left hemisphere.[132][133] Mice with knock-out to language related genes (such as FOXP2 and SRPX2) also resulted in the pups no longer emitting contact calls when separated from their mothers.[134][135] Supporting this model is also its ability to explain unique human phenomena, such as the use of intonations when converting words into commands and questions, the tendency of infants to mimic vocalisations during the first year of life (and its disappearance later on) and the protruding and visible human lips, which are not found in other apes. This theory could be considered an elaboration of the putting-down-the-baby theory of language evolution.

Grammaticalisation theoryEdit

«Grammaticalisation» is a continuous historical process in which free-standing words develop into grammatical appendages, while these in turn become ever more specialised and grammatical. An initially «incorrect» usage, in becoming accepted, leads to unforeseen consequences, triggering knock-on effects and extended sequences of change. Paradoxically, grammar evolves because, in the final analysis, humans care less about grammatical niceties than about making themselves understood.[136] If this is how grammar evolves today, according to this school of thought, similar principles at work can be legitimately inferred among distant human ancestors, when grammar itself was first being established.[137][138][139]

In order to reconstruct the evolutionary transition from early language to languages with complex grammars, it is necessary to know which hypothetical sequences are plausible and which are not. In order to convey abstract ideas, the first recourse of speakers is to fall back on immediately recognizable concrete imagery, very often deploying metaphors rooted in shared bodily experience.[140] A familiar example is the use of concrete terms such as «belly» or «back» to convey abstract meanings such as «inside» or «behind». Equally metaphorical is the strategy of representing temporal patterns on the model of spatial ones. For example, English speakers might say «It is going to rain», modelled on «I am going to London.» This can be abbreviated colloquially to «It’s gonna rain.» Even when in a hurry, English speakers do not say «I’m gonna London»—the contraction is restricted to the job of specifying tense. From such examples it can be seen why grammaticalisation is consistently unidirectional—from concrete to abstract meaning, not the other way around.[137]

Grammaticalisation theorists picture early language as simple, perhaps consisting only of nouns.[139]p. 111 Even under that extreme theoretical assumption, however, it is difficult to imagine what would realistically have prevented people from using, say, «spear» as if it were a verb («Spear that pig!»). People might have used their nouns as verbs or their verbs as nouns as occasion demanded. In short, while a noun-only language might seem theoretically possible, grammaticalisation theory indicates that it cannot have remained fixed in that state for any length of time.[137][141]

Creativity drives grammatical change.[141] This presupposes a certain attitude on the part of listeners. Instead of punishing deviations from accepted usage, listeners must prioritise imaginative mind-reading. Imaginative creativity—emitting a leopard alarm when no leopard was present, for example—is not the kind of behaviour which, say, vervet monkeys would appreciate or reward.[142] Creativity and reliability are incompatible demands; for «Machiavellian» primates as for animals generally, the overriding pressure is to demonstrate reliability.[143] If humans escape these constraints, it is because in their case, listeners are primarily interested in mental states.

To focus on mental states is to accept fictions—inhabitants of the imagination—as potentially informative and interesting. An example is metaphor: a metaphor is, literally, a false statement.[144] In Romeo and Juliet, Romeo declares «Juliet is the sun!». Juliet is a woman, not a ball of plasma in the sky, but human listeners are not (or not usually) pedants insistent on point-by-point factual accuracy. They want to know what the speaker has in mind. Grammaticalisation is essentially based on metaphor. To outlaw its use would be to stop grammar from evolving and, by the same token, to exclude all possibility of expressing abstract thought.[140][145]

A criticism of all this is that while grammaticalisation theory might explain language change today, it does not satisfactorily address the really difficult challenge—explaining the initial transition from primate-style communication to language as it is known today. Rather, the theory assumes that language already exists. As Bernd Heine and Tania Kuteva acknowledge: «Grammaticalisation requires a linguistic system that is used regularly and frequently within a community of speakers and is passed on from one group of speakers to another».[139] Outside modern humans, such conditions do not prevail.

Evolution-progression modelEdit

Human language is used for self-expression; however, expression displays different stages. The consciousness of self and feelings represents the stage immediately prior to the external, phonetic expression of feelings in the form of sound, i.e., language. Intelligent animals such as dolphins, Eurasian magpies, and chimpanzees live in communities, wherein they assign themselves roles for group survival and show emotions such as sympathy.[146] When such animals view their reflection (mirror test), they recognise themselves and exhibit self-consciousness.[147] Notably, humans evolved in a quite different environment than that of these animals. Human survival became easier with the development of tools, shelter, and fire, thus facilitating further advancement of social interaction, self-expression, and tool-making, as for hunting and gathering.[148] The increasing brain size allowed advanced provisioning and tools and the technological advances during the Palaeolithic era that built upon the previous evolutionary innovations of bipedalism and hand versatility allowed the development of human language.[citation needed]

Self-domesticated ape theoryEdit

According to a study investigating the song differences between white-rumped munias and its domesticated counterpart (Bengalese finch), the wild munias use a highly stereotyped song sequence, whereas the domesticated ones sing a highly unconstrained song. In wild finches, song syntax is subject to female preference—sexual selection—and remains relatively fixed. However, in the Bengalese finch, natural selection is replaced by breeding, in this case for colourful plumage, and thus, decoupled from selective pressures, stereotyped song syntax is allowed to drift. It is replaced, supposedly within 1000 generations, by a variable and learned sequence. Wild finches, moreover, are thought incapable of learning song sequences from other finches.[149] In the field of bird vocalisation, brains capable of producing only an innate song have very simple neural pathways: the primary forebrain motor centre, called the robust nucleus of arcopallium, connects to midbrain vocal outputs, which in turn project to brainstem motor nuclei. By contrast, in brains capable of learning songs, the arcopallium receives input from numerous additional forebrain regions, including those involved in learning and social experience. Control over song generation has become less constrained, more distributed, and more flexible.[149]

One way to think about human evolution is that humans are self-domesticated apes. Just as domestication relaxed selection for stereotypic songs in the finches—mate choice was supplanted by choices made by the aesthetic sensibilities of bird breeders and their customers—so might human cultural domestication have relaxed selection on many of their primate behavioural traits, allowing old pathways to degenerate and reconfigure. Given the highly indeterminate way that mammalian brains develop—they basically construct themselves «bottom up», with one set of neuronal interactions preparing for the next round of interactions—degraded pathways would tend to seek out and find new opportunities for synaptic hookups. Such inherited de-differentiations of brain pathways might have contributed to the functional complexity that characterises human language. And, as exemplified by the finches, such de-differentiations can occur in very rapid time-frames.[150]

Speech and language for communicationEdit

A distinction can be drawn between speech and language. Language is not necessarily spoken: it might alternatively be written or signed. Speech is among a number of different methods of encoding and transmitting linguistic information, albeit arguably the most natural one.[151]

Some scholars, such as Noam Chomsky, view language as an initially cognitive development, its «externalisation» to serve communicative purposes occurring later in human evolution. According to one such school of thought, the key feature distinguishing human language is recursion,[152] (in this context, the iterative embedding of phrases within phrases). Other scholars—notably Daniel Everett—deny that recursion is universal, citing certain languages (e.g. Pirahã) which allegedly lack this feature.[153]

The ability to ask questions is considered by some[like whom?] to distinguish language from non-human systems of communication.[154] Some captive primates (notably bonobos and chimpanzees), having learned to use rudimentary signing to communicate with their human trainers, proved able to respond correctly to complex questions and requests. Yet they failed to ask even the simplest questions themselves.[155] Conversely, human children are able to ask their first questions (using only question intonation) at the babbling period of their development, long before they start using syntactic structures. Although babies from different cultures acquire native languages from their social environment, all languages of the world without exception—tonal, non-tonal, intonational and accented—use similar rising «question intonation» for yes–no questions.[156][157] This fact is a strong evidence of the universality of question intonation. In general, according to some authors, sentence intonation/pitch is pivotal in spoken grammar and is the basic information used by children to learn the grammar of whatever language.[14]

Cognitive development and languageEdit

Language users have high-level reference (or deixis), the ability to refer to things or states of being that are not in the immediate realm of the speaker. This ability is often related to theory of mind, or an awareness of the other as a being like the self with individual wants and intentions. According to Chomsky, Hauser and Fitch (2002), there are six main aspects of this high-level reference system:

  • Theory of mind
  • Capacity to acquire non-linguistic conceptual representations, such as the object/kind distinction
  • Referential vocal signals
  • Imitation as a rational, intentional system
  • Voluntary control over signal production as evidence of intentional communication
  • Number representation[152]

Theory of mindEdit

Simon Baron-Cohen (1999) argues that theory of mind must have preceded language use, based on evidence of use of the following characteristics as much as 40,000 years ago: intentional communication, repairing failed communication, teaching, intentional persuasion, intentional deception, building shared plans and goals, intentional sharing of focus or topic, and pretending. Moreover, Baron-Cohen argues that many primates show some, but not all, of these abilities.[citation needed] Call and Tomasello’s research on chimpanzees supports this, in that individual chimps seem to understand that other chimps have awareness, knowledge, and intention, but do not seem to understand false beliefs. Many primates show some tendencies toward a theory of mind, but not a full one as humans have.[158]

Ultimately, there is some consensus within the field that a theory of mind is necessary for language use. Thus, the development of a full theory of mind in humans was a necessary precursor to full language use.[159]

Number representationEdit

In one particular study, rats and pigeons were required to press a button a certain number of times to get food. The animals showed very accurate distinction for numbers less than four, but as the numbers increased, the error rate increased.[152] In another, the primatologist Tetsuro Matsuzawa attempted to teach chimpanzees Arabic numerals.[160] The difference between primates and humans in this regard was very large, as it took the chimps thousands of trials to learn 1–9, with each number requiring a similar amount of training time; yet, after learning the meaning of 1, 2 and 3 (and sometimes 4), children (after the age of 5.5 to 6) easily comprehend the value of greater integers by using a successor function (i.e. 2 is 1 greater than 1, 3 is 1 greater than 2, 4 is 1 greater than 3; once 4 is reached it seems most children suddenly understand that the value of any integer n is 1 greater than the previous integer).[161] Put simply, other primates learn the meaning of numbers one by one, similar to their approach to other referential symbols, while children first learn an arbitrary list of symbols (1, 2, 3, 4…) and then later learn their precise meanings.[162] These results can be seen as evidence for the application of the «open-ended generative property» of language in human numeral cognition.[152]

Linguistic structuresEdit

Lexical-phonological principleEdit

Hockett (1966) details a list of features regarded as essential to describing human language.[163] In the domain of the lexical-phonological principle, two features of this list are most important:

  • Productivity: users can create and understand completely novel messages.
    • New messages are freely coined by blending, analogizing from, or transforming old ones.
    • Either new or old elements are freely assigned new semantic loads by circumstances and context. This says that in every language, new idioms constantly come into existence.
  • Duality (of Patterning): a large number of meaningful elements are made up of a conveniently small number of independently meaningless yet message-differentiating elements.

The sound system of a language is composed of a finite set of simple phonological items. Under the specific phonotactic rules of a given language, these items can be recombined and concatenated, giving rise to morphology and the open-ended lexicon. A key feature of language is that a simple, finite set of phonological items gives rise to an infinite lexical system wherein rules determine the form of each item, and meaning is inextricably linked with form. Phonological syntax, then, is a simple combination of pre-existing phonological units. Related to this is another essential feature of human language: lexical syntax, wherein pre-existing units are combined, giving rise to semantically novel or distinct lexical items.[This paragraph needs citation(s)]

Certain elements of the lexical-phonological principle are known to exist outside of humans. While all (or nearly all) have been documented in some form in the natural world, very few coexist within the same species. Bird-song, singing nonhuman apes, and the songs of whales all display phonological syntax, combining units of sound into larger structures apparently devoid of enhanced or novel meaning. Certain other primate species do have simple phonological systems with units referring to entities in the world. However, in contrast to human systems, the units in these primates’ systems normally occur in isolation, betraying a lack of lexical syntax. There is new[when?] evidence to suggest that Campbell’s monkeys also display lexical syntax, combining two calls (a predator alarm call with a «boom», the combination of which denotes a lessened threat of danger), however it is still unclear whether this is a lexical or a morphological phenomenon.[164]

Pidgins and creolesEdit

Pidgins are significantly simplified languages with only rudimentary grammar and a restricted vocabulary. In their early stage, pidgins mainly consist of nouns, verbs, and adjectives with few or no articles, prepositions, conjunctions or auxiliary verbs. Often the grammar has no fixed word order and the words have no inflection.[165]

If contact is maintained between the groups speaking the pidgin for long periods of time, the pidgins may become more complex over many generations. If the children of one generation adopt the pidgin as their native language it develops into a creole language, which becomes fixed and acquires a more complex grammar, with fixed phonology, syntax, morphology, and syntactic embedding. The syntax and morphology of such languages may often have local innovations not obviously derived from any of the parent languages.

Studies of creole languages around the world have suggested that they display remarkable similarities in grammar[citation needed] and are developed uniformly from pidgins in a single generation. These similarities are apparent even when creoles do not have any common language origins. In addition, creoles are similar, despite being developed in isolation from each other. Syntactic similarities include subject–verb–object word order. Even when creoles are derived from languages with a different word order they often develop the SVO word order. Creoles tend to have similar usage patterns for definite and indefinite articles, and similar movement rules for phrase structures even when the parent languages do not.[165]

Evolutionary timelineEdit

Primate communicationEdit

Field primatologists can give useful insights into great ape communication in the wild.[30] An important[according to whom?] finding is that nonhuman primates, including the other great apes, produce calls that are graded, as opposed to categorically differentiated, with listeners striving to evaluate subtle gradations in signallers’ emotional and bodily states. Nonhuman apes seemingly find it extremely difficult to produce vocalisations in the absence of the corresponding emotional states.[45] In captivity, nonhuman apes have been taught rudimentary forms of sign language or have been persuaded to use lexigrams—symbols that do not graphically resemble the corresponding words—on computer keyboards. Some nonhuman apes, such as Kanzi, have been able to learn and use hundreds of lexigrams.[166][167]

The Broca’s and Wernicke’s areas in the primate brain are responsible for controlling the muscles of the face, tongue, mouth, and larynx, as well as recognizing sounds. Primates are known to make «vocal calls», and these calls are generated by circuits in the brainstem and limbic system.[168]

In the wild, the communication of vervet monkeys has been the most extensively studied.[165] They are known to make up to ten different vocalizations. Many of these are used to warn other members of the group about approaching predators. They include a «leopard call», a «snake call», and an «eagle call».[169] Each call triggers a different defensive strategy in the monkeys who hear the call and scientists were able to elicit predictable responses from the monkeys using loudspeakers and prerecorded sounds. Other vocalisations may be used for identification. If an infant monkey calls, its mother turns toward it, but other vervet mothers turn instead toward that infant’s mother to see what she will do.[170][171]

Similarly, researchers have demonstrated that chimpanzees (in captivity) use different «words» in reference to different foods. They recorded vocalisations that chimps made in reference, for example, to grapes, and then other chimps pointed at pictures of grapes when they heard the recorded sound.[172][173]

Ardipithecus ramidusEdit

A study published in HOMO: Journal of Comparative Human Biology in 2017 claims that Ardipithecus ramidus, a hominin dated at approximately 4.5Ma, shows the first evidence of an anatomical shift in the hominin lineage suggestive of increased vocal capability.[174] This study compared the skull of A. ramidus with 29 chimpanzee skulls of different ages and found that in numerous features A. ramidus clustered with the infant and juvenile measures as opposed to the adult measures. Significantly,[according to whom?] such affinity with the shape dimensions of infant and juvenile chimpanzee skull architecture, it was argued, may have resulted in greater vocal capability. This assertion was based on the notion that the chimpanzee vocal tract ratios that prevent speech are a result of growth factors associated with puberty—growth factors absent in A. ramidus ontogeny. A. ramidus was also found to have a degree of cervical lordosis more conducive to vocal modulation when compared with chimpanzees as well as cranial base architecture suggestive of increased vocal capability.

What was significant in this study[according to whom?] was the observation that the changes in skull architecture that correlate with reduced aggression are the same changes necessary for the evolution of early hominin vocal ability. In integrating data on anatomical correlates of primate mating and social systems with studies of skull and vocal tract architecture that facilitate speech production, the authors argue that paleoanthropologists to date[when?] have failed to understand the important relationship between early hominin social evolution and language capacity.

While the skull of A. ramidus, according to the authors, lacks the anatomical impediments to speech evident in chimpanzees, it is unclear what the vocal capabilities of this early hominin were. While they suggest A. ramidus—based on similar vocal tract ratios—may have had vocal capabilities equivalent to a modern human infant or very young child, they concede this is obviously a debatable and speculative hypothesis. However, they do claim that changes in skull architecture through processes of social selection were a necessary prerequisite for language evolution. As they write:

We propose that as a result of paedomorphic morphogenesis of the cranial base and craniofacial morphology Ar. ramidus would have not been limited in terms of the mechanical components of speech production as chimpanzees and bonobos are. It is possible that Ar. ramidus had vocal capability approximating that of chimpanzees and bonobos, with its idiosyncratic skull morphology not resulting in any significant advances in speech capability. In this sense the anatomical features analysed in this essay would have been exapted in later more voluble species of hominin. However, given the selective advantages of pro-social vocal synchrony, we suggest the species would have developed significantly more complex vocal abilities than chimpanzees and bonobos.[174]

Early HomoEdit

Anatomically, some scholars believe that features of bipedalism developed in the australopithecines around 3.5 million years ago. Around this time, these structural developments within the skull led to a more prominently L-shaped vocal tract.[175][page needed] In order to generate the sounds modern homo sapiens are capable of making, such as vowels, it is vital that Early Homo populations must have a specifically shaped voice track and a lower sitting larynx.[176] Opposing research previously suggested that Neanderthals were physically incapable of creating the full range of vocals seen in modern humans due to the differences in larynx placement. Establishing distinct larynx positions through fossil remains of Homo sapiens and Neanderthals would support this theory; however, modern research has revealed that the hyoid bone was indistinguishable from the two populations. Though research has shown a lower sitting larynx is important to producing speech, another theory states it may not be as important as once thought.[177] Cataldo, Migliano, & Vinicius (2018) stated that speech may have emerged due to an increase in trade and communication between different groups. Another view by Cataldo states that speech was evolved to enable tool-making by the Neanderthals.[178]

Archaic Homo sapiensEdit

Steven Mithen proposed the term Hmmmmm for the pre-linguistic system of communication posited to have been used by archaic Homo, beginning with Homo ergaster and reaching the highest sophistication in the Middle Pleistocene with Homo heidelbergensis and Homo neanderthalensis. Hmmmmm is an acronym for holistic (non-compositional), manipulative (utterances are commands or suggestions, not descriptive statements), multi-modal (acoustic as well as gestural and facial), musical, and mimetic.[179]

Homo erectus

Evidence for Homo erectus potentially using language comes in the form of Acheulean tool usage. The use of abstract thought in the formation of Acheulean hand axes coincides with the symbol creation necessary for simple language.[180] Recent language theories present recursion as the unique facet of human language and theory of mind.[181][182] However, breaking down language into its symbolic parts: separating meaning from the requirements of grammar, it becomes possible to see that language does not depend on either recursion or grammar. This can be evidenced by the Pirahã language users in Brazil that have no myth or creation stories, no numbers and no colors within their language.[183] This is to highlight that even though grammar may have been unavailable, use of foresight, planning and symbolic thought can be evidence of language as early as one million years ago with Homo erectus.

Homo heidelbergensisEdit

Homo heidelbergensis was a close relative (most probably a migratory descendant) of Homo ergaster. Some researchers believe this species to be the first hominin to make controlled vocalisations, possibly mimicking animal vocalisations,[179] and that as Homo heidelbergensis developed more sophisticated culture, proceeded from this point and possibly developed an early form of symbolic language.

Homo neanderthalensisEdit

The discovery in 1989 of the (Neanderthal) Kebara 2 hyoid bone suggests that Neanderthals may have been anatomically capable of producing sounds similar to modern humans.[184][185] The hypoglossal nerve, which passes through the hypoglossal canal, controls the movements of the tongue, which may have enabled voicing for size exaggeration (see size exaggeration hypothesis below) or may reflect speech abilities.[25][186][187][188][189][190]

However, although Neanderthals may have been anatomically able to speak, Richard G. Klein in 2004 doubted that they possessed a fully modern language. He largely bases his doubts on the fossil record of archaic humans and their stone tool kit. Bart de Boer in 2017 acknowledges this ambiguity of a universally accepted Neanderthal vocal tract; however, he notes the similarities in the thoracic vertebral canal, potential air sacs, and hyoid bones between modern humans and Neanderthals to suggest the presence of complex speech.[191] For two million years following the emergence of Homo habilis, the stone tool technology of hominins changed very little. Klein, who has worked extensively on ancient stone tools, describes the crude stone tool kit of archaic humans as impossible to break down into categories based on their function, and reports that Neanderthals seem to have had little concern for the final aesthetic form of their tools. Klein argues that the Neanderthal brain may have not reached the level of complexity required for modern speech, even if the physical apparatus for speech production was well-developed.[192][193] The issue of the Neanderthal’s level of cultural and technological sophistication remains a controversial one.[citation needed]

Based on computer simulations used to evaluate that evolution of language that resulted in showing three stages in the evolution of syntax, Neanderthals are thought to have been in stage 2, showing they had something more evolved than proto-language but not quite as complex as the language of modern humans.[194]

Some researchers, applying auditory bioengineering models to computerised tomography scans of Neanderthal skulls, have asserted that Neanderthals had auditory capacity very similar to that of anatomically modern humans.[195] These researchers claim that this finding implies that «Neanderthals evolved the auditory capacities to support a vocal communication system as efficient as modern human speech.»[195]

Homo sapiensEdit

Anatomically modern humans begin to appear in the fossil record in Ethiopia some 200,000 years ago.[196] Although there is still much debate as to whether behavioural modernity emerged in Africa at around the same time, a growing number of archaeologists nowadays[when?] invoke the southern African Middle Stone Age use of red ochre pigments—for example at Blombos Cave—as evidence that modern anatomy and behaviour co-evolved.[197] These archaeologists argue strongly that if modern humans at this early stage were using red ochre pigments for ritual and symbolic purposes, they probably had symbolic language as well.[27]

According to the recent African origins hypothesis, from around 60,000 – 50,000 years ago[198] a group of humans left Africa and began migrating to occupy the rest of the world, carrying language and symbolic culture with them.[199]

The descended larynxEdit

The larynx or voice box is an organ in the neck housing the vocal folds, which are responsible for phonation. In humans, the larynx is descended. The human species is not unique in this respect: goats, dogs, pigs and tamarins lower the larynx temporarily, to emit loud calls.[200] Several deer species have a permanently lowered larynx, which may be lowered still further by males during their roaring displays.[201] Lions, jaguars, cheetahs and domestic cats also do this.[202] However, laryngeal descent in nonhumans (according to Philip Lieberman) is not accompanied by descent of the hyoid; hence the tongue remains horizontal in the oral cavity, preventing it from acting as a pharyngeal articulator.[203]

Larynx
 

Anatomy of the larynx, anterolateral view

Anatomical terminology

[edit on Wikidata]

Despite all this, scholars remain divided as to how «special» the human vocal tract really is. It has been shown that the larynx does descend to some extent during development in chimpanzees, followed by hyoidal descent.[204] As against this, Philip Lieberman points out that only humans have evolved permanent and substantial laryngeal descent in association with hyoidal descent, resulting in a curved tongue and two-tube vocal tract with 1:1 proportions. He argues that Neanderthals and early anatomically modern humans could not have possessed supralaryngeal vocal tracts capable of producing «fully human speech».[205] Uniquely in the human case, simple contact between the epiglottis and velum is no longer possible, disrupting the normal mammalian separation of the respiratory and digestive tracts during swallowing. Since this entails substantial costs—increasing the risk of choking while swallowing food—we are forced to ask what benefits might have outweighed those costs. The obvious benefit—so it is claimed—must have been speech. But this idea has been vigorously contested. One objection is that humans are in fact not seriously at risk of choking on food: medical statistics indicate that accidents of this kind are extremely rare.[206] Another objection is that in the view of most scholars, speech as it is known emerged relatively late in human evolution, roughly contemporaneously with the emergence of Homo sapiens.[32] A development as complex as the reconfiguration of the human vocal tract would have required much more time, implying an early date of origin. This discrepancy in timescales undermines the idea that human vocal flexibility was initially driven by selection pressures for speech, thus not excluding that it was selected for e.g. improved singing ability.

The size exaggeration hypothesisEdit

To lower the larynx is to increase the length of the vocal tract, in turn lowering formant frequencies so that the voice sounds «deeper»—giving an impression of greater size. John Ohala argues that the function of the lowered larynx in humans, especially males, is probably to enhance threat displays rather than speech itself.[207] Ohala points out that if the lowered larynx were an adaptation for speech, adult human males would be expected to be better adapted in this respect than adult females, whose larynx is considerably less low. However, females outperform males in verbal tests,[208] falsifying this whole line of reasoning.

W. Tecumseh Fitch likewise argues that this was the original selective advantage of laryngeal lowering in the human species. Although (according to Fitch) the initial lowering of the larynx in humans had nothing to do with speech, the increased range of possible formant patterns was subsequently co-opted for speech. Size exaggeration remains the sole function of the extreme laryngeal descent observed in male deer. Consistent with the size exaggeration hypothesis, a second descent of the larynx occurs at puberty in humans, although only in males. In response to the objection that the larynx is descended in human females, Fitch suggests that mothers vocalizing to protect their infants would also have benefited from this ability.[209]

Phonemic diversityEdit

In 2011, Quentin Atkinson published a survey of phonemes from 500 different languages as well as language families and compared their phonemic diversity by region, number of speakers and distance from Africa. The survey revealed that African languages had the largest number of phonemes, and Oceania and South America had the smallest number. After allowing for the number of speakers, the phonemic diversity was compared to over 2000 possible origin locations. Atkinson’s «best fit» model is that language originated in central and southern Africa between 80,000 and 160,000 years ago. This predates the hypothesized southern coastal peopling of Arabia, India, southeast Asia, and Australia. It would also mean that the origin of language occurred at the same time as the emergence of symbolic culture.[11]

HistoryEdit

In religion and mythologyEdit

The search for the origin of language has a long history in mythology. Most mythologies do not credit humans with the invention of language but speak of a divine language predating human language. Mystical languages used to communicate with animals or spirits, such as the language of the birds, are also common, and were of particular interest during the Renaissance.

Vāc is the Hindu goddess of speech, or «speech personified». As Brahman’s «sacred utterance», she has a cosmological role as the «Mother of the Vedas». The Aztecs’ story maintains that only a man, Coxcox, and a woman, Xochiquetzal, survived a flood, having floated on a piece of bark. They found themselves on land and had many children who were at first born unable to speak, but subsequently, upon the arrival of a dove, were endowed with language, although each one was given a different speech such that they could not understand one another.[210]

In the Old Testament, the Book of Genesis (11) says that God prevented the Tower of Babel from being completed through a miracle that made its construction workers start speaking different languages. After this, they migrated to other regions, grouped together according to which of the newly created languages they spoke, explaining the origins of languages and nations outside of the Fertile Crescent.[211]

Historical experimentsEdit

History contains a number of anecdotes about people who attempted to discover the origin of language by experiment. The first such tale was told by Herodotus (Histories 2.2). He relates that Pharaoh Psammetichus (probably Psammetichus I, 7th century BC) had two children raised by a shepherd, with the instructions that no one should speak to them, but that the shepherd should feed and care for them while listening to determine their first words. When one of the children cried «bekos» with outstretched arms the shepherd concluded that the word was Phrygian, because that was the sound of the Phrygian word for «bread». From this, Psammetichus concluded that the first language was Phrygian. King James V of Scotland is said to have tried a similar experiment; his children were supposed to have spoken Hebrew.[212]

Both the medieval monarch Frederick II and Akbar are said to have tried similar experiments; the children involved in these experiments did not speak. The current situation of deaf people also points into this direction.[clarification needed]

History of researchEdit

Modern linguistics did not begin until the late 18th century, and the Romantic or animist theses of Johann Gottfried Herder and Johann Christoph Adelung remained influential well into the 19th century. The question of language origin seemed inaccessible to methodical approaches, and in 1866 the Linguistic Society of Paris famously banned all discussion of the origin of language, deeming it to be an unanswerable problem. An increasingly systematic approach to historical linguistics developed in the course of the 19th century, reaching its culmination in the Neogrammarian school of Karl Brugmann and others.[citation needed]

However, scholarly interest in the question of the origin of language has only gradually been rekindled[colloquialism] from the 1950s on (and then controversially) with ideas such as universal grammar, mass comparison and glottochronology.[citation needed]

The «origin of language» as a subject in its own right emerged from studies in neurolinguistics, psycholinguistics and human evolution. The Linguistic Bibliography introduced «Origin of language» as a separate heading in 1988, as a sub-topic of psycholinguistics. Dedicated research institutes of evolutionary linguistics are a recent phenomenon, emerging only in the 1990s.[213]

See alsoEdit

  • Abiogenesis
  • Biolinguistics
  • Bouba/kiki effect
  • Bow-wow theory
  • Digital infinity
  • Essay on the Origin of Languages
  • Evolutionary psychology of language
  • FOXP2 and human evolution
  • Generative anthropology
  • Historical linguistics
  • Neurobiological origins of language
  • Origins of society
  • Origin of speech
  • Proto-language
  • Theory of language

ReferencesEdit

  1. ^ Hauser, M. D.; Yang, C.; Berwick, R. C.; Tattersall, I.; Ryan, M. J.; Watumull, J.; Chomsky, N.; Lewontin, R. C. (2014). «The mystery of language evolution». Frontiers in Psychology. 5: 401. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00401. PMC 4019876. PMID 24847300.
  2. ^ Stam, J. H. 1976. Inquiries into the origins of language. New York: Harper and Row, p. 255.
  3. ^ Tallerman, Maggie; Gibson, Kathleen Rita (2012). The Oxford handbook of language evolution. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954111-9. OCLC 724665645.
  4. ^ Müller, F. M. 1996 [1861]. The theoretical stage, and the origin of language. Lecture 9 from Lectures on the Science of Language. Reprinted in R. Harris (ed.), The Origin of Language. Bristol: Thoemmes Press, pp. 7–41.
  5. ^ Christiansen, Morten H; Kirby, Simon (2003). Morten H. Christiansen; Simon Kirby (eds.). Language evolution : the hardest problem in science?. Language evolution. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 77–93. ISBN 978-0-19-924484-3. OCLC 51235137.
  6. ^ a b c Ulbæk, Ib (1998). James R Hurford; Michael Studdert-Kennedy; Chris Knight (eds.). The origin of language and cognition. Approaches to the evolution of language : social and cognitive base. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 30–43. ISBN 978-0-521-63964-4. OCLC 37742390.
  7. ^
    Pinker, Steven (1994). The language instinct. New York: W. Morrow and Co. ISBN 978-0-688-12141-9. OCLC 28723210.
  8. ^ Tomasello, Michael (1996). B M Velichkovskiĭ; Duane M Rumbaugh; Universität Bielefeld Zentrum für Interdisziplinäre Forschung (eds.). The cultural roots of language. Communicating meaning : the evolution and development of language. Mahwah, N.J.: L. Erlbaum. ISBN 978-0-8058-2118-5. OCLC 34078362.
  9. ^ Pika, Simone; Mitani, John (2006). «Referential gestural communication in wild chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes)». Current Biology. 16 (6): R191–R192. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2006.02.037. ISSN 0960-9822. PMID 16546066. S2CID 2273018.
  10. ^ Dunn, M.; Greenhill, SJ.; Levinson, SC.; Gray, RD. (May 2011). «Evolved structure of language shows lineage-specific trends in word-order universals». Nature. 473 (7345): 79–82. Bibcode:2011Natur.473…79D. doi:10.1038/nature09923. hdl:11858/00-001M-0000-0013-3B19-B. PMID 21490599. S2CID 1588797.
  11. ^ a b c Atkinson, Quentin (2011). «Phonemic Diversity Supports a Serial Founder Effect Model of Language Expansion from Africa» (PDF). Science Magazine. 332 (6027): 346–349. Bibcode:2011Sci…332..346A. doi:10.1126/science.1199295. PMID 21493858. S2CID 42021647. Retrieved 9 July 2017.
  12. ^ The Economist, «The evolution of language: Babel or babble?», 16 April 2011, pp. 85–86.
  13. ^ Cross, Ian; Woodruff, Ghofur Eliot (23 April 2009). «Music as a Communicative medium». In Rudolf Botha; Chris Knight (eds.). The Prehistory of Language. OUP Oxford. pp. 77–98. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199545872.003.0005. ISBN 978-0-19-156287-7.
  14. ^ a b c Vaneechoutte, Mario (2014). «The Origin of Articulate Language Revisited: The Potential of a Semi-Aquatic Past of Human Ancestors to Explain the Origin of Human Musicality and Articulate Language» (PDF). Human Evolution. 29: 1–33.
  15. ^ Chomsky, N, 1996. Powers and Prospects. Reflections on human nature and the social order. London: Pluto Press, p 30.
  16. ^ Knight, Chris; Power, Camilla (2012). Maggie Tallerman; Kathleen R. Gibson (eds.). Social conditions for the evolutionary emergence of language (PDF). The Oxford handbook of language evolution. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 346–49. ISBN 978-0-19-954111-9. OCLC 724665645.
  17. ^ a b Rappaport, Roy (1999). Ritual and religion in the making of humanity. Cambridge, U.K. New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780521296908. OCLC 848728046.
  18. ^ a b c Knight, C. (2008). «‘Honest fakes’ and language origins» (PDF). Journal of Consciousness Studies. 15 (10–11): 236–48.
  19. ^ a b Knight, Chris (2010). Ulrich J Frey; Charlotte Störmer; Kai P Willführ (eds.). The origins of symbolic culture (PDF). Homo novus : a human without illusion. Berlin; New York: Springer. pp. 193–211. ISBN 978-3-642-12141-8. OCLC 639461749.
  20. ^ a b c d Knight, Chris (1998). James R Hurford; Michael Studdert-Kennedy; Chris Knight (eds.). Ritual/speech coevolution: a solution to the problem of deception (PDF). Approaches to the evolution of language : social and cognitive base. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 68–91. ISBN 978-0-521-63964-4. OCLC 37742390.
  21. ^ a b c Knight, Chris (2006). Angelo Cangelosi; Andrew D M Smith; Kenny Smith (eds.). Language co-evolved with the rule of law (PDF). The evolution of language : proceedings of the 6th international conference (EVOLANG6), Rome, Italy, 12–15 April 200. New Jersey: World Scientific Publishing. pp. 168–175. ISBN 978-981-256-656-0. OCLC 70797781.
  22. ^ Savage-Rumbaugh, Sue; McDonald, Kelly (1988). Richard W Byrne; Andrew Whiten (eds.). Deception and social manipulation in symbol-using apes. Machiavellian intelligence : social expertise and the evolution of intellect in monkeys, apes, and human. Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 224–237. ISBN 978-0-19-852175-4. OCLC 17260831.
  23. ^ Kegl, J., A. Senghas and M. Coppola (1998). Creation through Contact: Sign language emergence and sign language change in Nicaragua. In M. DeGraff (ed.), Language Creation and Change: Creolization, Diachrony and Development. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
  24. ^ Lieberman, P.; Crelin, E. S. (1971). «On the speech of Neandertal Man». Linguistic Inquiry. 2: 203–22.
  25. ^ a b Arensburg, B.; Tillier, A. M.; Vandermeersch, B.; Duday, H.; Schepartz, L. A.; Rak, Y. (1989). «A Middle Palaeolithic human hyoid bone». Nature. 338 (6218): 758–760. Bibcode:1989Natur.338..758A. doi:10.1038/338758a0. PMID 2716823. S2CID 4309147.
  26. ^ Diller, Karl C.; Cann, Rebecca L. (2009). Rudolf P Botha; Chris Knight (eds.). Evidence Against a Genetic-Based Revolution in Language 50,000 Years Ago. The cradle of language. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 135–149. ISBN 978-0-19-954586-5. OCLC 804498749.
  27. ^ a b Henshilwood, Christopher Stuart; Dubreuil, Benoît (2009). Rudolf P Botha; Chris Knight (eds.). Reading the Artefacts: Gleaning Language Skills From the Middle Stone Age in Southern Africa. The cradle of language. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 41–61. ISBN 978-0-19-954586-5. OCLC 804498749.
  28. ^ Knight, Chris (2009). Rudolf P Botha; Chris Knight (eds.). Language, Ochre, and the Rule of Law. The cradle of language. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 281–303. ISBN 978-0-19-954586-5. OCLC 804498749.
  29. ^ a b Watts, Ian (2009). Rudolf P Botha; Chris Knight (eds.). Red Ochre, Body Painting, and Language: Interpreting the Blombos Ochre. The cradle of language. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 62–92. ISBN 978-0-19-954586-5. OCLC 804498749.
  30. ^ a b Arcadi, AC. (August 2000). «Vocal responsiveness in male wild chimpanzees: implications for the evolution of language». Journal of Human Evolution. 39 (2): 205–23. doi:10.1006/jhev.2000.0415. PMID 10968929. S2CID 7403772.
  31. ^ Johanna Nichols, 1998. The origin and dispersal of languages: Linguistic evidence. In Nina Jablonski and Leslie C. Aiello, eds., The Origin and Diversification of Language, pp. 127–70. (Memoirs of the California Academy of Sciences, 24.) San Francisco: California Academy of Sciences.
  32. ^ a b Perreault, C.; Mathew, S. (2012). «Dating the origin of language using phonemic diversity». PLOS ONE. 7 (4): e35289. Bibcode:2012PLoSO…735289P. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0035289. PMC 3338724. PMID 22558135.
  33. ^
    Botha, Rudolf P.; Knight, Chris (2009). The cradle of language. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954586-5. OCLC 804498749.
  34. ^ Darwin, C. (1871). «The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex, 2 vols. London: Murray, p. 56.
  35. ^ Müller, F. M. 1996 [1861]. The theoretical stage, and the origin of language. Lecture 9 from Lectures on the Science of Language. Reprinted in R. Harris (ed.), The Origin of Language. Bristol: Thoemmes Press, pp. 7–41.
  36. ^ Paget, R. 1930. Human speech: some observations, experiments, and conclusions as to the nature, origin, purpose and possible improvement of human speech. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  37. ^ Firth, J. R. 1964. The Tongues of Men and Speech. London: Oxford University Press, pp. 25–6.
  38. ^ Stam, J. H. 1976. Inquiries into the origins of language. New York: Harper and Row, p. 243-44.
  39. ^ Shah, Mustafa (January 2011). «Classical Islamic Discourse on the Origins of Language: Cultural Memory and the Defense of Orthodoxy» (PDF). Numen. 58 (2–3): 314–343. doi:10.1163/156852711X562335. S2CID 55165312 – via CORE.
  40. ^ Weiss, B. (1987). «‘Ilm al-wad’: An Introductory Account of a Later Muslim Philological Science». Arabica. 34 (1): 339–356. doi:10.1163/157005887X00054. S2CID 161187751.
  41. ^ Weiss, B. (1974). «Medieval Muslim discussions of the origin of language» (PDF). Zeitschrift der Deutschen Morgenländischen Gesellschaft. 124 (1): 33–41. doi:10.1163/156852711X562335. JSTOR 43370636. S2CID 55165312 – via JSTOR.
  42. ^ a b Zahavi, A. (May 1993). «The fallacy of conventional signalling». Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 340 (1292): 227–230. Bibcode:1993RSPTB.340..227Z. doi:10.1098/rstb.1993.0061. PMID 8101657.
  43. ^ Zahavi, A. and A. Zahavi 1997. The Handicap Principle: A Missing Piece in Darwin’s Puzzle. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780190284589
  44. ^ Smith, J.Maynard (1994). «Must reliable signals always be costly?». Animal Behaviour. 47 (5): 1115–1120. doi:10.1006/anbe.1994.1149. ISSN 0003-3472. S2CID 54274718.
  45. ^ a b Goodall, Jane (1986). The chimpanzees of Gombe : patterns of behavior. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-11649-8. OCLC 12550961.
  46. ^ Byrne, Richard W.; Whiten, Andrew. (1988). Machiavellian intelligence : social expertise and the evolution of intellect in monkeys, apes, and humans. Oxford: Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-852175-4. OCLC 17260831.
  47. ^ de Waal, Frans B. M. (2005). «Intentional Deception in Primates». Evolutionary Anthropology. 1 (3): 86–92. doi:10.1002/evan.1360010306. S2CID 221736130.
  48. ^ a b Power, Camilla (1998). James R Hurford; Michael Studdert-Kennedy; Chris Knight (eds.). Old wives’ tales: the gossip hypothesis and the reliability of cheap signals. Approaches to the evolution of language : social and cognitive base. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 111–129. ISBN 978-0-521-63964-4. OCLC 37742390.
  49. ^ a b Fitch, W. T. (2004). «Kin selection and ‘mother tongues’: a neglected component in language evolution» (PDF). In Ulrike Griebel; D Kimbrough Oller (eds.). Evolution of communication systems : a comparative approach. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. pp. 275–296. ISBN 978-0-262-15111-5. OCLC 845673575.
  50. ^ Hamilton, W. D. (1964). «The genetical evolution of social behaviour. I, II». Journal of Theoretical Biology. 7 (1): 1–52. Bibcode:1964JThBi…7….1H. doi:10.1016/0022-5193(64)90038-4. PMID 5875341.
  51. ^ Knight, Chris (13 November 2000). «Play as Precursor of Phonology and Syntax». The Evolutionary Emergence of Language. Cambridge University Press. pp. 99–120. doi:10.1017/cbo9780511606441.007. ISBN 978-0-521-78157-2. S2CID 56418139.
  52. ^ a b Tallerman, Maggie (2013). Rudolf P Botha; Martin Everaert (eds.). Kin selection, pedagogy and linguistic complexity: whence protolanguage?. The evolutionary emergence of language : evidence and inference. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. pp. 77–96. ISBN 978-0-19-965485-7. OCLC 856795812.
  53. ^ Trivers, R. L. (1971). «The evolution of reciprocal altruism». Quarterly Review of Biology. 46: 35–57. doi:10.1086/406755. S2CID 19027999.
  54. ^ Dessalles, Jean L. (1998). James R. Hurford; Michael Studdert-Kennedy; Chris Knight (eds.). Altruism, status and the origin of relevance. Approaches to the evolution of language : social and cognitive base. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 130–147. ISBN 978-0-521-63964-4. OCLC 37742390.
  55. ^ a b Dunbar, R. I. M. (1996). Grooming, gossip and the evolution of language. London: Faber and Faber. ISBN 9780571173969. OCLC 34546743.
  56. ^ von Heiseler; Till Nikolaus (2014). «Language evolved for storytelling in a super-fast evolution». In R. L. C. Cartmill (ed.). Evolution of Language. London: World Scientific. pp. 114–121.
  57. ^ Power, C. (1998). «Old wives’ tales: the gossip hypothesis and the reliability of cheap signals». In J. R. Hurford; M. Studdert Kennedy; C. Knight (eds.). Approaches to the Evolution of Language: Social and Cognitive Bases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 111 29.[clarification needed]
  58. ^ Lewis, Jerome (2009). Rudolf P Botha; Chris Knight (eds.). As Well as Words: Congo Pygmy Hunting, Mimicry, and Play. The cradle of language. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 236–256. ISBN 978-0-19-954586-5. OCLC 804498749.
  59. ^ Enfield, N. J. (2010). «Without social context?» (PDF). Science. 329 (5999): 1600–1601. Bibcode:2010Sci…329.1600E. doi:10.1126/science.1194229. hdl:11858/00-001M-0000-0012-C777-5. S2CID 143530707.
  60. ^ Steels, L. (2009). Rudolf P. Botha; Chris Knight (eds.). Is sociality a crucial prerequisite for the emergence of language?. The prehistory of language. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954587-2. OCLC 819189595.
  61. ^ Deacon, Terrence William (1997). The symbolic species : the co-evolution of language and the brain. New York: W.W. Norton. ISBN 978-0-393-03838-5. OCLC 807018262.
  62. ^ Rappaport, Roy A. (1979). Ecology, Meaning, and Religion. Richmond, Calif.: North Atlantic Books. pp. 201–211. ISBN 978-0-913028-54-4. OCLC 397893672.
  63. ^ Searle, J. R. 1996. The Construction of Social Reality. London: Penguin.
  64. ^ Durkheim, E. 1947 [1915]. «Origins of these beliefs». Chapter VII. In É. Durkheim, The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life: A study in religious sociology. Trans. J. W. Swain. Glencoe, Illinois: The Free Press, pp. 205–239.
  65. ^ Chomsky, Noam (2011). «Language and Other Cognitive Systems. What is Special About Language?». Language Learning and Development. 7 (4): 263–78. doi:10.1080/15475441.2011.584041. S2CID 122866773.
  66. ^ a b Chomsky, N. (2005). «Three factors in language design». Linguistic Inquiry. 36 (1): 1–22. doi:10.1162/0024389052993655. S2CID 14954986.
  67. ^ a b Uomini, Natalie Thaïs; Meyer, Georg Friedrich (30 August 2013). Petraglia, Michael D. (ed.). «Shared Brain Lateralization Patterns in Language and Acheulean Stone Tool Production: A Functional Transcranial Doppler Ultrasound Study». PLOS ONE. 8 (8): e72693. Bibcode:2013PLoSO…872693U. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0072693. ISSN 1932-6203. PMC 3758346. PMID 24023634.
  68. ^ Stout, Dietrich; Chaminade, Thierry (12 January 2012). «Stone tools, language and the brain in human evolution». Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 367 (1585): 75–87. doi:10.1098/rstb.2011.0099. PMC 3223784. PMID 22106428.
  69. ^ Putt, Shelby S. J.; Anwarzai, Zara; Holden, Chloe; Ruck, Lana; Schoenemann, P. Thomas (4 January 2022). «The evolution of combinatoriality and compositionality in hominid tool use: a comparative perspective». International Journal of Primatology. doi:10.1007/s10764-021-00267-7. ISSN 1573-8604. S2CID 245654206.
  70. ^ Barham, Lawrence; Everett, Daniel (June 2021). «Semiotics and the Origin of Language in the Lower Palaeolithic». Journal of Archaeological Method and Theory. 28 (2): 535–579. doi:10.1007/s10816-020-09480-9. ISSN 1072-5369. S2CID 225509049.
  71. ^ Arnauld, Antoine; Lancelot, Claude (1975) [First published 1660]. General and Rational Grammar : The Port-Royal Grammar. The Hague: Mouton. ISBN 902793004X.
  72. ^ a b Daneš, František (1987). «On Prague school functionalism in linguistics». In Dirven, R.; Fried, V. (eds.). Functionalism in Linguistics. John Benjamins. pp. 3–38. ISBN 9789027215246.
  73. ^ Aronoff, Mark (2017). «Darwinism tested by the science of language». In Bowern; Horn; Zanuttini (eds.). On Looking into Words (and Beyond): Structures, Relations, Analyses. SUNY Press. pp. 443–456. ISBN 978-3-946234-92-0. Retrieved 3 March 2020.
  74. ^ de Saussure, Ferdinand (1959) [First published 1916]. Course in general linguistics (PDF). New York: Philosophy Library. ISBN 9780231157278.
  75. ^ Lévi-Strauss, Claude (1987). Introduction to the work of Marcel Mauss. Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd. pp. 59–60. ISBN 0-7100-9066-8.
  76. ^ Hejl, P. M. (2013). «The importance of the concepts of ‘organism’ and ‘evolution’ in Emile Durkheim’s division of social labor and the influence of Herbert Spencer». In Maasen, Sabine; Mendelsohn, E.; Weingart, P. (eds.). Biology as Society, Society as Biology: Metaphors. Springer. pp. 155–191. ISBN 9789401106733.
  77. ^ Chomsky, N. (2004). Language and Mind: Current thoughts on ancient problems. Part I & Part II. In Lyle Jenkins (ed.), Variation and Universals in Biolinguistics. Amsterdam: Elsevier, pp. 379–405.
  78. ^ Berwick, Robert; Chomsky, Noam (2016). Why Only Us: Language and Evolution. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. ISBN 9780262034241. OCLC 934433881.
  79. ^ de Boer, Bart; Thompson, Bill; Ravignani, Andrea; Boeckx, Cedric (16 January 2020). «Evolutionary Dynamics Do Not Motivate a Single-Mutant Theory of Human Language». Scientific Reports. 10 (1): 451. Bibcode:2020NatSR..10..451D. doi:10.1038/s41598-019-57235-8. ISSN 2045-2322. PMC 6965110. PMID 31949223.
  80. ^ Martins, Pedro Tiago; Boeckx, Cedric (27 November 2019). «Language evolution and complexity considerations: The no half-Merge fallacy». PLOS Biology. 17 (11): e3000389. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.3000389. ISSN 1545-7885. PMC 6880980. PMID 31774810.
  81. ^
    Carnie, Andrew (2012). Syntax: A Generative Introduction (3rd ed.). West Sussex, UK: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 20–21. ISBN 978-0-470-65531-3.
  82. ^ Dediu, Dan; Levinson, Stephen C. (2013). «On the antiquity of language: the reinterpretation of Neandertal linguistic capacities and its consequences». Frontiers in Psychology. 4: 397. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00397. ISSN 1664-1078. PMC 3701805. PMID 23847571.
  83. ^ a b Vyshedskiy, Andrey (29 July 2019). «Language evolution to revolution: the leap from rich-vocabulary non-recursive communication system to recursive language 70,000 years ago was associated with acquisition of a novel component of imagination, called Prefrontal Synthesis, enabled by a mutation that slowed down the prefrontal cortex maturation simultaneously in two or more children – the Romulus and Remus hypothesis». Research Ideas and Outcomes. 5. doi:10.3897/rio.5.e38546. ISSN 2367-7163.
  84. ^ Bakker, Peter (July 1987). «Autonomous Languages of Twins». Acta Geneticae Medicae et Gemellologiae: Twin Research. 36 (2): 233–238. doi:10.1017/S0001566000004463. ISSN 0001-5660. PMID 3434134.
  85. ^ Amos W.; Hoffman J. I. (7 January 2010). «Evidence that two main bottleneck events shaped modern human genetic diversity». Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 277 (1678): 131–137. doi:10.1098/rspb.2009.1473. PMC 2842629. PMID 19812086.
  86. ^ Premack, David & Premack, Ann James. The Mind of an Ape, ISBN 0-393-01581-5.
  87. ^ Pollick, AS.; de Waal, FB. (May 2007). «Ape Gestures and Language Evolution». Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 104 (19): 8184–9. Bibcode:2007PNAS..104.8184P. doi:10.1073/pnas.0702624104. PMC 1876592. PMID 17470779.
  88. ^ Kimura, Doreen (1993). Neuromotor mechanisms in human communication. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-505492-7. OCLC 26396505.
  89. ^ Newman, A. J.; et al. (2002). «A Critical Period for Right Hemisphere Recruitment in American Sign Language Processing». Nature Neuroscience. 5 (1): 76–80. doi:10.1038/nn775. PMID 11753419. S2CID 2745545.
  90. ^ a b Arbib MA; Liebal, K; Pika, S (December 2008). «Primate vocalization, gesture, and the evolution of human language». Current Anthropology. 49 (6): 1053–63, discussion 1063–76. doi:10.1086/593015. PMID 19391445. S2CID 18832100.
  91. ^ Capone, Nina C.; McGregor, Karla K. (2004). «Gesture Development». Journal of Speech, Language, and Hearing Research. 47 (1): 173–86. doi:10.1044/1092-4388(2004/015). PMID 15072537. S2CID 7244799.
  92. ^ Ozçalişkan S; Goldin-Meadow S (July 2005). «Gesture is at the cutting edge of early language development». Cognition. 96 (3): B101–13. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2005.01.001. PMID 15996556. S2CID 206863317.
  93. ^ a b Rizzolatti, G. (2008). Giacomo Rizzolatti on the Evolution of Language. Retrieved from http://gocognitive.net/interviews/evolution-language-gestures[full citation needed]
  94. ^ a b Kendon, Adam (February 2017). «Reflections on the «gesture-first» hypothesis of language origins». Psychonomic Bulletin & Review. 24 (1): 163–170. doi:10.3758/s13423-016-1117-3. PMC 5325861. PMID 27439503.
  95. ^ Corballis, Michael C. (2002). Alison Wray (ed.). The transition to language. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 161–179. ISBN 978-0-19-925066-0. OCLC 48532303.
  96. ^ Knight, Chris (2006). Angelo Cangelosi; Andrew D M Smith; Kenny Smith (eds.). Language co-evolved with the rule of law (PDF). The evolution of language : proceedings of the 6th international conference (EVOLANG6), Rome, Italy, 12–15 April 200. Vol. 7. New Jersey: World Scientific. pp. 109–128. doi:10.1007/s11299-007-0039-1. ISBN 9789812566560. OCLC 70797781. S2CID 143877486.
  97. ^ Knight, Chris (2000). Chris Knight; Michael Studdert-Kennedy; James R Hurford (eds.). Play as precursor of phonology and syntax. The Evolutionary emergence of language : social function and the origins of linguistic for. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 99–1119. ISBN 978-0-521-78157-2. OCLC 807262339.
  98. ^ Kolb, Bryan & Ian Q. Whishaw (2003). Fundamentals of Human Neuropsychology (5th ed.). Worth Publishers. ISBN 978-0-7167-5300-1.
  99. ^ Sandler, Wendy; & Lillo-Martin, Diane. (2006). Sign Language and Linguistic Universals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  100. ^ Meena, Dr. Ram Lakhan (2021). Current Trends of Applied Linguistics. K.K. Publications. p. 48.
  101. ^ Agrawal, Pramod Kumar (1 June 2020). «Psychological Model of Phonosemantics». Journal of Psycholinguistic Research. 49 (3): 453–474. doi:10.1007/s10936-020-09701-y. ISSN 1573-6555. PMC 7253384. PMID 32323122.
  102. ^ Hewes, Gordon W.; Andrew, R. J.; Carini, Louis; Choe, Hackeny; Gardner, R. Allen; Kortlandt, A.; Krantz, Grover S.; McBride, Glen; Nottebohm, Fernando; Pfeiffer, John; Rumbaugh, Duane G.; Steklis, Horst D.; Raliegh, Michael J.; Stopa, Roman; Suzuki, Akira; Washburn, S. L.; Wescott, Roger W. (1973). «Primate Communication and the Gestural Origin of Language [and Comments and Reply]». Current Anthropology. 14 (1/2): 5–24. doi:10.1086/201401. JSTOR 2741093. S2CID 146288708.
  103. ^ McNeill, David; Bertenthal, Bennett; Cole, Jonathan; Gallagher, Shaun (April 2005). «Gesture-first, but no gestures?». Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 28 (2): 138–139. doi:10.1017/S0140525X05360031. S2CID 51753637.
  104. ^
  105. ^ Skoyles, John R., Gesture, Language Origins, and Right Handedness, Psycholoqy: 11,#24, 2000
  106. ^ a b Petrides, M.; Cadoret, G.; Mackey, S. (June 2005). «Orofacial somatomotor responses in the macaque monkey homologue of Broca’s area». Nature. 435 (7046): 1235–8. Bibcode:2005Natur.435.1235P. doi:10.1038/nature03628. PMID 15988526. S2CID 4397762.
  107. ^ Porter, RJ.; Lubker, JF. (September 1980). «Rapid reproduction of vowel-vowel sequences: evidence for a fast and direct acoustic-motoric linkage in speech». Journal of Speech and Hearing Research. 23 (3): 593–602. doi:10.1044/jshr.2303.593. PMID 7421161.
  108. ^ McCarthy, R.; Warrington, EK. (June 1984). «A two-route model of speech production. Evidence from aphasia». Brain. 107 (2): 463–85. doi:10.1093/brain/107.2.463. PMID 6722512.
  109. ^ McCarthy, RA.; Warrington, EK. (2001). «Repeating without semantics: surface dysphasia?». Neurocase. 7 (1): 77–87. doi:10.1093/neucas/7.1.77. PMID 11239078. S2CID 12988855.
  110. ^ Marslen-Wilson, W. (1973). «Linguistic structure and speech shadowing at very short latencies». Nature. 244 (5417): 522–523. Bibcode:1973Natur.244..522M. doi:10.1038/244522a0. PMID 4621131. S2CID 4220775.
  111. ^ Fay, WH.; Coleman, RO. (July 1977). «A human sound transducer/reproducer: temporal capabilities of a profoundly echolalic child». Brain and Language. 4 (3): 396–402. doi:10.1016/0093-934x(77)90034-7. PMID 907878. S2CID 29492873.
  112. ^ Schippers, MB; Roebroeck, A; Renken, R; Nanetti, L; Keysers, C (2010). «Mapping the Information flow from one brain to another during gestural communication». Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 107 (20): 9388–93. Bibcode:2010PNAS..107.9388S. doi:10.1073/pnas.1001791107. PMC 2889063. PMID 20439736.
  113. ^ Moro, Andrea (2008). The boundaries of Babel : the brain and the enigma of impossible language. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-13498-9. OCLC 804408004.[page needed]
  114. ^ a b Falk, D. (August 2004). «Prelinguistic evolution in early hominins: whence motherese?» (PDF). Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 27 (4): 491–503, discussion 503–83. doi:10.1017/s0140525x04000111. PMID 15773427. S2CID 39547572. Archived from the original (PDF) on 4 January 2014. Retrieved 4 January 2014.
  115. ^ Kaye, K. (1982). The Mental and Social Life of Babies. Univ. Chicago Press. pp. 186. ISBN 0226428486.
  116. ^ Poliva, Oren (20 September 2017). «From where to what: a neuroanatomically based evolutionary model of the emergence of speech in humans». F1000Research. 4: 67. doi:10.12688/f1000research.6175.3. ISSN 2046-1402. PMC 5600004. PMID 28928931.
  117. ^ Poliva, Oren (30 June 2016). «From Mimicry to Language: A Neuroanatomically Based Evolutionary Model of the Emergence of Vocal Language». Frontiers in Neuroscience. 10: 307. doi:10.3389/fnins.2016.00307. ISSN 1662-453X. PMC 4928493. PMID 27445676.
  118. ^ Scott, S. K. (1 December 2000). «Identification of a pathway for intelligible speech in the left temporal lobe». Brain. 123 (12): 2400–2406. doi:10.1093/brain/123.12.2400. ISSN 1460-2156. PMC 5630088. PMID 11099443.
  119. ^ Davis, Matthew H.; Johnsrude, Ingrid S. (15 April 2003). «Hierarchical Processing in Spoken Language Comprehension». The Journal of Neuroscience. 23 (8): 3423–3431. doi:10.1523/jneurosci.23-08-03423.2003. ISSN 0270-6474. PMC 6742313. PMID 12716950.
  120. ^ Petkov, Christopher I; Kayser, Christoph; Steudel, Thomas; Whittingstall, Kevin; Augath, Mark; Logothetis, Nikos K (10 February 2008). «A voice region in the monkey brain». Nature Neuroscience. 11 (3): 367–374. doi:10.1038/nn2043. ISSN 1097-6256. PMID 18264095. S2CID 5505773.
  121. ^ Buchsbaum, Bradley R.; Baldo, Juliana; Okada, Kayoko; Berman, Karen F.; Dronkers, Nina; D’Esposito, Mark; Hickok, Gregory (December 2011). «Conduction aphasia, sensory-motor integration, and phonological short-term memory – An aggregate analysis of lesion and fMRI data». Brain and Language. 119 (3): 119–128. doi:10.1016/j.bandl.2010.12.001. ISSN 0093-934X. PMC 3090694. PMID 21256582.
  122. ^ Warren, Jane E.; Wise, Richard J.S.; Warren, Jason D. (December 2005). «Sounds do-able: auditory–motor transformations and the posterior temporal plane». Trends in Neurosciences. 28 (12): 636–643. doi:10.1016/j.tins.2005.09.010. ISSN 0166-2236. PMID 16216346. S2CID 36678139.
  123. ^ Campbell, Ruth (12 March 2008). «The processing of audio-visual speech: empirical and neural bases». Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences. 363 (1493): 1001–1010. doi:10.1098/rstb.2007.2155. ISSN 0962-8436. PMC 2606792. PMID 17827105.
  124. ^ Kayser, Christoph; Petkov, Christopher I.; Logothetis, Nikos K. (December 2009). «Multisensory interactions in primate auditory cortex: fMRI and electrophysiology». Hearing Research. 258 (1–2): 80–88. doi:10.1016/j.heares.2009.02.011. ISSN 0378-5955. PMID 19269312. S2CID 31412246.
  125. ^ Hickok, Gregory; Buchsbaum, Bradley; Humphries, Colin; Muftuler, Tugan (1 July 2003). «Auditory–Motor Interaction Revealed by fMRI: Speech, Music, and Working Memory in Area Spt». Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience. 15 (5): 673–682. doi:10.1162/089892903322307393. ISSN 1530-8898. PMID 12965041.
  126. ^ Schwartz, M. F.; Faseyitan, O.; Kim, J.; Coslett, H. B. (20 November 2012). «The dorsal stream contribution to phonological retrieval in object naming». Brain. 135 (12): 3799–3814. doi:10.1093/brain/aws300. ISSN 0006-8950. PMC 3525060. PMID 23171662.
  127. ^ Gow, David W. (June 2012). «The cortical organization of lexical knowledge: A dual lexicon model of spoken language processing». Brain and Language. 121 (3): 273–288. doi:10.1016/j.bandl.2012.03.005. ISSN 0093-934X. PMC 3348354. PMID 22498237.
  128. ^ Buchsbaum, Bradley R.; D’Esposito, Mark (May 2008). «The Search for the Phonological Store: From Loop to Convolution». Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience. 20 (5): 762–778. doi:10.1162/jocn.2008.20501. ISSN 0898-929X. PMID 18201133. S2CID 17878480.
  129. ^ Lachaux, Jean-Philippe; Jerbi, Karim; Bertrand, Olivier; Minotti, Lorella; Hoffmann, Dominique; Schoendorff, Benjamin; Kahane, Philippe (31 October 2007). «A Blueprint for Real-Time Functional Mapping via Human Intracranial Recordings». PLOS ONE. 2 (10): e1094. Bibcode:2007PLoSO…2.1094L. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0001094. ISSN 1932-6203. PMC 2040217. PMID 17971857.
  130. ^ Jardri, Renaud; Houfflin-Debarge, Véronique; Delion, Pierre; Pruvo, Jean-Pierre; Thomas, Pierre; Pins, Delphine (April 2012). «Assessing fetal response to maternal speech using a noninvasive functional brain imaging technique». International Journal of Developmental Neuroscience. 30 (2): 159–161. doi:10.1016/j.ijdevneu.2011.11.002. ISSN 0736-5748. PMID 22123457. S2CID 2603226.
  131. ^ Petersen, M.; Beecher, M.; Zoloth; Moody, D.; Stebbins, W. (20 October 1978). «Neural lateralization of species-specific vocalizations by Japanese macaques (Macaca fuscata)». Science. 202 (4365): 324–327. Bibcode:1978Sci…202..324P. doi:10.1126/science.99817. ISSN 0036-8075. PMID 99817.
  132. ^ Heffner, H.; Heffner, R. (5 October 1984). «Temporal lobe lesions and perception of species-specific vocalizations by macaques». Science. 226 (4670): 75–76. Bibcode:1984Sci…226…75H. doi:10.1126/science.6474192. ISSN 0036-8075. PMID 6474192.
  133. ^ Shu, W.; Cho, J. Y.; Jiang, Y.; Zhang, M.; Weisz, D.; Elder, G. A.; Schmeidler, J.; De Gasperi, R.; Sosa, M. A. G. (27 June 2005). «Altered ultrasonic vocalization in mice with a disruption in the Foxp2 gene». Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 102 (27): 9643–9648. Bibcode:2005PNAS..102.9643S. doi:10.1073/pnas.0503739102. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 1160518. PMID 15983371.
  134. ^ Sia, G. M.; Clem, R. L.; Huganir, R. L. (31 October 2013). «The Human Language-Associated Gene SRPX2 Regulates Synapse Formation and Vocalization in Mice». Science. 342 (6161): 987–991. Bibcode:2013Sci…342..987S. doi:10.1126/science.1245079. ISSN 0036-8075. PMC 3903157. PMID 24179158.
  135. ^ Sperber, D. and D. Wilson 1986. Relevance. Communication and cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.
  136. ^ a b c Deutscher, Guy (2005). The unfolding of language : an evolutionary tour of mankind’s greatest invention. New York: Metropolitan Books. ISBN 978-0-8050-7907-4. OCLC 57311730.
  137. ^ Hopper, P. J. 1998. Emergent grammar. In M. Tomasello (ed.), The New Psychology of Language. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, 155–175.
  138. ^ a b c Heine, Bernd; Kuteva, Tania (2007). The genesis of grammar : a reconstructio. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-922777-8. OCLC 849464326.
  139. ^ a b Lakoff, G. and M. Johnson 1980. Metaphors We Live By. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  140. ^ a b Heine, Bernd; Kuteva, Tania (2012). Maggie Tallerman; Kathleen R. Gibson (eds.). Grammaticalization theory as a tool for reconstructing language evolution. The Oxford handbook of language evolution. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 512–527. ISBN 978-0-19-954111-9. OCLC 724665645.
  141. ^ Cheney, Dorothy L.; Seyfarth, Robert M. (2005). «Constraints and preadaptations in the earliest stages of language evolution» (PDF). The Linguistic Review. 22 (2–4): 135–59. doi:10.1515/tlir.2005.22.2-4.135. S2CID 18939193.
  142. ^ Maynard Smith, John; Harper, David (2003). Animal signals. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-852684-1. OCLC 54460090.
  143. ^ Davidson, R. D. 1979. What metaphors mean. In S. Sacks (ed.), On Metaphor. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 29–45.
  144. ^ Lakoff, G. and R. Núñez 2000. Where mathematics comes from. New York: Basic Books.
  145. ^ Gallup, GG Jr. (1970). «Chimpanzees: Self recognition». Science. 167 (3914): 86–87. Bibcode:1970Sci…167…86G. doi:10.1126/science.167.3914.86. PMID 4982211. S2CID 145295899.
  146. ^ Mitchell, R.W. (1995). «Evidence of dolphin self-recognition and the difficulties of interpretation». Consciousness and Cognition. 4 (2): 229–234. doi:10.1006/ccog.1995.1029. PMID 8521261. S2CID 45507064.
  147. ^ Ko, Kwang Hyun (2016). «Origins of human intelligence: The chain of tool-making and brain evolution» (PDF). Anthropological Notebooks. 22 (1): 5–22.
  148. ^ a b Soma, M.; Hiraiwa-Hasegawa, M.; Okanoya, K. (2009). «Early ontogenetic effects on song quality in the Bengalese finch (Lonchura striata var. domestica): laying order, sibling competition and song syntax». Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology. 63 (3): 363–370. doi:10.1007/s00265-008-0670-9. S2CID 23137306.
  149. ^ Graham Ritchie; Simon Kirby (2005). «Selection, domestication, and the emergence of learned communication systems» (PDF). Second International Symposium on the Emergence and Evolution of Linguistic Communication. Archived from the original (PDF) on 21 January 2012.
  150. ^ MacNeilage, P. 1998. Evolution of the mechanism of language output: comparative neurobiology of vocal and manual communication. In J. R. Hurford, M. Studdert Kennedy and C. Knight (eds), Approaches to the Evolution of Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 222 41[clarify].
  151. ^ a b c d Hauser, M. D.; Chomsky, N.; Fitch, W. T. (November 2002). «The faculty of language: what is it, who has it, and how did it evolve?» (PDF). Science. 298 (5598): 1569–1579. doi:10.1126/science.298.5598.1569. PMID 12446899. Archived from the original (PDF) on 28 December 2013.
  152. ^ Everett, Daniel L. (2005). «Cultural Constraints on Grammar and Cognition in Piraha Another Look at the Design Features of Human Language» (PDF). Current Anthropology. 46 (4): 621–646. doi:10.1086/431525. hdl:2066/41103. S2CID 2223235.
  153. ^ Zhordania, I. M. (2006). Who asked the first question : the origins of human choral singing, intelligence, language and speech. Tbilisi, Georgia: Logos Tbilisi Ivane Javakhishvili State University. ISBN 9789994031818. OCLC 224993377.
  154. ^ Savage-Rumbaugh, E. Sue; Murphy, Jeannine; Sevcik, Rose A.; Brakke, Karen E.; Williams, Shelly L.; Rumbaugh, Duane M.; Bates, Elizabeth (1993). «Language Comprehension in Ape and Child». Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development. 58 (3/4): i–252. doi:10.2307/1166068. JSTOR 1166068. PMID 8366872.
  155. ^ Bolinger, Dwight L. (Editor) 1972. Intonation. Selected Readings. Harmondsworth: Penguin, p. 314.
  156. ^ Cruttenden, Alan (1986). Intonation. Cambridge [Cambridgeshire]; New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 169–174. ISBN 978-0-521-26028-2. OCLC 12103838.
  157. ^ Tomasello, Michael; Call, Josep; Hare, Brian (April 2003). «Chimpanzees understand psychological states – the question is which ones and to what extent». Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 7 (4): 153–156. doi:10.1016/S1364-6613(03)00035-4. PMID 12691762. S2CID 3390980.
  158. ^ Hale, Courtney Melinda; Tager-Flusberg, Helen (June 2003). «The influence of language on theory of mind: a training study». Developmental Science. 6 (3): 346–359. doi:10.1111/1467-7687.00289. PMC 1350918. PMID 16467908.
  159. ^ Matsuzawa, Tetsuro (1985). «Use of numbers by a chimpanzee». Nature. 315 (6014): 57–59. Bibcode:1985Natur.315…57M. doi:10.1038/315057a0. PMID 3990808. S2CID 4361089.
  160. ^ Cheung, Pierina; Rubenson, Miriam; Barner, David (February 2017). «To infinity and beyond: Children generalize the successor function to all possible numbers years after learning to count». Cognitive Psychology. 92: 22–36. doi:10.1016/j.cogpsych.2016.11.002. PMID 27889550. S2CID 206867905 – via Science Direct.
  161. ^ Carey, Susan (2001). «Cognitive Foundations of Arithmetic: Evolution and Ontogenisis» (PDF). Mind and Language. 16 (1): 37–55. doi:10.1111/1468-0017.00155. Archived from the original (PDF) on 25 July 2013. Retrieved 13 January 2014.
  162. ^ Hockett, Charles F. (1960). «The Origin of Speech» (PDF). Scientific American. 203 (3): 88–96. Bibcode:1960SciAm.203c..88H. doi:10.1038/scientificamerican0960-88. PMID 14402211. Archived from the original (PDF) on 6 January 2014. Retrieved 6 January 2014.
  163. ^ Schlenker, Philippe; Chemla, Emmanuel; Arnold, Kate; Lemasson, Alban; Ouattara, Karim; Keenan, Sumir; Stephan, Claudia; Ryder, Robin; Zuberbühler, Klaus (December 2014). «Monkey semantics: two ‘dialects’ of Campbell’s monkey alarm calls». Linguistics and Philosophy. 37 (6): 439–501. doi:10.1007/s10988-014-9155-7. S2CID 3428900.
  164. ^ a b c Diamond, Jared M. (1992). «Bridges to human language». The third chimpanzee : the evolution and future of the human animal. New York: HarperCollins. pp. 141–167. ISBN 978-0-06-018307-3. OCLC 24246928.
  165. ^ Savage-Rumbaugh, E. Sue; Lewin, Roger. (1994). Kanzi : the ape at the brink of the human mind. New York: Wiley. ISBN 978-0-471-58591-6. OCLC 30112573.
  166. ^ Savage-Rumbaugh, E. Sue; Shanker, Stuart.; Taylor, Talbot J. (1998). Apes, language, and the human mind. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-510986-3. OCLC 38566026.
  167. ^ Freeman, Scott; Jon C. Herron., Evolutionary Analysis (4th ed.), Pearson Education, Inc. (2007), ISBN 0-13-227584-8 pages 789–90
  168. ^ Seyfarth, Robert M.; Cheney, Dorothy L.; Marler, Peter (1980). «Vervet monkey alarm calls: Semantic communication in a free-ranging primate». Animal Behaviour. 28 (4): 1070–1094. doi:10.1016/S0003-3472(80)80097-2. S2CID 53165940.
  169. ^ Arnold, Kate; Zuberbühler, Klaus (2006). «Language evolution: Semantic combinations in primate calls». Nature. 441 (7091): 303. Bibcode:2006Natur.441..303A. doi:10.1038/441303a. PMID 16710411. S2CID 4413635.
  170. ^ Wade, Nicholas (23 May 2006). «Nigerian Monkeys Drop Hints on Language Origin». The New York Times. Retrieved 9 September 2007.
  171. ^ Gibbons, Christopher M. (2007). The referentiality of chimpanzee vocal signaling: behavioral and acoustic analysis of food barks (Thesis). Ohio State University.
  172. ^ Slocombe, Katie E.; Zuberbühler, Klaus (2005). «Functionally Referential Communication in a Chimpanzee» (PDF). Current Biology. 15 (19): 1779–1784. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2005.08.068. PMID 16213827. S2CID 6774592.
  173. ^ a b Clark, Gary; Henneberg, Maciej (2017). «Ardipithecus ramidus and the evolution of language and singing: An early origin for hominin vocal capability». HOMO. 68 (2): 101–121. doi:10.1016/j.jchb.2017.03.001. PMID 28363458.
  174. ^ Aronoff, Mark; Rees-Miller, Janie. (2001). The handbook of linguistics. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell Publishers. ISBN 0631204970. OCLC 43115110.
  175. ^ Fitch, W.Tecumseh (2000). «The evolution of speech: a comparative review». Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 4 (7): 258–267. doi:10.1016/S1364-6613(00)01494-7. PMID 10859570. S2CID 14706592.
  176. ^ Ohala, John J. (10 September 1987). «Experimental Phonology». Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society. 13: 207. doi:10.3765/bls.v13i0.1803. ISSN 2377-1666.
  177. ^ «APA Upgrades APA PsycNET Content Delivery Platform». American Psychological Association. 2017. doi:10.1037/e500792018-001. [full citation needed]
  178. ^ a b Mithen, Steven J. (2006). The singing neanderthals : the origins of music, language, mind, and body. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-02192-1. OCLC 62090869.
  179. ^ Barham, Lawrence; Everett, Daniel (1 June 2021). «Semiotics and the Origin of Language in the Lower Palaeolithic». Journal of Archaeological Method and Theory. 28 (2): 535–579. doi:10.1007/s10816-020-09480-9. ISSN 1573-7764. S2CID 225509049.
  180. ^ Vicari, Giuseppe; Adenzato, Mauro (May 2014). «Is recursion language-specific? Evidence of recursive mechanisms in the structure of intentional action». Consciousness and Cognition. 26: 169–188. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2014.03.010. hdl:2318/154505. PMID 24762973. S2CID 206955548.
  181. ^ Corballis, Michael (2007). «The Uniqueness of Human Recursive Thinking». American Scientist. 95 (3): 240. doi:10.1511/2007.65.240. ISSN 0003-0996.
  182. ^ Everett, Daniel L. (August 2005). «Cultural Constraints on Grammar and Cognition in Pirahã: Another Look at the Design Features of Human Language». Current Anthropology. 46 (4): 621–646. doi:10.1086/431525. hdl:2066/41103. ISSN 0011-3204. S2CID 2223235.
  183. ^ Arensburg, B.; Schepartz, L.A.; Tillier, A.M.; Vandermeersch, B.; Rak, Y. (October 1990). «A reappraisal of the anatomical basis for speech in Middle Palaeolithic hominids». American Journal of Physical Anthropology. 83 (2): 137–46. doi:10.1002/ajpa.1330830202. PMID 2248373.
  184. ^ D’Anastasio, R.; Wroe, S.; Tuniz, C.; Mancini, L.; Cesana, D.T.; Dreossi, D.; Ravichandiran, M.; Attard, M.; et al. (2013). «Micro-biomechanics of the kebara 2 hyoid and its implications for speech in neanderthals». PLOS ONE. 8 (12): e82261. Bibcode:2013PLoSO…882261D. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0082261. PMC 3867335. PMID 24367509.
  185. ^ Jungers, W.L.; Pokempner, A.A.; Kay, R.F.; Cartmill, M. (August 2003). «Hypoglossal canal size in living hominoids and the evolution of human speech» (PDF). Human Biology. 75 (4): 473–84. doi:10.1353/hub.2003.0057. PMID 14655872. S2CID 30777048. Archived from the original (PDF) on 12 June 2007.
  186. ^ DeGusta, D.; Gilbert, W.H.; Turner, S.P. (February 1999). «Hypoglossal canal size and hominid speech». Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 96 (4): 1800–4. Bibcode:1999PNAS…96.1800D. doi:10.1073/pnas.96.4.1800. PMC 15600. PMID 9990105.
  187. ^ Johansson, Sverker (April 2006). «Constraining the Time When Language Evolved» (PDF). Evolution of Language: Sixth International Conference, Rome: 152–159. doi:10.1142/9789812774262_0020. ISBN 9789812566560. Archived from the original (PDF) on 15 October 2006. Retrieved 10 September 2007.
  188. ^ Houghton, P. (February 1993). «Neandertal supralaryngeal vocal tract». American Journal of Physical Anthropology. 90 (2): 139–46. doi:10.1002/ajpa.1330900202. PMID 8430750.
  189. ^ Boë, Louis-Jean; Maeda, Shinji; Heim, Jean-Louis (1999). «Neandertal man was not morphologically handicapped for speech». Evolution of Communication. 3 (1): 49–77. doi:10.1075/eoc.3.1.05boe.
  190. ^ de Boer, Bart (2017). «Evolution of speech and evolution of language». Psychonomic Bulletin & Review. 24 (1): 158–162. doi:10.3758/s13423-016-1130-6. ISSN 1069-9384.
  191. ^ Klarreich, E. (2004). «Biography of Richard G. Klein». Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 101 (16): 5705–7. Bibcode:2004PNAS..101.5705K. doi:10.1073/pnas.0402190101. PMC 395972. PMID 15079069.
  192. ^ Klein, Richard G. «Three Distinct Human Populations». Biological and Behavioral Origins of Modern Humans. Access Excellence @ The National Health Museum. Retrieved 10 September 2007.
  193. ^ Marwick, Ben (2003). «Pleistocene Exchange Networks as Evidence for the Evolution of Language». Cambridge Archaeological Journal. 13: 67–81. doi:10.1017/S0959774303000040. hdl:1885/42089. S2CID 15514627.
  194. ^ a b Conde-Valverde, Mercedes; Martínez, Ignacio; Quam, Rolf M.; Rosa, Manuel; Velez, Alex D.; Lorenzo, Carlos; Jarabo, Pilar; Bermúdez de Castro, José María; Carbonell, Eudald; Arsuaga, Juan Luis (1 March 2021). «Neanderthals and Homo sapiens had similar auditory and speech capacities». Nature Ecology & Evolution. 5 (5): 609–615. doi:10.1038/s41559-021-01391-6. ISSN 2397-334X. PMID 33649543. S2CID 232090739.
  195. ^ Fleagle, John G.; Assefa, Zelalem; Brown, Francis H.; Shea, John J. (2008). «Paleoanthropology of the Kibish Formation, southern Ethiopia: Introduction». Journal of Human Evolution. 55 (3): 360–5. doi:10.1016/j.jhevol.2008.05.007. PMID 18617219.
  196. ^ Henshilwood, C. S.; d’Errico, F.; Yates, R.; Jacobs, Z.; Tribolo, C.; Duller, G. A. T.; Mercier, N.; Sealy, J. C.; Valladas, H.; Watts, I.; Wintle, A. G. (2002). «Emergence of modern human behavior: Middle Stone Age engravings from South Africa». Science. 295 (5558): 1278–1280. Bibcode:2002Sci…295.1278H. doi:10.1126/science.1067575. PMID 11786608. S2CID 31169551.
  197. ^ Minkel, J. R. (18 July 2007). «Skulls Add to «Out of Africa» Theory of Human Origins: Pattern of skull variation bolsters the case that humans took over from earlier species». Scientific American.com. Retrieved 9 September 2007.
  198. ^ Chris Stringer, 2011. The Origin of Our Species. London: Penguin.
  199. ^ Fitch, WT. (2000). «The phonetic potential of nonhuman vocal tracts: comparative cineradiographic observations of vocalizing animals». Phonetica. 57 (2–4): 205–18. doi:10.1159/000028474. PMID 10992141. S2CID 202652500.
  200. ^ Fitch, WT.; Reby, D. (August 2001). «The descended larynx is not uniquely human». Proceedings of the Royal Society B. 268 (1477): 1669–75. doi:10.1098/rspb.2001.1704. PMC 1088793. PMID 11506679.
  201. ^ Weissengruber, GE.; Forstenpointner, G.; Peters, G.; Kübber-Heiss, A.; Fitch, WT. (September 2002). «Hyoid apparatus and pharynx in the lion (Panthera leo), jaguar (Panthera onca), tiger (Panthera tigris), cheetah (Acinonyxjubatus) and domestic cat (Felis silvestris f. catus)». Journal of Anatomy. 201 (3): 195–209. doi:10.1046/j.1469-7580.2002.00088.x. PMC 1570911. PMID 12363272.
  202. ^ Lieberman, Philip (2007). «The Evolution of Human Speech: Its Anatomical and Neural Bases» (PDF). Current Anthropology. 48 (1): 39–66. doi:10.1086/509092. S2CID 28651524.
  203. ^ Nishimura, T.; Mikami, A.; Suzuki, J.; Matsuzawa, T. (September 2006). «Descent of the hyoid in chimpanzees: evolution of face flattening and speech». Journal of Human Evolution. 51 (3): 244–54. doi:10.1016/j.jhevol.2006.03.005. PMID 16730049.
  204. ^ Lieberman, Philip; McCarthy, Robert C.; Strait, David (2006). «The Recent Origin of Human Speech». The Journal of the Acoustical Society of America. 119 (5): 3441. Bibcode:2006ASAJ..119.3441L. doi:10.1121/1.4786937.
  205. ^ M. Clegg 2001. The Comparative Anatomy and Evolution of the Human Vocal Tract Unpublished thesis, University of London.
  206. ^ John J. Ohala, 2000. The irrelevance of the lowered larynx in modern Man for the development of speech. Paris, ENST: The Evolution of Language, pp. 171–172.
  207. ^ Barel, Efrat; Tzischinsky, Orna (June 2018). «Age and Sex Differences in Verbal and Visuospatial Abilities». Advances in Cognitive Psychology. 2 (14): 51–61. doi:10.5709/acp-0238-x. PMC 7186802. PMID 32362962.
  208. ^ Fitch, W. T. (2002). Comparative vocal production and the evolution of speech: Reinterpreting the descent of the larynx. In A. Wray (ed.), The Transition to Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 21–45.
  209. ^ Turner, P. and Russell-Coulter, C. (2001) Dictionary of Ancient Deities (Oxford: OUP)
  210. ^ Pennock, Robert T. (2000). Tower of Babel: The Evidence against the New Creationism. Bradford Books. ISBN 9780262661652.
  211. ^ Lindsay, Robert (1728). The history of Scotland: from 21 February 1436. to March, 1565. In which are contained accounts of many remarkable passages altogether differing from our other historians; and many facts are related, either concealed by some, or omitted by others. Baskett and company. p. 104.
  212. ^ Meena, Dr Ram Lakhan (3 August 2021). Current Trends of Applied Linguistics. K.K. Publications. Retrieved 9 January 2022.

Further readingEdit

  • Allott, Robin. (1989). The Motor Theory of Language Origin. Sussex, England: Book Guild. ISBN 978-0-86332-359-1. OCLC 21874255.
  • Armstrong, David F.; Stokoe, William C.; Wilcox, Sherman E. (1995). Gesture and the Nature of Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-52-146772-8.
  • Botha, Rudolf P; Everaert, Martin, eds. (2013). The Evolutionary Emergence of Language: Evidence and Inference. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-965484-0. OCLC 828055639.
  • Botha, Rudolf P.; Knight, Chris (2009). The Prehistory of Language. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954587-2. OCLC 819189595.
  • Burling, Robbins (2005). The Talking Ape: How Language Evolved. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-927940-1. OCLC 750809912.
  • Cangelosi, Angelo; Greco, Alberto; Harnad, Stevan (2002). Angelo Cangelosi; Domenico Parisi (eds.). Symbol Grounding and the Symbolic Theft Hypothesis. Simulating the Evolution of Language. London; New York: Springer. ISBN 978-1-85233-428-4. OCLC 47824669.
  • Corballis, Michael C. (2002). From Hand to Mouth: The Origins of Language. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-08803-7. OCLC 469431753.
  • Crystal, David (1997). The Cambridge Encyclopedia of Language. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-55967-6. OCLC 34704876.
  • de Grolier, E. (ed.), 1983. The Origin and Evolution of Language. Paris: Harwood Academic Publishers.
  • Dessalles, J-L., 2007. Why We Talk: The Evolutionary Origins of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0199563463
  • Dor, Dan; Knight, Chris; Lewis, Jerome (2015). The Social Origins of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-966533-4.
  • Dunbar, R. I. M. (Robin Ian MacDonald); Knight, Chris; Power, Camilla (1999). The Evolution of Culture: An Interdisciplinary View. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. ISBN 978-0-7486-1076-1. OCLC 807340111.
  • Everett, Daniel L. (2017). How Language Began: The Story of Humanity’s Greatest Invention. New York: Liveright. ISBN 978-0871407955.
  • Fitch, W. Tecumseh (2010). The Evolution of Language. Cambridge: Cambridge. ISBN 978-0-521-67736-3. OCLC 428024376.
  • Givón, Talmy; Malle, Bertram F (2002). The Evolution of Language out of Pre-Language. Amsterdam; Philadelphia: J. Benjamins Pub. ISBN 978-1-58811-237-8. OCLC 223393453.
  • Harnad, Stevan R. (1976). Steklis, Horst D.; Lancaster, Jane (eds.). Origins and Evolution of Language and Speech. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, v. 280. New York: New York Academy of Sciences. ISBN 0-89072-026-6. OCLC 2493424.
  • Hillert, Dieter (2014). The Nature of Language: Evolution, Paradigms and Circuits. New York: Springer Nature. ISBN 978-1-4939-0609-3.
  • Hurford, James R (1990). I. M. Roca (ed.). Nativist and Functional Explanations in Language Acquisition (PDF). Logical issues in language acquisition. Dordrecht, Holland Providence, R.I: Foris Publications. ISBN 9789067655064. OCLC 832515162.
  • Hurford, James R. (2007). The Origins of Meaning: Language in the Light of Evolution. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-920785-5. OCLC 263645256.
  • Hurford, James R.; Studdert-Kennedy, Michael.; Knight, Chris (1998). Approaches to the Evolution of Language: Social and Cognitive Bases. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-63964-4. OCLC 37742390.
  • Kenneally, Christine. (2007). The First Word: The Search for the Origins of Language. New York: Viking. ISBN 978-0-670-03490-1. OCLC 80460757.
  • Knight, Chris (2016). «Puzzles and Mysteries in the Origin of Language» (PDF). Language and Communication. 50: 12–21. doi:10.1016/j.langcom.2016.09.002.
  • Knight, Chris; Studdert-Kennedy, Michael.; Hurford, James R. (2000). The Evolutionary Emergence of Language: Social Function and the Origins of Linguistic Form. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-78157-2. OCLC 807262339.
  • Komarova, Natalia L. (2006). L E Grinin; Victor C De Munck; A V Korotaev; Rossiĭskiĭ gosudarstvennyĭ gumanitarnyĭ universitet. (eds.). Language and Mathematics: An evolutionary model of grammatical communication. History and mathematics. Analyzing and modeling global development. [Moskva]: URSS. pp. 164–179. ISBN 978-5-484-01001-1. OCLC 182730511.
  • Lenneberg, E. H. 1967. Biological Foundations of Language. New York: Wiley. ISBN 9780471526261
  • Leroi-Gourhan, A. 1993. Gesture and Speech. Trans. A. Bostock Berger. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. ISBN 9780262121736
  • Lieberman, Philip. (1991). Uniquely Human: The Evolution of Speech, Thought, and Selfless Behavior. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-92182-5. OCLC 21764294.
  • Lieberman, P. (2007). «The Evolution of Human Speech: Its Anatomical and Neural Bases» (PDF). Current Anthropology. 48 (1): 39–66. doi:10.1086/509092. S2CID 28651524.
  • Lieberman, Philip. (2006). Toward an Evolutionary Biology of Language. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-02184-6. OCLC 62766735.
  • Logan, Robert K. 2007. The Extended Mind: The Emergence of Language, the Human Mind and Culture. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. ISBN 9781442691803
  • MacNeilage, P. 2008. The Origin of Speech. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780199581580
  • Mazlumyan, Victoria 2008. Origins of Language and Thought. ISBN 0977391515.
  • Mithen, Stephen 2006. The Singing Neanderthals: The Origins of Music, Language, Mind and Body. ISBN 9780753820513
  • Pinker, Steven (2007). The Language Instinct: How the Mind Creates Language. New York: HarperPerennial ModernClassics. ISBN 9780061336461. OCLC 672454779.
  • Tomasello, M. 2008. Origins of Human Communication. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. ISBN 9780262261203

External linksEdit

Look up glottogony in Wiktionary, the free dictionary.

  • Origin of Language – Givens, David B.
  • Behavioral and Biological Origins of Modern Humans – Klein, Richard G.
  • The Origin of Language – Vajda, Edward
  • First Language Acquisition – Vajda, Edward
  • Speaking in Tongues: The History of Language Archived 21 February 2014 at the Wayback Machine
  • Decoding Chomsky: Science and revolutionary politics – Chris Knight

English[edit]

Pronunciation[edit]

  • enPR: lăngʹgwĭj, IPA(key): /ˈlæŋɡwɪd͡ʒ/
    • (General American, Canada) IPA(key): (see /æ/ raising) [ˈleɪŋɡwɪd͡ʒ]
  • Rhymes: -æŋɡwɪdʒ
  • Hyphenation: lan‧guage

Etymology 1[edit]

From Middle English langage, language, from Old French language, from Vulgar Latin *linguāticum, from Latin lingua (tongue, speech, language), from Old Latin dingua (tongue), from Proto-Indo-European *dn̥ǵʰwéh₂s (tongue, speech, language). Displaced native Old English ġeþēode.

Noun[edit]

language (countable and uncountable, plural languages)

Examples

The English Wiktionary uses the English language to define words from all of the world’s languages.


This person is saying «hello» in American sign language.

  1. (countable) A body of words, and set of methods of combining them (called a grammar), understood by a community and used as a form of communication.

    The English language and the German language are related.

    Deaf and mute people communicate using languages like ASL.

    • 1867, Report on the Systems of Deaf-Mute Instruction pursued in Europe, quoted in 1983 in History of the College for the Deaf, 1857-1907 →ISBN, page 240:
      Hence the natural language of the mute is, in schools of this class, suppressed as soon and as far as possible, and its existence as a language, capable of being made the reliable and precise vehicle for the widest range of thought, is ignored.
    • 2000, Geary Hobson, The Last of the Ofos, →ISBN, page 113:

      Mr. Darko, generally acknowledged to be the last surviving member of the Ofo Tribe, was also the last remaining speaker of the tribe’s language.

  2. (uncountable) The ability to communicate using words.

    the gift of language

    • 1981, William Irwin Thompson, The Time Falling Bodies Take to Light: Mythology, Sexuality and the Origins of Culture, London: Rider/Hutchinson & Co., page 15:

      Language is the articulation of the limited to express the unlimited; it is the ultimate mystery which is the image of God, for in breaking up infinity to create finite beings, God has found a way to let the limited being yet be a reflection of His unlimited Being.

  3. (uncountable) A sublanguage: the slang of a particular community or jargon of a particular specialist field.
    • 1892, Walter Besant, “Prologue: Who is Edmund Gray?”, in The Ivory Gate [], New York, N.Y.: Harper & Brothers, [], →OCLC:

      Thus, when he drew up instructions in lawyer language, he expressed the important words by an initial, a medial, or a final consonant, and made scratches for all the words between; his clerks, however, understood him very well.

    • 1991, Stephen Fry, The Liar, London: Heinemann, →OCLC, page 35:

      And ‘blubbing’… Blubbing went out with ‘decent’ and ‘ripping’. Mind you, not a bad new language to start up. Nineteen-twenties schoolboy slang could be due for a revival.

    legal language;   the language of chemistry

  4. (countable, uncountable, figurative) The expression of thought (the communication of meaning) in a specified way; that which communicates something, as language does.

    body language;   the language of the eyes

    • 2001, Eugene C. Kennedy; Sara C. Charles, On Becoming a Counselor, →ISBN:

      A tale about themselves [is] told by people with help from the universal languages of their eyes, their hands, and even their shirting feet.

    • 2005, Sean Dooley, The Big Twitch, Sydney: Allen and Unwin, page 231:

      Birding had become like that for me. It is a language that, once learnt, I have been unable to unlearn.

  5. (countable, uncountable) A body of sounds, signs and/or signals by which animals communicate, and by which plants are sometimes also thought to communicate.
    • 1983, The Listener, volume 110, page 14:
      A more likely hypothesis was that the attacked leaves were transmitting some airborne chemical signal to sound the alarm, rather like insects sending out warnings [] But this is the first time that a plant-to-plant language has been detected.
    • 2009, Animals in Translation, page 274:
      Prairie dogs use their language to refer to real dangers in the real world, so it definitely has meaning.
  6. (computing, countable) A computer language; a machine language.
    • 2015, Kent D. Lee, Foundations of Programming Languages, →ISBN, page 94:

      In fact pointers are called references in these languages to distinguish them from pointers in languages like C and C++.

  7. (uncountable) Manner of expression.
    • 1782, William Cowper, Hope
      Their language simple, as their manners meek, []
  8. (uncountable) The particular words used in a speech or a passage of text.

    The language used in the law does not permit any other interpretation.

    The language he used to talk to me was obscene.

  9. (uncountable) Profanity.
    • 1978, James Carroll, Mortal Friends, →ISBN, page 500:

      «Where the hell is Horace?» ¶ «There he is. He’s coming. You shouldn’t use language

Synonyms[edit]
  • (form of communication): see Thesaurus:language
  • (vocabulary of a particular field): see Thesaurus:jargon
  • (computer language): computer language, programming language, machine language
  • (particular words used): see Thesaurus:wording
Hypernyms[edit]
  • medium
Hyponyms[edit]
  • See Category:en:Languages
  • artificial language
  • auxiliary language
  • bad language
  • body language
  • common language
  • computer/computing language
  • constructed language
  • corpus language
  • dead language
  • endangered language
  • engineered language
  • everyday language
  • experimental language
  • extinct language
  • foreign language
  • formal language
  • foul language
  • global language
  • hardware description language
  • indigenous language
  • international language
  • link language
  • literary language
  • living language
  • logical language
  • machine language
  • main language
  • mathematical language
  • meta language
  • metaphorical language
  • minority language
  • modern language
  • multi-paradigm language
  • natural language
  • object language
  • pattern language
  • philosophical language
  • phonetic language
  • planned language
  • principal language
  • private language
  • programming language
  • scripting language
  • secular language
  • sign language
  • spoken language
  • standard language
  • subject-oriented language
  • target language
  • universal language
  • vehicular language
  • vernacular language
  • working language
  • world language
  • active-stative language
  • agglutinative language
  • analytic language
  • direct-inverse language
  • E-language
  • ergative-absolutive language
  • I-language
  • isolating language
  • nominative-accusative language
  • oligosynthetic language
  • OV language
  • polysynthetic language
  • synthetic language
  • tripartite language
  • VO language
Derived terms[edit]
  • A language
  • AB language
  • abstract language
  • aspect-oriented language
  • aspect-oriented programming language
  • assembly language
  • B language
  • C language
  • child language
  • class-based language
  • classical language
  • clean language
  • community language
  • Community language
  • conditional assembly language
  • contact language
  • context-free language
  • curly-brace language
  • curly-braces language
  • curly-bracket language
  • daughter language
  • delegation language
  • domain-specific language
  • dynamic language
  • e-language learning
  • English-language
  • esoteric programming language
  • expressive language
  • first language
  • German-language
  • ghost language
  • good language
  • heritage language
  • high-level language
  • home language
  • imperative language
  • indexing language
  • interlanguage
  • intermediate language
  • international auxiliary language
  • Iranian language
  • Iranic language
  • killer language
  • language area
  • language arts
  • language assimilation
  • language assistant
  • language barrier
  • language code
  • language contact
  • language continuum
  • language cop
  • language death
  • language ecology
  • language exchange
  • language extinction
  • language family
  • language game
  • language island
  • language isolate
  • language lab
  • language laboratory
  • language model
  • language nest
  • language of education
  • language of flowers
  • language planning
  • language police
  • language pollution
  • language processing
  • language replacement
  • language school
  • language shift
  • language swap
  • language technology
  • language transfer
  • language-agnostic
  • language-independent
  • languaging
  • large language model
  • link-language
  • lip language
  • liturgical language
  • loaded language
  • logical language
  • love language
  • low-level language
  • macro language
  • markup language
  • matrix language
  • mind one’s language
  • mini-language
  • mixed language
  • moon language
  • mother language
  • native language
  • natural language processing
  • natural language understanding
  • null-subject language
  • object-based language
  • object-oriented language
  • official language
  • Oïl language
  • pandanus language
  • parent language
  • people-first language
  • Polish-language
  • private language argument
  • private language problem
  • private language thesis
  • pro-drop language
  • proto-language
  • prototype-based language
  • query language
  • receptive language
  • reconstructed language
  • regular language
  • role-oriented language
  • Romance language
  • second language
  • sleeping language
  • source language
  • speak someone’s language
  • speak the same language
  • specific language impairment
  • static language
  • statically-typed language
  • strong language
  • style sheet language
  • Sydney language
  • symbolic language
  • systems language
  • Turkish-language
  • unparliamentary language
  • ur-language
  • village sign language
  • visual language
  • visual programming language
  • watch one’s language
  • Western Desert language
  • whole language
  • wooden language
[edit]
  • langue
  • lingua
  • lingua franca
  • linguine
  • linguistics
  • tonguage
Translations[edit]

Verb[edit]

language (third-person singular simple present languages, present participle languaging, simple past and past participle languaged)

  1. (rare, now nonstandard or technical) To communicate by language; to express in language.
    • 1655, Thomas Fuller, James Nichols, editor, The Church History of Britain, [], volume (please specify |volume=I to III), new edition, London: [] [James Nichols] for Thomas Tegg and Son, [], published 1837, →OCLC:

      Others were languaged in such doubtful expressions that they have a double sense.

Interjection[edit]

language

  1. An admonishment said in response to vulgar language.

    You’re a pile of shit!
    Hey! Language!

See also[edit]

  • bilingual
  • lexis
  • linguistics
  • multilingual
  • term
  • trilingual
  • word

Etymology 2[edit]

Alteration of languet.

Noun[edit]

language (plural languages)

  1. A languet, a flat plate in or below the flue pipe of an organ.
    • 1896, William Horatio Clarke, The Organist’s Retrospect, →ISBN Invalid ISBN, page 79:

      A flue-pipe is one in which the air passes through the throat, or flue, which is the narrow, longitudinal aperture between the lower lip and the tongue, or language. [] The language is adjusted by slightly elevating or depressing it, []

References[edit]

  • language at OneLook Dictionary Search
  • language in Keywords for Today: A 21st Century Vocabulary, edited by The Keywords Project, Colin MacCabe, Holly Yanacek, 2018.
  • “language”, in The Century Dictionary [], New York, N.Y.: The Century Co., 1911, →OCLC.

French[edit]

Noun[edit]

language m (plural languages)

  1. Archaic spelling of langage.

Middle English[edit]

Noun[edit]

language (plural languages)

  1. Alternative form of langage

Middle French[edit]

Alternative forms[edit]

  • langage, langaige, languaige

Etymology[edit]

From Old French language.

Noun[edit]

language m (plural languages)

  1. language (style of communicating)

[edit]

  • langue

Descendants[edit]

  • French: langage (see there for further descendants)

Old French[edit]

Alternative forms[edit]

Etymology[edit]

From Vulgar Latin *linguāticum, from Classical Latin lingua (tongue, language).

Pronunciation[edit]

  • (archaic) IPA(key): /lenˈɡwad͡ʒə/
  • (classical) IPA(key): /lanˈɡad͡ʒə/
  • (late) IPA(key): /lanˈɡaʒə/

Noun[edit]

language f (oblique plural languages, nominative singular language, nominative plural languages)

  1. language (style of communicating)

[edit]

  • langue, lingue

Descendants[edit]

  • Bourguignon: langaige
  • Middle French: language, langage, langaige, languaige
    • French: langage (see there for further descendants)

Borrowings: (some possibly from O.Occitan lenguatge instead)

  • Middle English: langage, language, langag, langwache
    • English: language
  • Friulian: lengaç
  • Ladin: lingaz
  • Romansch: linguatg, lungatg; lungaitg; linguach

Introduction

There have been many attempts to unearth the origin of language, but “most of these are”, says E. Sapir, “hardly more than exercises of the speculative imagination.” Of the various theories advanced to explain the origin of language, four are well-known.

1.The Bow-wow Theory

This theory by Max Muller supposes that human speech originated in man’s attempt to imitate the sounds of nature. Thus a dog might be called “bow-wow”, or a cow “moo”. There is no denying the fact that such imitation accounts for a certain number of words in the English vocabulary e.g. cuckoo, hiss, gurgle, whistle, whine, babbie, prattlehoopoe, peewit etc. Words that have this origin are sometimes said to be onomatopoeic. This theory forms a part of the larger subject of ‘sound symbolism‘.

2. The Ding-dong Theory

Another familiar theory of the origin of language is the ‘dingdong theory’. At one stage it was upheld by Max Muller but later it was abandoned. It sought to explain the correspondence between sound and sense, by a law of nature, a mysterious law of harmony, that everything that is struck rings and rings in a peculiar way. The words ‘zigzag’ and ‘dazzle’ may be cited as examples. In the opinion of Prof. Taraporewala, the Hindi word “Jana Gana” “Jog Mog” and a larger number of the Bengali words (Dhonatyak Shobdo) may come under this head. Reduplications for the sake of emphasis, as in “a big big man’, may come under this head.

3. The Pooh pooh Theory

This theory seeks the origin of language in such involuntary exclamations or interjections of pain, surprise, wonder, disapproval, pleasure as oh! bah! pshaw! fie, and the like. As a theory of the origin of language it stands upon a very slippery ground.

4. The Gesture Theory

This holds that language originates in gesture. This theory was formulated and advanced by Wilhelm Wundt and Sir Richard Paget. The gesture-theorists opine that the primitive people communicated with one another by means of gestures made by hand, and ultimately the language-equivalents were substituted for these gestures. Sir Percy Nunn in his book Education, its Data and first Principles develops his theory in full, and Macdonald Critchley deals with it elaborately in his work, The Language of Gesture.

They seem to point out that in saying ‘I’ and ‘me’ the lips are drawn inwards as if hinting at the speaker, and in saying ‘you’ and ‘thou’ the lips are moved outwards as if hinting at the person addressed. Similarly, in saying ‘here’ and ‘there’ the lips are drawn inwards and thrown outwards respectively.

5. The yo-he-ho Theory

Noire enunciated the ‘yo-he-ho theory’. He saw the source of speech in acts of joint or common work, in which, during intense physical effort, cries or sounds partly consonantal might be emitted. Such sounds might come to be associated with the work performed and so become a symbol for it; the first words would accordingly mean something like ‘heave’ or ‘haul’.

6. The ta-ta Theory

The idea of the origin of language is the use of tongue and mouth gestures to mimic manual gestures. For example, saying ta-ta is like waving goodbye with your tongue. But most of the things we talk about do not have characteristic gestures associated with them, much less gestures you can imitate with the tongue and mouth.

7. The la-la Theory

The idea that speech emerged from the sounds of inspired playfulness, love, poetic sensibility, and song. This one is lovely, and no more or less likely than any of the others.

8. Biblical Theory

Let us peep into the Biblical account of the origin of language which is contained in the second chapter in the book of Genesis. According to this account, “the Lord God formed man of dust from the ground, and breathed into his nostrils the breath of life, and man became a living being.” Afterwards he created trees and rivers. And then “out of the ground the Lord God formed every beast of the field and every bird of the air, and brought them to the man to see what he would call them; and whatever the man called every living creature, that was its name. The man gave names to all cattle, and to the birds of the air, and to every beast of the field….” It is an account of the birth of language in man, who is placed at the centre of the world.

9. Another theory to be mentioned was adduced over a century ago in the early days of modern linguistics. In 1823 was published in Edinburgh The History of the European Languages by Alexander Murray, D.D.  In this work he states 9 words which he calls “the foundations of language.” They were uttered at first, and probably for several generations, in an insulated manner. The circumstances of the actions were communicated by gestures and variable tunes of the voice, but actions themselves were expressed through suitable monosyllables.

10. The last theory of the origin of language was proposed some years ago by the Danish linguist, Otto Jespersen. This language expert says, ‘we must imagine primitive language as consisting (chiefly, at least) of very long words, full of difficult sounds, and sung rather than spoken’. It is the strangest of all theories, but deserves serious thought because of the learning of the author.

Also Read:

Language : Definitions, Types, Functions, Approaches

Jespersen, unlike many other linguists of his day, was not prepared to accept the view that the origin of speech is unknowable. He suggested that “there once was a time when all speech was song, or rather when these two actions were not yet differentiated ….”

According to him,

“Language was born in the courting days of mankind; the first utterances of speech I fancy to myself like something between the nightly love-lyrics of puss upon the tiles and melodious love-songs of the nightingale.”

Conclusion

All the theories noted above are only partially true and do not seem to satisfy fully the intelligentsia. As they are many, they frustrate any attempt at arriving at an acceptable and convincing solution. For the present, we may rest content with ample knowledge of the theories alone.

Like this post? Please share to your friends:
  • The origin of the word land
  • The origin of the word jeans
  • The origin of the word house
  • The origin of the word hospitality
  • The origin of the word google