The meaning of the word free will

A biker performing a dirt jump that, according to some interpretations, is the result of free will.

Free will is the notional capacity or ability to choose between different possible courses of action unimpeded.[1]

Free will is closely linked to the concepts of moral responsibility, praise, culpability, sin, and other judgements which apply only to actions that are freely chosen. It is also connected with the concepts of advice, persuasion, deliberation, and prohibition. Traditionally, only actions that are freely willed are seen as deserving credit or blame. Whether free will exists, what it is and the implications of whether it exists or not are some of the longest running debates of philosophy and religion. Some conceive of free will as the ability to act beyond the limits of external influences or wishes.

Some conceive free will to be the capacity to make choices undetermined by past events. Determinism suggests that only one course of events is possible, which is inconsistent with a libertarian model of free will.[2] Ancient Greek philosophy identified this issue,[3] which remains a major focus of philosophical debate. The view that conceives free will as incompatible with determinism is called incompatibilism and encompasses both metaphysical libertarianism (the claim that determinism is false and thus free will is at least possible) and hard determinism (the claim that determinism is true and thus free will is not possible). Incompatibilism also encompasses hard incompatibilism, which holds not only determinism but also indeterminism to be incompatible with free will and thus free will to be impossible whatever the case may be regarding determinism.

In contrast, compatibilists hold that free will is compatible with determinism. Some compatibilists even hold that determinism is necessary for free will, arguing that choice involves preference for one course of action over another, requiring a sense of how choices will turn out.[4][5] Compatibilists thus consider the debate between libertarians and hard determinists over free will vs. determinism a false dilemma.[6] Different compatibilists offer very different definitions of what «free will» means and consequently find different types of constraints to be relevant to the issue. Classical compatibilists considered free will nothing more than freedom of action, considering one free of will simply if, had one counterfactually wanted to do otherwise, one could have done otherwise without physical impediment. Contemporary compatibilists instead identify free will as a psychological capacity, such as to direct one’s behavior in a way responsive to reason, and there are still further different conceptions of free will, each with their own concerns, sharing only the common feature of not finding the possibility of determinism a threat to the possibility of free will.[7]

History of free will[edit]

The problem of free will has been identified in ancient Greek philosophical literature. The notion of compatibilist free will has been attributed to both Aristotle (fourth century BCE) and Epictetus (1st century CE); «it was the fact that nothing hindered us from doing or choosing something that made us have control over them».[3][8] According to Susanne Bobzien, the notion of incompatibilist free will is perhaps first identified in the works of Alexander of Aphrodisias (third century CE); «what makes us have control over things is the fact that we are causally undetermined in our decision and thus can freely decide between doing/choosing or not doing/choosing them».

The term «free will» (liberum arbitrium) was introduced by Christian philosophy (4th century CE). It has traditionally meant (until the Enlightenment proposed its own meanings) lack of necessity in human will,[9] so that «the will is free» meant «the will does not have to be such as it is». This requirement was universally embraced by both incompatibilists and compatibilists.[10]

Western philosophy[edit]

The underlying questions are whether we have control over our actions, and if so, what sort of control, and to what extent. These questions predate the early Greek stoics (for example, Chrysippus), and some modern philosophers lament the lack of progress over all these centuries.[11][12]

On one hand, humans have a strong sense of freedom, which leads them to believe that they have free will.[13][14] On the other hand, an intuitive feeling of free will could be mistaken.[15][16]

It is difficult to reconcile the intuitive evidence that conscious decisions are causally effective with the view that the physical world can be explained entirely by physical law.[17] The conflict between intuitively felt freedom and natural law arises when either causal closure or physical determinism (nomological determinism) is asserted. With causal closure, no physical event has a cause outside the physical domain, and with physical determinism, the future is determined entirely by preceding events (cause and effect).

The puzzle of reconciling ‘free will’ with a deterministic universe is known as the problem of free will or sometimes referred to as the dilemma of determinism.[18] This dilemma leads to a moral dilemma as well: the question of how to assign responsibility for actions if they are caused entirely by past events.[19][20]

Compatibilists maintain that mental reality is not of itself causally effective.[21][22] Classical compatibilists have addressed the dilemma of free will by arguing that free will holds as long as humans are not externally constrained or coerced.[23] Modern compatibilists make a distinction between freedom of will and freedom of action, that is, separating freedom of choice from the freedom to enact it.[24] Given that humans all experience a sense of free will, some modern compatibilists think it is necessary to accommodate this intuition.[25][26] Compatibilists often associate freedom of will with the ability to make rational decisions.

A different approach to the dilemma is that of incompatibilists, namely, that if the world is deterministic, then our feeling that we are free to choose an action is simply an illusion. Metaphysical libertarianism is the form of incompatibilism which posits that determinism is false and free will is possible (at least some people have free will).[27] This view is associated with non-materialist constructions,[15] including both traditional dualism, as well as models supporting more minimal criteria; such as the ability to consciously veto an action or competing desire.[28][29] Yet even with physical indeterminism, arguments have been made against libertarianism in that it is difficult to assign Origination (responsibility for «free» indeterministic choices).

Free will here is predominantly treated with respect to physical determinism in the strict sense of nomological determinism, although other forms of determinism are also relevant to free will.[30] For example, logical and theological determinism challenge metaphysical libertarianism with ideas of destiny and fate, and biological, cultural and psychological determinism feed the development of compatibilist models. Separate classes of compatibilism and incompatibilism may even be formed to represent these.[31]

Below are the classic arguments bearing upon the dilemma and its underpinnings.

Incompatibilism[edit]

Incompatibilism is the position that free will and determinism are logically incompatible, and that the major question regarding whether or not people have free will is thus whether or not their actions are determined. «Hard determinists», such as d’Holbach, are those incompatibilists who accept determinism and reject free will. In contrast, «metaphysical libertarians», such as Thomas Reid, Peter van Inwagen, and Robert Kane, are those incompatibilists who accept free will and deny determinism, holding the view that some form of indeterminism is true.[32] Another view is that of hard incompatibilists, which state that free will is incompatible with both determinism and indeterminism.[33]

Traditional arguments for incompatibilism are based on an «intuition pump»: if a person is like other mechanical things that are determined in their behavior such as a wind-up toy, a billiard ball, a puppet, or a robot, then people must not have free will.[32][34] This argument has been rejected by compatibilists such as Daniel Dennett on the grounds that, even if humans have something in common with these things, it remains possible and plausible that we are different from such objects in important ways.[35]

Another argument for incompatibilism is that of the «causal chain». Incompatibilism is key to the idealist theory of free will. Most incompatibilists reject the idea that freedom of action consists simply in «voluntary» behavior. They insist, rather, that free will means that someone must be the «ultimate» or «originating» cause of his actions. They must be causa sui, in the traditional phrase. Being responsible for one’s choices is the first cause of those choices, where first cause means that there is no antecedent cause of that cause. The argument, then, is that if a person has free will, then they are the ultimate cause of their actions. If determinism is true, then all of a person’s choices are caused by events and facts outside their control. So, if everything someone does is caused by events and facts outside their control, then they cannot be the ultimate cause of their actions. Therefore, they cannot have free will.[36][37][38] This argument has also been challenged by various compatibilist philosophers.[39][40]

A third argument for incompatibilism was formulated by Carl Ginet in the 1960s and has received much attention in the modern literature. The simplified argument runs along these lines: if determinism is true, then we have no control over the events of the past that determined our present state and no control over the laws of nature. Since we can have no control over these matters, we also can have no control over the consequences of them. Since our present choices and acts, under determinism, are the necessary consequences of the past and the laws of nature, then we have no control over them and, hence, no free will. This is called the consequence argument.[41][42] Peter van Inwagen remarks that C.D. Broad had a version of the consequence argument as early as the 1930s.[43]

The difficulty of this argument for some compatibilists lies in the fact that it entails the impossibility that one could have chosen other than one has. For example, if Jane is a compatibilist and she has just sat down on the sofa, then she is committed to the claim that she could have remained standing, if she had so desired. But it follows from the consequence argument that, if Jane had remained standing, she would have either generated a contradiction, violated the laws of nature or changed the past. Hence, compatibilists are committed to the existence of «incredible abilities», according to Ginet and van Inwagen. One response to this argument is that it equivocates on the notions of abilities and necessities, or that the free will evoked to make any given choice is really an illusion and the choice had been made all along, oblivious to its «decider».[42] David Lewis suggests that compatibilists are only committed to the ability to do something otherwise if different circumstances had actually obtained in the past.[44]

Using T, F for «true» and «false» and ? for undecided, there are exactly nine positions regarding determinism/free will that consist of any two of these three possibilities:[45]

Galen Strawson’s table[45]

1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9
Determinism D T F T F T F ? ? ?
Free will FW F T T F ? ? F T ?

Incompatibilism may occupy any of the nine positions except (5), (8) or (3), which last corresponds to soft determinism. Position (1) is hard determinism, and position (2) is libertarianism. The position (1) of hard determinism adds to the table the contention that D implies FW is untrue, and the position (2) of libertarianism adds the contention that FW implies D is untrue. Position (9) may be called hard incompatibilism if one interprets ? as meaning both concepts are of dubious value. Compatibilism itself may occupy any of the nine positions, that is, there is no logical contradiction between determinism and free will, and either or both may be true or false in principle. However, the most common meaning attached to compatibilism is that some form of determinism is true and yet we have some form of free will, position (3).[46]

Alex Rosenberg makes an extrapolation of physical determinism as inferred on the macroscopic scale by the behaviour of a set of dominoes to neural activity in the brain where; «If the brain is nothing but a complex physical object whose states are as much governed by physical laws as any other physical object, then what goes on in our heads is as fixed and determined by prior events as what goes on when one domino topples another in a long row of them.»[47] Physical determinism is currently disputed by prominent interpretations of quantum mechanics, and while not necessarily representative of intrinsic indeterminism in nature, fundamental limits of precision in measurement are inherent in the uncertainty principle.[48] The relevance of such prospective indeterminate activity to free will is, however, contested,[49] even when chaos theory is introduced to magnify the effects of such microscopic events.[29][50]

Below these positions are examined in more detail.[45]

Hard determinism[edit]

A simplified taxonomy of philosophical positions regarding free will and determinism

Determinism can be divided into causal, logical and theological determinism.[51] Corresponding to each of these different meanings, there arises a different problem for free will.[52] Hard determinism is the claim that determinism is true, and that it is incompatible with free will, so free will does not exist. Although hard determinism generally refers to nomological determinism (see causal determinism below), it can include all forms of determinism that necessitate the future in its entirety.[53] Relevant forms of determinism include:

Causal determinism
The idea that everything is caused by prior conditions, making it impossible for anything else to happen.[54] In its most common form, nomological (or scientific) determinism, future events are necessitated by past and present events combined with the laws of nature. Such determinism is sometimes illustrated by the thought experiment of Laplace’s demon. Imagine an entity that knows all facts about the past and the present, and knows all natural laws that govern the universe. If the laws of nature were determinate, then such an entity would be able to use this knowledge to foresee the future, down to the smallest detail.[55][56]
Logical determinism
The notion that all propositions, whether about the past, present or future, are either true or false. The problem of free will, in this context, is the problem of how choices can be free, given that what one does in the future is already determined as true or false in the present.[52]
Theological determinism
The idea that the future is already determined, either by a creator deity decreeing or knowing its outcome in advance.[57][58] The problem of free will, in this context, is the problem of how our actions can be free if there is a being who has determined them for us in advance, or if they are already set in time.

Other forms of determinism are more relevant to compatibilism, such as biological determinism, the idea that all behaviors, beliefs, and desires are fixed by our genetic endowment and our biochemical makeup, the latter of which is affected by both genes and environment, cultural determinism and psychological determinism.[52] Combinations and syntheses of determinist theses, such as bio-environmental determinism, are even more common.

Suggestions have been made that hard determinism need not maintain strict determinism, where something near to, like that informally known as adequate determinism, is perhaps more relevant.[30] Despite this, hard determinism has grown less popular in present times, given scientific suggestions that determinism is false – yet the intention of their position is sustained by hard incompatibilism.[27]

Metaphysical libertarianism[edit]

Various definitions of free will that have been proposed for Metaphysical Libertarianism (agent/substance causal,[59] centered accounts,[60] and efforts of will theory[29]), along with examples of other common free will positions (Compatibilism,[17] Hard Determinism,[61] and Hard Incompatibilism[33]). Red circles represent mental states; blue circles represent physical states; arrows describe causal interaction.

Metaphysical libertarianism is one philosophical view point under that of incompatibilism. Libertarianism holds onto a concept of free will that requires that the agent be able to take more than one possible course of action under a given set of circumstances.[62]

Accounts of libertarianism subdivide into non-physical theories and physical or naturalistic theories. Non-physical theories hold that the events in the brain that lead to the performance of actions do not have an entirely physical explanation, which requires that the world is not closed under physics. This includes interactionist dualism, which claims that some non-physical mind, will, or soul overrides physical causality. Physical determinism implies there is only one possible future and is therefore not compatible with libertarian free will. As consequent of incompatibilism, metaphysical libertarian explanations that do not involve dispensing with physicalism require physical indeterminism, such as probabilistic subatomic particle behavior – theory unknown to many of the early writers on free will. Incompatibilist theories can be categorised based on the type of indeterminism they require; uncaused events, non-deterministically caused events, and agent/substance-caused events.[59]

Non-causal theories[edit]

Non-causal accounts of incompatibilist free will do not require a free action to be caused by either an agent or a physical event. They either rely upon a world that is not causally closed, or physical indeterminism. Non-causal accounts often claim that each intentional action requires a choice or volition – a willing, trying, or endeavoring on behalf of the agent (such as the cognitive component of lifting one’s arm).[63][64] Such intentional actions are interpreted as free actions. It has been suggested, however, that such acting cannot be said to exercise control over anything in particular. According to non-causal accounts, the causation by the agent cannot be analysed in terms of causation by mental states or events, including desire, belief, intention of something in particular, but rather is considered a matter of spontaneity and creativity. The exercise of intent in such intentional actions is not that which determines their freedom – intentional actions are rather self-generating. The «actish feel» of some intentional actions do not «constitute that event’s activeness, or the agent’s exercise of active control», rather they «might be brought about by direct stimulation of someone’s brain, in the absence of any relevant desire or intention on the part of that person».[59] Another question raised by such non-causal theory, is how an agent acts upon reason, if the said intentional actions are spontaneous.

Some non-causal explanations involve invoking panpsychism, the theory that a quality of mind is associated with all particles, and pervades the entire universe, in both animate and inanimate entities.

Event-causal theories[edit]

Event-causal accounts of incompatibilist free will typically rely upon physicalist models of mind (like those of the compatibilist), yet they presuppose physical indeterminism, in which certain indeterministic events are said to be caused by the agent. A number of event-causal accounts of free will have been created, referenced here as deliberative indeterminism, centred accounts, and efforts of will theory.[59] The first two accounts do not require free will to be a fundamental constituent of the universe. Ordinary randomness is appealed to as supplying the «elbow room» that libertarians believe necessary. A first common objection to event-causal accounts is that the indeterminism could be destructive and could therefore diminish control by the agent rather than provide it (related to the problem of origination). A second common objection to these models is that it is questionable whether such indeterminism could add any value to deliberation over that which is already present in a deterministic world.

Deliberative indeterminism asserts that the indeterminism is confined to an earlier stage in the decision process.[65][66] This is intended to provide an indeterminate set of possibilities to choose from, while not risking the introduction of luck (random decision making). The selection process is deterministic, although it may be based on earlier preferences established by the same process. Deliberative indeterminism has been referenced by Daniel Dennett[67] and John Martin Fischer.[68] An obvious objection to such a view is that an agent cannot be assigned ownership over their decisions (or preferences used to make those decisions) to any greater degree than that of a compatibilist model.

Centred accounts propose that for any given decision between two possibilities, the strength of reason will be considered for each option, yet there is still a probability the weaker candidate will be chosen.[60][69][70][71][72][73][74] An obvious objection to such a view is that decisions are explicitly left up to chance, and origination or responsibility cannot be assigned for any given decision.

Efforts of will theory is related to the role of will power in decision making. It suggests that the indeterminacy of agent volition processes could map to the indeterminacy of certain physical events – and the outcomes of these events could therefore be considered caused by the agent. Models of volition have been constructed in which it is seen as a particular kind of complex, high-level process with an element of physical indeterminism. An example of this approach is that of Robert Kane, where he hypothesizes that «in each case, the indeterminism is functioning as a hindrance or obstacle to her realizing one of her purposes – a hindrance or obstacle in the form of resistance within her will which must be overcome by effort.»[29] According to Robert Kane such «ultimate responsibility» is a required condition for free will.[75] An important factor in such a theory is that the agent cannot be reduced to physical neuronal events, but rather mental processes are said to provide an equally valid account of the determination of outcome as their physical processes (see non-reductive physicalism).

Although at the time quantum mechanics (and physical indeterminism) was only in the initial stages of acceptance, in his book Miracles: A preliminary study C.S. Lewis stated the logical possibility that if the physical world were proved indeterministic this would provide an entry point to describe an action of a non-physical entity on physical reality.[76] Indeterministic physical models (particularly those involving quantum indeterminacy) introduce random occurrences at an atomic or subatomic level. These events might affect brain activity, and could seemingly allow incompatibilist free will if the apparent indeterminacy of some mental processes (for instance, subjective perceptions of control in conscious volition) map to the underlying indeterminacy of the physical construct. This relationship, however, requires a causative role over probabilities that is questionable,[77] and it is far from established that brain activity responsible for human action can be affected by such events. Secondarily, these incompatibilist models are dependent upon the relationship between action and conscious volition, as studied in the neuroscience of free will. It is evident that observation may disturb the outcome of the observation itself, rendering limited our ability to identify causality.[48] Niels Bohr, one of the main architects of quantum theory, suggested, however, that no connection could be made between indeterminism of nature and freedom of will.[49]

Agent/substance-causal theories[edit]

Agent/substance-causal accounts of incompatibilist free will rely upon substance dualism in their description of mind. The agent is assumed power to intervene in the physical world.[78][79][80][81][82][83][84][85]
Agent (substance)-causal accounts have been suggested by both George Berkeley[86] and Thomas Reid.[87] It is required that what the agent causes is not causally determined by prior events. It is also required that the agent’s causing of that event is not causally determined by prior events. A number of problems have been identified with this view. Firstly, it is difficult to establish the reason for any given choice by the agent, which suggests they may be random or determined by luck (without an underlying basis for the free will decision). Secondly, it has been questioned whether physical events can be caused by an external substance or mind – a common problem associated with interactionalist dualism.

Hard incompatibilism[edit]

Hard incompatibilism is the idea that free will cannot exist, whether the world is deterministic or not. Derk Pereboom has defended hard incompatibilism, identifying a variety of positions where free will is irrelevant to indeterminism/determinism, among them the following:

  1. Determinism (D) is true, D does not imply we lack free will (F), but in fact we do lack F.
  2. D is true, D does not imply we lack F, but in fact we don’t know if we have F.
  3. D is true, and we do have F.
  4. D is true, we have F, and F implies D.
  5. D is unproven, but we have F.
  6. D isn’t true, we do have F, and would have F even if D were true.
  7. D isn’t true, we don’t have F, but F is compatible with D.
Derk Pereboom, Living without Free Will,[33] p. xvi.

Pereboom calls positions 3 and 4 soft determinism, position 1 a form of hard determinism, position 6 a form of classical libertarianism, and any position that includes having F as compatibilism.

John Locke denied that the phrase «free will» made any sense (compare with theological noncognitivism, a similar stance on the existence of God). He also took the view that the truth of determinism was irrelevant. He believed that the defining feature of voluntary behavior was that individuals have the ability to postpone a decision long enough to reflect or deliberate upon the consequences of a choice: «…the will in truth, signifies nothing but a power, or ability, to prefer or choose».[88]

The contemporary philosopher Galen Strawson agrees with Locke that the truth or falsity of determinism is irrelevant to the
problem.[89] He argues that the notion of free will leads to an infinite regress and is therefore senseless.
According to Strawson, if one is responsible for what one does in a given situation, then one must be responsible for the way one is in certain mental respects. But it is impossible for one to be responsible for the way one is in any respect. This is because to be responsible in some situation S, one must have been responsible for the way one was at S−1. To be responsible for the way one was at S−1, one must have been responsible for the way one was at S−2, and so on. At some point in the chain, there must have been an act of origination of a new causal chain. But this is impossible. Man cannot create himself or his mental states ex nihilo. This argument entails that free will itself is absurd, but not that it is incompatible with determinism. Strawson calls his own view «pessimism» but it can be classified as hard incompatibilism.[89]

Causal determinism[edit]

Causal determinism is the concept that events within a given paradigm are bound by causality in such a way that any state (of an object or event) is completely determined by prior states. Causal determinism proposes that there is an unbroken chain of prior occurrences stretching back to the origin of the universe. Causal determinists believe that there is nothing uncaused or self-caused. The most common form of causal determinism is nomological determinism (or scientific determinism), the notion that the past and the present dictate the future entirely and necessarily by rigid natural laws, that every occurrence results inevitably from prior events. Quantum mechanics poses a serious challenge to this view.

Fundamental debate continues over whether the physical universe is likely to be deterministic. Although the scientific method cannot be used to rule out indeterminism with respect to violations of causal closure, it can be used to identify indeterminism in natural law. Interpretations of quantum mechanics at present are both deterministic and indeterministic, and are being constrained by ongoing experimentation.[90]

Destiny and fate[edit]

Destiny or fate is a predetermined course of events. It may be conceived as a predetermined future, whether in general or of an individual. It is a concept based on the belief that there is a fixed natural order to the cosmos.

Although often used interchangeably, the words «fate» and «destiny» have distinct connotations.

Fate generally implies there is a set course that cannot be deviated from, and over which one has no control. Fate is related to determinism, but makes no specific claim of physical determinism. Even with physical indeterminism an event could still be fated externally (see for instance theological determinism). Destiny likewise is related to determinism, but makes no specific claim of physical determinism. Even with physical indeterminism an event could still be destined to occur.

Destiny implies there is a set course that cannot be deviated from, but does not of itself make any claim with respect to the setting of that course (i.e., it does not necessarily conflict with incompatibilist free will). Free will if existent could be the mechanism by which that destined outcome is chosen (determined to represent destiny).[91]

Logical determinism[edit]

Discussion regarding destiny does not necessitate the existence of supernatural powers. Logical determinism or determinateness is the notion that all propositions, whether about the past, present, or future, are either true or false. This creates a unique problem for free will given that propositions about the future already have a truth value in the present (that is it is already determined as either true or false), and is referred to as the problem of future contingents.

Omniscience[edit]

Omniscience is the capacity to know everything that there is to know (included in which are all future events), and is a property often attributed to a creator deity. Omniscience implies the existence of destiny. Some authors have claimed that free will cannot coexist with omniscience. One argument asserts that an omniscient creator not only implies destiny but a form of high level predeterminism such as hard theological determinism or predestination – that they have independently fixed all events and outcomes in the universe in advance. In such a case, even if an individual could have influence over their lower level physical system, their choices in regard to this cannot be their own, as is the case with libertarian free will. Omniscience features as an incompatible-properties argument for the existence of God, known as the argument from free will, and is closely related to other such arguments, for example the incompatibility of omnipotence with a good creator deity (i.e. if a deity knew what they were going to choose, then they are responsible for letting them choose it).

Predeterminism[edit]

Predeterminism is the idea that all events are determined in advance.[92][93] Predeterminism is the philosophy that all events of history, past, present and future, have been decided or are known (by God, fate, or some other force), including human actions. Predeterminism is frequently taken to mean that human actions cannot interfere with (or have no bearing on) the outcomes of a pre-determined course of events, and that one’s destiny was established externally (for example, exclusively by a creator deity). The concept of predeterminism is often argued by invoking causal determinism, implying that there is an unbroken chain of prior occurrences stretching back to the origin of the universe. In the case of predeterminism, this chain of events has been pre-established, and human actions cannot interfere with the outcomes of this pre-established chain. Predeterminism can be used to mean such pre-established causal determinism, in which case it is categorised as a specific type of determinism.[92][94] It can also be used interchangeably with causal determinism – in the context of its capacity to determine future events.[92][95] Despite this, predeterminism is often considered as independent of causal determinism.[96][97] The term predeterminism is also frequently used in the context of biology and heredity, in which case it represents a form of biological determinism.[98]

The term predeterminism suggests not just a determining of all events, but the prior and deliberately conscious determining of all events (therefore done, presumably, by a conscious being). While determinism usually refers to a naturalistically explainable causality of events, predeterminism seems by definition to suggest a person or a «someone» who is controlling or planning the causality of events before they occur and who then perhaps resides beyond the natural, causal universe. Predestination asserts that a supremely powerful being has indeed fixed all events and outcomes in the universe in advance, and is a famous doctrine of the Calvinists in Christian theology. Predestination is often considered a form of hard theological determinism.

Predeterminism has therefore been compared to fatalism.[99] Fatalism is the idea that everything is fated to happen, so that humans have no control over their future.

Theological determinism[edit]

Theological determinism is a form of determinism stating that all events that happen are pre-ordained, or predestined to happen, by a monotheistic deity, or that they are destined to occur given its omniscience. Two forms of theological determinism exist, here referenced as strong and weak theological determinism.[100]

  • The first one, strong theological determinism, is based on the concept of a creator deity dictating all events in history: «everything that happens has been predestined to happen by an omniscient, omnipotent divinity.»[101]
  • The second form, weak theological determinism, is based on the concept of divine foreknowledge – «because God’s omniscience is perfect, what God knows about the future will inevitably happen, which means, consequently, that the future is already fixed.»[102]

There exist slight variations on the above categorisation. Some claim that theological determinism requires predestination of all events and outcomes by the divinity (that is, they do not classify the weaker version as ‘theological determinism’ unless libertarian free will is assumed to be denied as a consequence), or that the weaker version does not constitute ‘theological determinism’ at all.[53] Theological determinism can also be seen as a form of causal determinism, in which the antecedent conditions are the nature and will of God.[54] With respect to free will and the classification of theological compatibilism/incompatibilism below, «theological determinism is the thesis that God exists and has infallible knowledge of all true propositions including propositions about our future actions,» more minimal criteria designed to encapsulate all forms of theological determinism.[30]

A simplified taxonomy of philosophical positions regarding free will and theological determinism[31]

There are various implications for metaphysical libertarian free will as consequent of theological determinism and its philosophical interpretation.

  • Strong theological determinism is not compatible with metaphysical libertarian free will, and is a form of hard theological determinism (equivalent to theological fatalism below). It claims that free will does not exist, and God has absolute control over a person’s actions. Hard theological determinism is similar in implication to hard determinism, although it does not invalidate compatibilist free will.[31] Hard theological determinism is a form of theological incompatibilism (see figure, top left).
  • Weak theological determinism is either compatible or incompatible with metaphysical libertarian free will depending upon one’s philosophical interpretation of omniscience – and as such is interpreted as either a form of hard theological determinism (known as theological fatalism), or as soft theological determinism (terminology used for clarity only). Soft theological determinism claims that humans have free will to choose their actions, holding that God, while knowing their actions before they happen, does not affect the outcome. God’s providence is «compatible» with voluntary choice. Soft theological determinism is known as theological compatibilism (see figure, top right). A rejection of theological determinism (or divine foreknowledge) is classified as theological incompatibilism also (see figure, bottom), and is relevant to a more general discussion of free will.[31]

The basic argument for theological fatalism in the case of weak theological determinism is as follows:

  1. Assume divine foreknowledge or omniscience
  2. Infallible foreknowledge implies destiny (it is known for certain what one will do)
  3. Destiny eliminates alternate possibility (one cannot do otherwise)
  4. Assert incompatibility with metaphysical libertarian free will

This argument is very often accepted as a basis for theological incompatibilism: denying either libertarian free will or divine foreknowledge (omniscience) and therefore theological determinism. On the other hand, theological compatibilism must attempt to find problems with it. The formal version of the argument rests on a number of premises, many of which have received some degree of contention. Theological compatibilist responses have included:

  • Deny the truth value of future contingents, although this denies foreknowledge and therefore theological determinism.
  • Assert differences in non-temporal knowledge (space-time independence), an approach taken for example by Boethius,[103] Thomas Aquinas,[104] and C.S. Lewis.[105]
  • Deny the Principle of Alternate Possibilities: «If you cannot do otherwise when you do an act, you do not act freely.» For example, a human observer could in principle have a machine that could detect what will happen in the future, but the existence of this machine or their use of it has no influence on the outcomes of events.[106]

In the definition of compatibilism and incompatibilism, the literature often fails to distinguish between physical determinism and higher level forms of determinism (predeterminism, theological determinism, etc.) As such, hard determinism with respect to theological determinism (or «Hard Theological Determinism» above) might be classified as hard incompatibilism with respect to physical determinism (if no claim was made regarding the internal causality or determinism of the universe), or even compatibilism (if freedom from the constraint of determinism was not considered necessary for free will), if not hard determinism itself. By the same principle, metaphysical libertarianism (a form of incompatibilism with respect to physical determinism) might be classified as compatibilism with respect to theological determinism (if it was assumed such free will events were pre-ordained and therefore were destined to occur, but of which whose outcomes were not «predestined» or determined by God). If hard theological determinism is accepted (if it was assumed instead that such outcomes were predestined by God), then metaphysical libertarianism is not, however, possible, and would require reclassification (as hard incompatibilism for example, given that the universe is still assumed to be indeterministic – although the classification of hard determinism is technically valid also).[53]

Mind–body problem[edit]

The idea of free will is one aspect of the mind–body problem, that is, consideration of the relation between mind (for example, consciousness, memory, and judgment) and body (for example, the human brain and nervous system). Philosophical models of mind are divided into physical and non-physical expositions.

Cartesian dualism holds that the mind is a nonphysical substance, the seat of consciousness and intelligence, and is not identical with physical states of the brain or body. It is suggested that although the two worlds do interact, each retains some measure of autonomy. Under cartesian dualism external mind is responsible for bodily action, although unconscious brain activity is often caused by external events (for example, the instantaneous reaction to being burned).[107] Cartesian dualism implies that the physical world is not deterministic – and in which external mind controls (at least some) physical events, providing an interpretation of incompatibilist free will. Stemming from Cartesian dualism, a formulation sometimes called interactionalist dualism suggests a two-way interaction, that some physical events cause some mental acts and some mental acts cause some physical events. One modern vision of the possible separation of mind and body is the «three-world» formulation of Popper.[108] Cartesian dualism and Popper’s three worlds are two forms of what is called epistemological pluralism, that is the notion that different epistemological methodologies are necessary to attain a full description of the world. Other forms of epistemological pluralist dualism include psychophysical parallelism and epiphenomenalism. Epistemological pluralism is one view in which the mind-body problem is not reducible to the concepts of the natural sciences.

A contrasting approach is called physicalism. Physicalism is a philosophical theory holding that everything that exists is no more extensive than its physical properties; that is, that there are no non-physical substances (for example physically independent minds). Physicalism can be reductive or non-reductive. Reductive physicalism is grounded in the idea that everything in the world can actually be reduced analytically to its fundamental physical, or material, basis. Alternatively, non-reductive physicalism asserts that mental properties form a separate ontological class to physical properties: that mental states (such as qualia) are not ontologically reducible to physical states. Although one might suppose that mental states and neurological states are different in kind, that does not rule out the possibility that mental states are correlated with neurological states. In one such construction, anomalous monism, mental events supervene on physical events, describing the emergence of mental properties correlated with physical properties – implying causal reducibility. Non-reductive physicalism is therefore often categorised as property dualism rather than monism, yet other types of property dualism do not adhere to the causal reducibility of mental states (see epiphenomenalism).

Incompatibilism requires a distinction between the mental and the physical, being a commentary on the incompatibility of (determined) physical reality and one’s presumably distinct experience of will. Secondarily, metaphysical libertarian free will must assert influence on physical reality, and where mind is responsible for such influence (as opposed to ordinary system randomness), it must be distinct from body to accomplish this. Both substance and property dualism offer such a distinction, and those particular models thereof that are not causally inert with respect to the physical world provide a basis for illustrating incompatibilist free will (i.e. interactionalist dualism and non-reductive physicalism).

It has been noted that the laws of physics have yet to resolve the hard problem of consciousness:[109] «Solving the hard problem of consciousness involves determining how physiological processes such as ions flowing across the nerve membrane cause us to have experiences.»[110] According to some, «Intricately related to the hard problem of consciousness, the hard problem of free will represents the core problem of conscious free will: Does conscious volition impact the material world?»[15] Others however argue that «consciousness plays a far smaller role in human life than Western culture has tended to believe.»[111]

Compatibilism[edit]

Compatibilists maintain that determinism is compatible with free will. They believe freedom can be present or absent in a situation for reasons that have nothing to do with metaphysics. For instance, courts of law make judgments about whether individuals are acting under their own free will under certain circumstances without bringing in metaphysics. Similarly, political liberty is a non-metaphysical concept.[citation needed] Likewise, some compatibilists define free will as freedom to act according to one’s determined motives without hindrance from other individuals. So for example Aristotle in his Nicomachean Ethics,[112] and the Stoic Chrysippus.[113]
In contrast, the incompatibilist positions are concerned with a sort of «metaphysically free will», which compatibilists claim has never been coherently defined. Compatibilists argue that determinism does not matter; though they disagree among themselves about what, in turn, does matter. To be a compatibilist, one need not endorse any particular conception of free will, but only deny that determinism is at odds with free will.[114]

Although there are various impediments to exercising one’s choices, free will does not imply freedom of action. Freedom of choice (freedom to select one’s will) is logically separate from freedom to implement that choice (freedom to enact one’s will), although not all writers observe this distinction.[24] Nonetheless, some philosophers have defined free will as the absence of various impediments. Some «modern compatibilists», such as Harry Frankfurt and Daniel Dennett, argue free will is simply freely choosing to do what constraints allow one to do. In other words, a coerced agent’s choices can still be free if such coercion coincides with the agent’s personal intentions and desires.[35][115]

Free will as lack of physical restraint[edit]

Most «classical compatibilists», such as Thomas Hobbes, claim that a person is acting on the person’s own will only when it is the desire of that person to do the act, and also possible for the person to be able to do otherwise, if the person had decided to. Hobbes sometimes attributes such compatibilist freedom to each individual and not to some abstract notion of will, asserting, for example, that «no liberty can be inferred to the will, desire, or inclination, but the liberty of the man; which consisteth in this, that he finds no stop, in doing what he has the will, desire, or inclination to doe [sic].»[116] In articulating this crucial proviso, David Hume writes, «this hypothetical liberty is universally allowed to belong to every one who is not a prisoner and in chains.»[117] Similarly, Voltaire, in his Dictionnaire philosophique, claimed that «Liberty then is only and can be only the power to do what one will.» He asked, «would you have everything at the pleasure of a million blind caprices?» For him, free will or liberty is «only the power of acting, what is this power? It is the effect of the constitution and present state of our organs.»

Free will as a psychological state[edit]

Compatibilism often regards the agent free as virtue of their reason. Some explanations of free will focus on the internal causality of the mind with respect to higher-order brain processing – the interaction between conscious and unconscious brain activity.[118] Likewise, some modern compatibilists in psychology have tried to revive traditionally accepted struggles of free will with the formation of character.[119] Compatibilist free will has also been attributed to our natural sense of agency, where one must believe they are an agent in order to function and develop a theory of mind.[120][121]

The notion of levels of decision is presented in a different manner by Frankfurt.[115] Frankfurt argues for a version of compatibilism called the «hierarchical mesh». The idea is that an individual can have conflicting desires at a first-order level and also have a desire about the various first-order desires (a second-order desire) to the effect that one of the desires prevails over the others. A person’s will is identified with their effective first-order desire, that is, the one they act on, and this will is free if it was the desire the person wanted to act upon, that is, the person’s second-order desire was effective. So, for example, there are «wanton addicts», «unwilling addicts» and «willing addicts». All three groups may have the conflicting first-order desires to want to take the drug they are addicted to and to not want to take it.

The first group, wanton addicts, have no second-order desire not to take the drug. The second group, «unwilling addicts», have a second-order desire not to take the drug, while the third group, «willing addicts», have a second-order desire to take it. According to Frankfurt, the members of the first group are devoid of will and therefore are no longer persons. The members of the second group freely desire not to take the drug, but their will is overcome by the addiction. Finally, the members of the third group willingly take the drug they are addicted to. Frankfurt’s theory can ramify to any number of levels. Critics of the theory point out that there is no certainty that conflicts will not arise even at the higher-order levels of desire and preference.[122] Others argue that Frankfurt offers no adequate explanation of how the various levels in the hierarchy mesh together.[123]

Free will as unpredictability[edit]

In Elbow Room, Dennett presents an argument for a compatibilist theory of free will, which he further elaborated in the book Freedom Evolves.[124] The basic reasoning is that, if one excludes God, an infinitely powerful demon, and other such possibilities, then because of chaos and epistemic limits on the precision of our knowledge of the current state of the world, the future is ill-defined for all finite beings. The only well-defined things are «expectations». The ability to do «otherwise» only makes sense when dealing with these expectations, and not with some unknown and unknowable future.

According to Dennett, because individuals have the ability to act differently from what anyone expects, free will can exist.[124] Incompatibilists claim the problem with this idea is that we may be mere «automata responding in predictable ways to stimuli in our environment». Therefore, all of our actions are controlled by forces outside ourselves, or by random chance.[125] More sophisticated analyses of compatibilist free will have been offered, as have other critiques.[114]

In the philosophy of decision theory, a fundamental question is: From the standpoint of statistical outcomes, to what extent do the choices of a conscious being have the ability to influence the future? Newcomb’s paradox and other philosophical problems pose questions about free will and predictable outcomes of choices.

The physical mind[edit]

Compatibilist models of free will often consider deterministic relationships as discoverable in the physical world (including the brain). Cognitive naturalism[126] is a physicalist approach to studying human cognition and consciousness in which the mind is simply part of nature, perhaps merely a feature of many very complex self-programming feedback systems (for example, neural networks and cognitive robots), and so must be studied by the methods of empirical science, such as the behavioral and cognitive sciences (i.e. neuroscience and cognitive psychology).[107][127] Cognitive naturalism stresses the role of neurological sciences. Overall brain health, substance dependence, depression, and various personality disorders clearly influence mental activity, and their impact upon volition is also important.[118] For example, an addict may experience a conscious desire to escape addiction, but be unable to do so. The «will» is disconnected from the freedom to act. This situation is related to an abnormal production and distribution of dopamine in the brain.[128] The neuroscience of free will places restrictions on both compatibilist and incompatibilist free will conceptions.

Compatibilist models adhere to models of mind in which mental activity (such as deliberation) can be reduced to physical activity without any change in physical outcome. Although compatibilism is generally aligned to (or is at least compatible with) physicalism, some compatibilist models describe the natural occurrences of deterministic deliberation in the brain in terms of the first person perspective of the conscious agent performing the deliberation.[15] Such an approach has been considered a form of identity dualism. A description of «how conscious experience might affect brains» has been provided in which «the experience of conscious free will is the first-person perspective of the neural correlates of choosing.»[15]

Recently,[when?] Claudio Costa developed a neocompatibilist theory based on the causal theory of action that is complementary to classical compatibilism. According to him, physical, psychological and rational restrictions can interfere at different levels of the causal chain that would naturally lead to action. Correspondingly, there can be physical restrictions to the body, psychological restrictions to the decision, and rational restrictions to the formation of reasons (desires plus beliefs) that should lead to what we would call a reasonable action. The last two are usually called «restrictions of free will». The restriction at the level of reasons is particularly important since it can be motivated by external reasons that are insufficiently conscious to the agent. One example was the collective suicide led by Jim Jones. The suicidal agents were not conscious that their free will have been manipulated by external, even if ungrounded, reasons.[129]

Non-naturalism[edit]

Alternatives to strictly naturalist physics, such as mind–body dualism positing a mind or soul existing apart from one’s body while perceiving, thinking, choosing freely, and as a result acting independently on the body, include both traditional religious metaphysics and less common newer compatibilist concepts.[130] Also consistent with both autonomy and Darwinism,[131] they allow for free personal agency based on practical reasons within the laws of physics.[132] While less popular among 21st-century philosophers, non-naturalist compatibilism is present in most if not almost all religions.[133]

Other views[edit]

Some philosophers’ views are difficult to categorize as either compatibilist or incompatibilist, hard determinist or libertarian. For example, Ted Honderich holds the view that «determinism is true, compatibilism and incompatibilism are both false» and the real problem lies elsewhere. Honderich maintains that determinism is true because quantum phenomena are not events or things that can be located in space and time, but are abstract entities. Further, even if they were micro-level events, they do not seem to have any relevance to how the world is at the macroscopic level. He maintains that incompatibilism is false because, even if indeterminism is true, incompatibilists have not provided, and cannot provide, an adequate account of origination. He rejects compatibilism because it, like incompatibilism, assumes a single, fundamental notion of freedom. There are really two notions of freedom: voluntary action and origination. Both notions are required to explain freedom of will and responsibility. Both determinism and indeterminism are threats to such freedom. To abandon these notions of freedom would be to abandon moral responsibility. On the one side, we have our intuitions; on the other, the scientific facts. The «new» problem is how to resolve this conflict.[134]

Free will as an illusion[edit]

Spinoza thought that there is no free will.

«Experience teaches us no less clearly than reason, that men believe themselves free, simply because they are conscious of their actions, and unconscious of the causes whereby those actions are determined.» Baruch Spinoza, Ethics[135]

David Hume discussed the possibility that the entire debate about free will is nothing more than a merely «verbal» issue. He suggested that it might be accounted for by «a false sensation or seeming experience» (a velleity), which is associated with many of our actions when we perform them. On reflection, we realize that they were necessary and determined all along.[136]

Arthur Schopenhauer claimed that phenomena do not have freedom of the will, but the will as noumenon is not subordinate to the laws of necessity (causality) and is thus free.

According to Arthur Schopenhauer, the actions of humans, as phenomena, are subject to the principle of sufficient reason and thus liable to necessity. Thus, he argues, humans do not possess free will as conventionally understood. However, the will [urging, craving, striving, wanting, and desiring], as the noumenon underlying the phenomenal world, is in itself groundless: that is, not subject to time, space, and causality (the forms that governs the world of appearance). Thus, the will, in itself and outside of appearance, is free. Schopenhauer discussed the puzzle of free will and moral responsibility in The World as Will and Representation, Book 2, Sec. 23:

But the fact is overlooked that the individual, the person, is not will as thing-in-itself, but is phenomenon of the will, is as such determined, and has entered the form of the phenomenon, the principle of sufficient reason. Hence we get the strange fact that everyone considers himself to be a priori quite free, even in his individual actions, and imagines he can at any moment enter upon a different way of life… But a posteriori through experience, he finds to his astonishment that he is not free, but liable to necessity; that notwithstanding all his resolutions and reflections he does not change his conduct, and that from the beginning to the end of his life he must bear the same character that he himself condemns, and, as it were, must play to the end the part he has taken upon himself.[137]

Schopenhauer elaborated on the topic in Book IV of the same work and in even greater depth in his later essay On the Freedom of the Will. In this work, he stated, «You can do what you will, but in any given moment of your life you can will only one definite thing and absolutely nothing other than that one thing.»[138]

In his book Free Will, philosopher and neuroscientist Sam Harris argues that free will is an illusion, stating that «thoughts and intentions emerge from background causes of which we are unaware and over which we exert no conscious control.»[139]

Free will as «moral imagination»[edit]

Rudolf Steiner, who collaborated in a complete edition of Arthur Schopenhauer’s work,[140] wrote The Philosophy of Freedom, which focuses on the problem of free will. Steiner (1861–1925) initially divides this into the two aspects of freedom: freedom of thought and freedom of action. The controllable and uncontrollable aspects of decision making thereby are made logically separable, as pointed out in the introduction. This separation of will from action has a very long history, going back at least as far as Stoicism and the teachings of Chrysippus (279–206 BCE), who separated external antecedent causes from the internal disposition receiving this cause.[141]

Steiner then argues that inner freedom is achieved when we integrate our sensory impressions, which reflect the outer appearance of the world, with our thoughts, which lend coherence to these impressions and thereby disclose to us an understandable world. Acknowledging the many influences on our choices, he nevertheless points out that they do not preclude freedom unless we fail to recognise them. Steiner argues that outer freedom is attained by permeating our deeds with moral imagination. «Moral» in this case refers to action that is willed, while «imagination» refers to the mental capacity to envision conditions that do not already hold. Both of these functions are necessarily conditions for freedom. Steiner aims to show that these two aspects of inner and outer freedom are integral to one another, and that true freedom is only achieved when they are united.[142]

Free will as a pragmatically useful concept[edit]

William James’ views were ambivalent. While he believed in free will on «ethical grounds», he did not believe that there was evidence for it on scientific grounds, nor did his own introspections support it.[143] Ultimately he believed that the problem of free will was a metaphysical issue and, therefore, could not be settled by science. Moreover, he did not accept incompatibilism as formulated below; he did not believe that the indeterminism of human actions was a prerequisite of moral responsibility. In his work Pragmatism, he wrote that «instinct and utility between them can safely be trusted to carry on the social business of punishment and praise» regardless of metaphysical theories.[144] He did believe that indeterminism is important as a «doctrine of relief» – it allows for the view that, although the world may be in many respects a bad place, it may, through individuals’ actions, become a better one. Determinism, he argued, undermines meliorism – the idea that progress is a real concept leading to improvement in the world.[144]

Free will and views of causality[edit]

In 1739, David Hume in his A Treatise of Human Nature approached free will via the notion of causality. It was his position that causality was a mental construct used to explain the repeated association of events, and that one must examine more closely the relation between things regularly succeeding one another (descriptions of regularity in nature) and things that result in other things (things that cause or necessitate other things).[145] According to Hume, ‘causation’ is on weak grounds: «Once we realise that ‘A must bring about B’ is tantamount merely to ‘Due to their constant conjunction, we are psychologically certain that B will follow A,’ then we are left with a very weak notion of necessity.»[146]

This empiricist view was often denied by trying to prove the so-called apriority of causal law (i.e. that it precedes all experience and is rooted in the construction of the perceivable world):

  • Kant’s proof in Critique of Pure Reason (which referenced time and time ordering of causes and effects)[147]
  • Schopenhauer’s proof from The Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason (which referenced the so-called intellectuality of representations, that is, in other words, objects and qualia perceived with senses)[148]

In the 1780s Immanuel Kant suggested at a minimum our decision processes with moral implications lie outside the reach of everyday causality, and lie outside the rules governing material objects.[149] «There is a sharp difference between moral judgments and judgments of fact… Moral judgments… must be a priori judgments.»[150]

Freeman introduces what he calls «circular causality» to «allow for the contribution of self-organizing dynamics», the «formation of macroscopic population dynamics that shapes the patterns of activity of the contributing individuals», applicable to «interactions between neurons and neural masses… and between the behaving animal and its environment».[151] In this view, mind and neurological functions are tightly coupled in a situation where feedback between collective actions (mind) and individual subsystems (for example, neurons and their synapses) jointly decide upon the behaviour of both.

Free will according to Thomas Aquinas[edit]

Thirteenth century philosopher Thomas Aquinas viewed humans as pre-programmed (by virtue of being human) to seek certain goals, but able to choose between routes to achieve these goals (our Aristotelian telos). His view has been associated with both compatibilism and libertarianism.[152][153]

In facing choices, he argued that humans are governed by intellect, will, and passions. The will is «the primary mover of all the powers of the soul… and it is also the efficient cause of motion in the body.»[154] Choice falls into five stages: (i) intellectual consideration of whether an objective is desirable, (ii) intellectual consideration of means of attaining the objective, (iii) will arrives at an intent to pursue the objective, (iv) will and intellect jointly decide upon choice of means (v) will elects execution.[155] Free will enters as follows: Free will is an «appetitive power», that is, not a cognitive power of intellect (the term «appetite» from Aquinas’s definition «includes all forms of internal inclination»).[156] He states that judgment «concludes and terminates counsel. Now counsel is terminated, first, by the judgment of reason; secondly, by the acceptation of the appetite [that is, the free-will].»[157]

A compatibilist interpretation of Aquinas’s view is defended thus: «Free-will is the cause of its own movement, because by his free-will man moves himself to act. But it does not of necessity belong to liberty that what is free should be the first cause of itself, as neither for one thing to be cause of another need it be the first cause. God, therefore, is the first cause, Who moves causes both natural and voluntary. And just as by moving natural causes He does not prevent their acts being natural, so by moving voluntary causes He does not deprive their actions of being voluntary: but rather is He the cause of this very thing in them; for He operates in each thing according to its own nature.»[158][159]

Free will as a pseudo-problem[edit]

Historically, most of the philosophical effort invested in resolving the dilemma has taken the form of close examination of definitions and ambiguities in the concepts designated by «free», «freedom», «will», «choice» and so forth. Defining ‘free will’ often revolves around the meaning of phrases like «ability to do otherwise» or «alternative possibilities». This emphasis upon words has led some philosophers to claim the problem is merely verbal and thus a pseudo-problem.[160] In response, others point out the complexity of decision making and the importance of nuances in the terminology.[citation needed]

Eastern philosophy[edit]

Buddhist philosophy[edit]

Buddhism accepts both freedom and determinism (or something similar to it), but in spite of its focus towards the human agency, rejects the western concept of a total agent from external sources.[161] According to the Buddha, «There is free action, there is retribution, but I see no agent that passes out from one set of momentary elements into another one, except the [connection] of those elements.»[161] Buddhists believe in neither absolute free will, nor determinism. It preaches a middle doctrine, named pratītyasamutpāda in Sanskrit, often translated as «dependent origination», «dependent arising» or «conditioned genesis». It teaches that every volition is a conditioned action as a result of ignorance. In part, it states that free will is inherently conditioned and not «free» to begin with. It is also part of the theory of karma in Buddhism. The concept of karma in Buddhism is different from the notion of karma in Hinduism. In Buddhism, the idea of karma is much less deterministic. The Buddhist notion of karma is primarily focused on the cause and effect of moral actions in this life, while in Hinduism the concept of karma is more often connected with determining one’s destiny in future lives.

In Buddhism it is taught that the idea of absolute freedom of choice (that is that any human being could be completely free to make any choice) is unwise, because it denies the reality of one’s physical needs and circumstances. Equally incorrect is the idea that humans have no choice in life or that their lives are pre-determined. To deny freedom would be to deny the efforts of Buddhists to make moral progress (through our capacity to freely choose compassionate action). Pubbekatahetuvada, the belief that all happiness and suffering arise from previous actions, is considered a wrong view according to Buddhist doctrines. Because Buddhists also reject agenthood, the traditional compatibilist strategies are closed to them as well. Instead, the Buddhist philosophical strategy is to examine the metaphysics of causality. Ancient India had many heated arguments about the nature of causality with Jains, Nyayists, Samkhyists, Cārvākans, and Buddhists all taking slightly different lines. In many ways, the Buddhist position is closer to a theory of «conditionality» (idappaccayatā) than a theory of «causality», especially as it is expounded by Nagarjuna in the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā.[161]

Hindu philosophy[edit]

The six orthodox (astika) schools of thought in Hindu philosophy do not agree with each other entirely on the question of free will. For the Samkhya, for instance, matter is without any freedom, and soul lacks any ability to control the unfolding of matter. The only real freedom (kaivalya) consists in realizing the ultimate separateness of matter and self.[162] For the Yoga school, only Ishvara is truly free, and its freedom is also distinct from all feelings, thoughts, actions, or wills, and is thus not at all a freedom of will. The metaphysics of the Nyaya and Vaisheshika schools strongly suggest a belief in determinism, but do not seem to make explicit claims about determinism or free will.[163]

A quotation from Swami Vivekananda, a Vedantist, offers a good example of the worry about free will in the Hindu tradition.

Therefore we see at once that there cannot be any such thing as free-will; the very words are a contradiction, because will is what we know, and everything that we know is within our universe, and everything within our universe is moulded by conditions of time, space and causality. … To acquire freedom we have to get beyond the limitations of this universe; it cannot be found here.[164]

However, the preceding quote has often been misinterpreted as Vivekananda implying that everything is predetermined. What Vivekananda actually meant by lack of free will was that the will was not «free» because it was heavily influenced by the law of cause and effect – «The will is not free, it is a phenomenon bound by cause and effect, but there is something behind the will which is free.»[164] Vivekananda never said things were absolutely determined and placed emphasis on the power of conscious choice to alter one’s past karma: «It is the coward and the fool who says this is his fate. But it is the strong man who stands up and says I will make my own fate.»[164]

Scientific approaches[edit]

Science has contributed to the free will problem in at least three ways. First, physics has addressed the question of whether nature is deterministic, which is viewed as crucial by incompatibilists (compatibilists, however, view it as irrelevant). Second, although free will can be defined in various ways, all of them involve aspects of the way people make decisions and initiate actions, which have been studied extensively by neuroscientists. Some of the experimental observations are widely viewed as implying that free will does not exist or is an illusion (but many philosophers see this as a misunderstanding). Third, psychologists have studied the beliefs that the majority of ordinary people hold about free will and its role in assigning moral responsibility.

From an anthropological perspective, free will can be regarded as an explanation for human behavior that justifies a socially sanctioned system of rewards and punishments. Under this definition, free will may be described as a political ideology. In a society where people are taught to believe that humans have free will, free will may be described as a political doctrine.

Quantum physics[edit]

Early scientific thought often portrayed the universe as deterministic – for example in the thought of Democritus or the Cārvākans – and some thinkers claimed that the simple process of gathering sufficient information would allow them to predict future events with perfect accuracy. Modern science, on the other hand, is a mixture of deterministic and stochastic theories.[165] Quantum mechanics predicts events only in terms of probabilities, casting doubt on whether the universe is deterministic at all, although evolution of the universal state vector is completely deterministic. Current physical theories cannot resolve the question of whether determinism is true of the world, being very far from a potential theory of everything, and open to many different interpretations.[166][167]

Assuming that an indeterministic interpretation of quantum mechanics is correct, one may still object that such indeterminism is for all practical purposes confined to microscopic phenomena.[168] This is not always the case: many macroscopic phenomena are based on quantum effects. For instance, some hardware random number generators work by amplifying quantum effects into practically usable signals. A more significant question is whether the indeterminism of quantum mechanics allows for the traditional idea of free will (based on a perception of free will). If a person’s action is, however, only a result of complete quantum randomness, mental processes as experienced have no influence on the probabilistic outcomes (such as volition).[29] According to many interpretations, non-determinism enables free will to exist,[169] while others assert the opposite (because the action was not controllable by the physical being who claims to possess the free will).[170]

Genetics[edit]

Like physicists, biologists have frequently addressed questions related to free will. One of the most heated debates in biology is that of «nature versus nurture», concerning the relative importance of genetics and biology as compared to culture and environment in human behavior.[171] The view of many researchers is that many human behaviors can be explained in terms of humans’ brains, genes, and evolutionary histories.[172][173][174] This point of view raises the fear that such attribution makes it impossible to hold others responsible for their actions. Steven Pinker’s view is that fear of determinism in the context of «genetics» and «evolution» is a mistake, that it is «a confusion of explanation with exculpation«. Responsibility does not require that behavior be uncaused, as long as behavior responds to praise and blame.[175] Moreover, it is not certain that environmental determination is any less threatening to free will than genetic determination.[176]

Neuroscience and neurophilosophy[edit]

It has become possible to study the living brain, and researchers can now watch the brain’s decision-making process at work. A seminal experiment in this field was conducted by Benjamin Libet in the 1980s, in which he asked each subject to choose a random moment to flick their wrist while he measured the associated activity in their brain; in particular, the build-up of electrical signal called the readiness potential (after German Bereitschaftspotential, which was discovered by Kornhuber & Deecke in 1965.[177]). Although it was well known that the readiness potential reliably preceded the physical action, Libet asked whether it could be recorded before the conscious intention to move. To determine when subjects felt the intention to move, he asked them to watch the second hand of a clock. After making a movement, the volunteer reported the time on the clock when they first felt the conscious intention to move; this became known as Libet’s W time.[178]

Libet found that the unconscious brain activity of the readiness potential leading up to subjects’ movements began approximately half a second before the subject was aware of a conscious intention to move.[178][179]

These studies of the timing between actions and the conscious decision bear upon the role of the brain in understanding free will. A subject’s declaration of intention to move a finger appears after the brain has begun to implement the action, suggesting to some that unconsciously the brain has made the decision before the conscious mental act to do so. Some believe the implication is that free will was not involved in the decision and is an illusion. The first of these experiments reported the brain registered activity related to the move about 0.2 s before movement onset.[180] However, these authors also found that awareness of action was anticipatory to activity in the muscle underlying the movement; the entire process resulting in action involves more steps than just the onset of brain activity. The bearing of these results upon notions of free will appears complex.[181][182]

Some argue that placing the question of free will in the context of motor control is too narrow. The objection is that the time scales involved in motor control are very short, and motor control involves a great deal of unconscious action, with much physical movement entirely unconscious. On that basis «…free will cannot be squeezed into time frames of 150–350 ms; free will is a longer term phenomenon» and free will is a higher level activity that «cannot be captured in a description of neural activity or of muscle activation…»[183] The bearing of timing experiments upon free will is still under discussion.

More studies have since been conducted, including some that try to:

  • support Libet’s original findings
  • suggest that the cancelling or «veto» of an action may first arise subconsciously as well
  • explain the underlying brain structures involved
  • suggest models that explain the relationship between conscious intention and action

Benjamin Libet’s results are quoted[184] in favor of epiphenomenalism, but he believes subjects still have a «conscious veto», since the readiness potential does not invariably lead to an action. In Freedom Evolves, Daniel Dennett argues that a no-free-will conclusion is based on dubious assumptions about the location of consciousness, as well as questioning the accuracy and interpretation of Libet’s results. Kornhuber and Deecke underlined that absence of conscious will during the early Bereitschaftspotential (termed BP1) is not a proof of the non-existence of free will, as also unconscious agendas may be free and non-deterministic. According to their suggestion, man has relative freedom, i.e. freedom in degrees, that can be increased or decreased through deliberate choices that involve both conscious and unconscious (panencephalic) processes.[185]

Others have argued that data such as the Bereitschaftspotential undermine epiphenomenalism for the same reason, that such experiments rely on a subject reporting the point in time at which a conscious experience occurs, thus relying on the subject to be able to consciously perform an action. That ability would seem to be at odds with early epiphenomenalism, which according to Huxley is the broad claim that consciousness is «completely without any power… as the steam-whistle which accompanies the work of a locomotive engine is without influence upon its machinery».[186]

Adrian G. Guggisberg and Annaïs Mottaz have also challenged those findings.[187]

A study by Aaron Schurger and colleagues published in the Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences[188] challenged assumptions about the causal nature of the readiness potential itself (and the «pre-movement buildup» of neural activity in general), casting doubt on conclusions drawn from studies such as Libet’s[178] and Fried’s.[189]

A study that compared deliberate and arbitrary decisions, found that the early signs of decision are absent for the deliberate ones.[190]

It has been shown that in several brain-related conditions, individuals cannot entirely control their own actions, though the existence of such conditions does not directly refute the existence of free will. Neuroscientific studies are valuable tools in developing models of how humans experience free will.

For example, people with Tourette syndrome and related tic disorders make involuntary movements and utterances (called tics) despite the fact that they would prefer not to do so when it is socially inappropriate. Tics are described as semi-voluntary or unvoluntary,[191] because they are not strictly involuntary: they may be experienced as a voluntary response to an unwanted, premonitory urge. Tics are experienced as irresistible and must eventually be expressed.[191] People with Tourette syndrome are sometimes able to suppress their tics for limited periods, but doing so often results in an explosion of tics afterward. The control exerted (from seconds to hours at a time) may merely postpone and exacerbate the ultimate expression of the tic.[192]

In alien hand syndrome, the affected individual’s limb will produce unintentional movements without the will of the person. The affected limb effectively demonstrates ‘a will of its own.’ The sense of agency does not emerge in conjunction with the overt appearance of the purposeful act even though the sense of ownership in relationship to the body part is maintained. This phenomenon corresponds with an impairment in the premotor mechanism manifested temporally by the appearance of the readiness potential recordable on the scalp several hundred milliseconds before the overt appearance of a spontaneous willed movement. Using functional magnetic resonance imaging with specialized multivariate analyses to study the temporal dimension in the activation of the cortical network associated with voluntary movement in human subjects, an anterior-to-posterior sequential activation process beginning in the supplementary motor area on the medial surface of the frontal lobe and progressing to the primary motor cortex and then to parietal cortex has been observed.[193] The sense of agency thus appears to normally emerge in conjunction with this orderly sequential network activation incorporating premotor association cortices together with primary motor cortex. In particular, the supplementary motor complex on the medial surface of the frontal lobe appears to activate prior to primary motor cortex presumably in associated with a preparatory pre-movement process. In a recent study using functional magnetic resonance imaging, alien movements were characterized by a relatively isolated activation of the primary motor cortex contralateral to the alien hand, while voluntary movements of the same body part included the natural activation of motor association cortex associated with the premotor process.[194] The clinical definition requires «feeling that one limb is foreign or has a will of its own, together with observable involuntary motor activity» (emphasis in original).[195] This syndrome is often a result of damage to the corpus callosum, either when it is severed to treat intractable epilepsy or due to a stroke. The standard neurological explanation is that the felt will reported by the speaking left hemisphere does not correspond with the actions performed by the non-speaking right hemisphere, thus suggesting that the two hemispheres may have independent senses of will.[196][197]

In addition, one of the most important («first rank») diagnostic symptoms of schizophrenia is the patient’s delusion of being controlled by an external force.[198] People with schizophrenia will sometimes report that, although they are acting in the world, they do not recall initiating the particular actions they performed. This is sometimes likened to being a robot controlled by someone else. Although the neural mechanisms of schizophrenia are not yet clear, one influential hypothesis is that there is a breakdown in brain systems that compare motor commands with the feedback received from the body (known as proprioception), leading to attendant hallucinations and delusions of control.[199]

Experimental psychology[edit]

Experimental psychology’s contributions to the free will debate have come primarily through social psychologist Daniel Wegner’s work on conscious will. In his book, The Illusion of Conscious Will,[200] Wegner summarizes what he believes is empirical evidence supporting the view that human perception of conscious control is an illusion. Wegner summarizes some empirical evidence that may suggest that the perception of conscious control is open to modification (or even manipulation). Wegner observes that one event is inferred to have caused a second event when two requirements are met:

  1. The first event immediately precedes the second event, and
  2. The first event is consistent with having caused the second event.

For example, if a person hears an explosion and sees a tree fall down that person is likely to infer that the explosion caused the tree to fall over. However, if the explosion occurs after the tree falls down (that is, the first requirement is not met), or rather than an explosion, the person hears the ring of a telephone (that is, the second requirement is not met), then that person is not likely to infer that either noise caused the tree to fall down.

Wegner has applied this principle to the inferences people make about their own conscious will. People typically experience a thought that is consistent with a behavior, and then they observe themselves performing this behavior. As a result, people infer that their thoughts must have caused the observed behavior. However, Wegner has been able to manipulate people’s thoughts and behaviors so as to conform to or violate the two requirements for causal inference.[200][201] Through such work, Wegner has been able to show that people often experience conscious will over behaviors that they have not, in fact, caused – and conversely, that people can be led to experience a lack of will over behaviors they did cause. For instance, priming subjects with information about an effect increases the probability that a person falsely believes is the cause.[202] The implication for such work is that the perception of conscious will (which he says might be more accurately labelled as ‘the emotion of authorship’) is not tethered to the execution of actual behaviors, but is inferred from various cues through an intricate mental process, authorship processing. Although many interpret this work as a blow against the argument for free will, both psychologists[203][204] and philosophers[205][206] have criticized Wegner’s theories.

Emily Pronin has argued that the subjective experience of free will is supported by the introspection illusion. This is the tendency for people to trust the reliability of their own introspections while distrusting the introspections of other people. The theory implies that people will more readily attribute free will to themselves rather than others. This prediction has been confirmed by three of Pronin and Kugler’s experiments. When college students were asked about personal decisions in their own and their roommate’s lives, they regarded their own choices as less predictable. Staff at a restaurant described their co-workers’ lives as more determined (having fewer future possibilities) than their own lives. When weighing up the influence of different factors on behavior, students gave desires and intentions the strongest weight for their own behavior, but rated personality traits as most predictive of other people.[207]

Caveats have, however, been identified in studying a subject’s awareness of mental events, in that the process of introspection itself may alter the experience.[208]

Regardless of the validity of belief in free will, it may be beneficial to understand where the idea comes from. One contribution is randomness.[209] While it is established that randomness is not the only factor in the perception of the free will, it has been shown that randomness can be mistaken as free will due to its indeterminacy. This misconception applies both when considering oneself and others. Another contribution is choice.[210] It has been demonstrated that people’s belief in free will increases if presented with a simple level of choice. The specificity of the amount of choice is important, as too little or too great a degree of choice may negatively influence belief. It is also likely that the associative relationship between level of choice and perception of free will is influentially bidirectional. It is also possible that one’s desire for control, or other basic motivational patterns, act as a third variable.

Other experiments[edit]

Other experiments have also been proposed to test free will. Ender Tosun argues for the reality of free will, based on combined experiments consisting of empirical and thought experiments. In the empirical part of these experiments, experimenter 2 is expected to predict which object experimenter 1 will touch. Experimenter 1 is always able to negate the prediction of experimenter 2. In the thought experiment part, Laplace’s demon makes the predictions and experimenter 1 is never able to negate his predictions. Based on the non-correspondence of the predictions of experimenter 2 in the empirical experiment with the predictions of Laplace’s demon, and contradictions in the possible layers of causality, Tosun concludes that free will is real. He also extends these experiments to indeterministic processes and real-time brain observations while willing, assuming that an agent has every technological means to probe and rewire his brain. In this thought experiment, experimenter 1 notices the «circuit» of his brain which disables him from willing one of the alternatives, then he probes other circuits to see if he can have the will to rewire that circuit. Experimenter 1 notices that all circuits of his brain being so as to prevent him from rewiring or bypassing the circuits which prevent him from willing to touch one of the objects is impossible.[citation needed]

Believing in free will[edit]

Since at least 1959,[211] free will belief in individuals has been analysed with respect to traits in social behaviour. In general, the concept of free will researched to date in this context has been that of the incompatibilist, or more specifically, the libertarian, that is freedom from determinism.

What people believe[edit]

Whether people naturally adhere to an incompatibilist model of free will has been questioned in the research. Eddy Nahmias has found that incompatibilism is not intuitive – it was not adhered to, in that determinism does not negate belief in moral responsibility (based on an empirical study of people’s responses to moral dilemmas under a deterministic model of reality).[212] Edward Cokely has found that incompatibilism is intuitive – it was naturally adhered to, in that determinism does indeed negate belief in moral responsibility in general.[213] Joshua Knobe and Shaun Nichols have proposed that incompatibilism may or may not be intuitive, and that it is dependent to some large degree upon the circumstances; whether or not the crime incites an emotional response – for example if it involves harming another human being.[214] They found that belief in free will is a cultural universal, and that the majority of participants said that (a) our universe is indeterministic and (b) moral responsibility is not compatible with determinism.[215]

Studies indicate that peoples’ belief in free will is inconsistent. Emily Pronin and Matthew Kugler found that people believe they have more free will than others.[216]

Studies also reveal a correlation between the likelihood of accepting a deterministic model of mind and personality type. For example, Adam Feltz and Edward Cokely found that people of an extrovert personality type are more likely to dissociate belief in determinism from belief in moral responsibility.[217]

Roy Baumeister and colleagues reviewed literature on the psychological effects of a belief (or disbelief) in free will and found that most people tend to believe in a sort of «naive compatibilistic free will».[218][219]

The researchers also found that people consider acts more «free» when they involve a person opposing external forces, planning, or making random actions.[220] Notably, the last behaviour, «random» actions, may not be possible; when participants attempt to perform tasks in a random manner (such as generating random numbers), their behaviour betrays many patterns.[221][222]

Among philosophers[edit]

A recent 2020 survey has shown that compatibilism is quite a popular stance among those who specialize in philosophy (59.2%). Belief in libertarianism amounted to 18.8%, while a lack of belief in free will equaled 11.2%.[223]

Among evolutionary biologists[edit]

79 percent of evolutionary biologists said that they believe in free will according to a survey conducted in 2007, only 14 percent chose no free will, and 7 percent did not answer the question.[224]

Effects of the belief itself[edit]

Baumeister and colleagues found that provoking disbelief in free will seems to cause various negative effects. The authors concluded, in their paper, that it is belief in determinism that causes those negative effects.[218] Kathleen Vohs has found that those whose belief in free will had been eroded were more likely to cheat.[225] In a study conducted by Roy Baumeister, after participants read an article arguing against free will, they were more likely to lie about their performance on a test where they would be rewarded with cash.[226] Provoking a rejection of free will has also been associated with increased aggression and less helpful behaviour.[226] However, although these initial studies suggested that believing in free will is associated with more morally praiseworthy behavior, more recent studies (including direct, multi-site replications) with substantially larger sample sizes have reported contradictory findings (typically, no association between belief in free will and moral behavior), casting doubt over the original findings.[227][228][229][230][231]

An alternative explanation builds on the idea that subjects tend to confuse determinism with fatalism… What happens then when agents’ self-efficacy is undermined? It is not that their basic desires and drives are defeated. It is rather, I suggest, that they become skeptical that they can control those desires; and in the face of that skepticism, they fail to apply the effort that is needed even to try. If they were tempted to behave badly, then coming to believe in fatalism makes them less likely to resist that temptation.

—Richard Holton[232]

Moreover, whether or not these experimental findings are a result of actual manipulations in belief in free will is a matter of debate.[232] First of all, free will can at least refer to either libertarian (indeterministic) free will or compatibilistic (deterministic) free will. Having participants read articles that simply «disprove free will» is unlikely to increase their understanding of determinism, or the compatibilistic free will that it still permits.[232] In other words, experimental manipulations purporting to «provoke disbelief in free will» may instead cause a belief in fatalism, which may provide an alternative explanation for previous experimental findings.[232][233] To test the effects of belief in determinism, it has been argued that future studies would need to provide articles that do not simply «attack free will», but instead focus on explaining determinism and compatibilism.[232][234]

Baumeister and colleagues also note that volunteers disbelieving in free will are less capable of counterfactual thinking.[218] This is worrying because counterfactual thinking («If I had done something different…») is an important part of learning from one’s choices, including those that harmed others.[235] Again, this cannot be taken to mean that belief in determinism is to blame; these are the results we would expect from increasing people’s belief in fatalism.[232]

Along similar lines, Tyler Stillman has found that belief in free will predicts better job performance.[236]

In theology[edit]

Christianity[edit]

Augustine’s view of free will and predestination would go on to have a profound impact on Christian theology.

The notions of free will and predestination are heavily debated among Christians. Free will in the Christian sense is the ability to choose between good or evil. Among Catholics, there are those holding to Thomism, adopted from what Thomas Aquinas put forth in the Summa Theologica. There are also some holding to Molinism which was put forth by Jesuit priest Luis de Molina. Among Protestants there is Arminianism, held primarily by the Methodist Churches, and formulated by Dutch theologian Jacobus Arminius; and there is also Calvinism held by most in the Reformed tradition which was formulated by the French Reformed theologian, John Calvin. John Calvin was heavily influenced by Augustine of Hippo views on predestination put forth in his work On the Predestination of the Saints. Martin Luther seems to hold views on predestination similar to Calvinism in his On the Bondage of the Will, thus rejecting free will. In condemnation of Calvin and Luther views, the Roman Catholic Council of Trent declared that «the free will of man, moved and excited by God, can by its consent co-operate with God, Who excites and invites its action; and that it can thereby dispose and prepare itself to obtain the grace of justification. The will can resist grace if it chooses. It is not like a lifeless thing, which remains purely passive. Weakened and diminished by Adam’s fall, free will is yet not destroyed in the race (Sess. VI, cap. i and v).» John Wesley, the father of the Methodist tradition, taught that humans, enabled by prevenient grace, have free will through which they can choose God and to do good works, with the goal of Christian perfection.[237] Upholding synergism (the belief that God and man cooperate in salvation), Methodism teaches that «Our Lord Jesus Christ did so die for all men as to make salvation attainable by every man that cometh into the world. If men are not saved that fault is entirely their own, lying solely in their own unwillingness to obtain the salvation offered to them. (John 1:9; I Thess. 5:9; Titus 2:11-12).»[238]

Paul the Apostle discusses Predestination in some of his Epistles.

«For whom He foreknew, He also predestined to become conformed to the image of His Son, that He might be the first-born among many brethren; and whom He predestined, these He also called; and whom He called, these He also justified; and whom He justified, these He also glorified.» —Romans 8:29–30

«He predestined us to adoption as sons through Jesus Christ to Himself, according to the kind intention of His will.» —Ephesians 1:5

There are also mentions of moral freedom in what are now termed as ‘Deuterocanonical’ works which the Orthodox and Catholic Churches use. In Sirach 15 the text states:

«Do not say: «It was God’s doing that I fell away,» for what he hates he does not do. Do not say: «He himself has led me astray,» for he has no need of the wicked. Abominable wickedness the Lord hates and he does not let it happen to those who fear him. God in the beginning created human beings and made them subject to their own free choice. If you choose, you can keep the commandments; loyalty is doing the will of God. Set before you are fire and water; to whatever you choose, stretch out your hand. Before everyone are life and death, whichever they choose will be given them. Immense is the wisdom of the Lord; mighty in power, he sees all things. The eyes of God behold his works, and he understands every human deed. He never commands anyone to sin, nor shows leniency toward deceivers.»
— Ben Sira‬ ‭15:11-20‬ ‭NABRE

The exact meaning of these verses has been debated by Christian theologians throughout history.

Judaism[edit]

In Jewish thought the concept of «Free will» (Hebrew: bechirah chofshit בחירה חפשית, bechirah בחירה) is foundational.
The most succinct statement is by Maimonides, in a two part treatment, where human free will is specified as part of the universe’s Godly design:

  1. Maimonides’s reasoned [239] that human beings must have free will (at least in the context of choosing to do good or evil), as without this, the demands of the prophets would have been meaningless, there would be no need for the Torah and Mitzvot («commandments»), and justice could not be administered.
  2. At the same time, Maimonides — and other thinkers — recognizes [240] the paradox that will arise given (i) that Judaism simultaneously recognizes God’s omniscience, and further (ii) the nature of Divine providence as understood in Judaism. (In fact the problem may be seen to overlap several others in Jewish Philosophy.)

Islam[edit]

In Islam the theological issue is not usually how to reconcile free will with God’s foreknowledge, but with God’s jabr, or divine commanding power. al-Ash’ari developed an «acquisition» or «dual-agency» form of compatibilism, in which human free will and divine jabr were both asserted, and which became a cornerstone of the dominant Ash’ari position.[241][242] In Shia Islam, Ash’aris understanding of a higher balance toward predestination is challenged by most theologians.[243] Free will, according to Islamic doctrine is the main factor for man’s accountability in his/her actions throughout life. Actions taken by people exercising free will are counted on the Day of Judgement because they are their own; however, the free will happens with the permission of God.[244]

Others[edit]

The philosopher Søren Kierkegaard claimed that divine omnipotence cannot be separated from divine goodness.[245] As a truly omnipotent and good being, God could create beings with true freedom over God. Furthermore, God would voluntarily do so because «the greatest good… which can be done for a being, greater than anything else that one can do for it, is to be truly free.»[246] Alvin Plantinga’s free-will defense is a contemporary expansion of this theme, adding how God, free will, and evil are consistent.[247]

Some philosophers follow William of Ockham in holding that necessity and possibility are defined with respect to a given point in time and a given matrix of empirical circumstances, and so something that is merely possible from the perspective of one observer may be necessary from the perspective of an omniscient.[248] Some philosophers follow Philo of Alexandria, a philosopher known for his homocentrism, in holding that free will is a feature of a human’s soul, and thus that non-human animals lack free will.[249]

See also[edit]

  • Agency in Mormonism
  • Angst#Existentialist angst
  • Argument from free will
  • Buridan’s ass
  • De libero arbitrio – early treatise about the freedom of will by Augustine of Hippo
  • Free will theorem
  • Locus of control
  • Karma
  • Prevenient grace
  • Problem of mental causation
  • Prospection
  • Superdeterminism
  • True Will
  • Voluntarism (philosophy)

References[edit]

Citations[edit]

  1. ^ Carus, Paul (1910). «Person and personality». In Hegeler, Edward C. (ed.). The Monist. Vol. 20. Chicago: Open Court Publishing Company. p. 369. To state it briefly, we define «free will» as a will unimpeded by any compulsion.
  2. ^ Baumeister, Roy F.; Monroe, Andrew E. (2014). Recent Research on Free Will. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology. Vol. 50. pp. 1–52. doi:10.1016/B978-0-12-800284-1.00001-1. ISBN 9780128002841.
  3. ^ a b Bobzien, Susanne (1998). Determinism and freedom in Stoic philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-823794-5. Retrieved 2015-12-09. …Aristotle and Epictetus: In the latter authors it was the fact that nothing hindered us from doing or choosing something that made us have control over them. In Alexander’s account, the terms are understood differently: what makes us have control over things is the fact that we are causally undetermined in our decision and thus can freely decide between doing/choosing or not doing/choosing them.
  4. ^ An argument by Rudolf Carnap described by: C. James Goodwin (2009). Research In Psychology: Methods and Design (6th ed.). Wiley. p. 11. ISBN 978-0-470-52278-3.
  5. ^ Robert C Bishop (2010). «§28.2: Compatibilism and incompatibilism». In Raymond Y. Chiao; Marvin L. Cohen; Anthony J. Leggett; William D. Phillips; Charles L. Harper, Jr. (eds.). Visions of Discovery: New Light on Physics, Cosmology, and Consciousness. Cambridge University Press. p. 603. ISBN 978-0-521-88239-2.
  6. ^ See, for example, Janet Richards (2001). «The root of the free will problem: kinds of non-existence». Human Nature After Darwin: A Philosophical Introduction. Routledge. pp. 142 ff. ISBN 978-0-415-21243-4.
  7. ^ McKenna, Michael; Coates, D. Justin (2015). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy – via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  8. ^ Bobzien, Susanne (2000). «Did Epicurus discover the free-will problem?». Retrieved 2015-12-09.
  9. ^ Schopenhauer, A. «What is freedom?». On the Freedom of the Will.
  10. ^ Hence the notion of contingency appeared as the very opposition of necessity, so that wherever a thing is considered dependent or relies upon another thing, it is contingent and thus not necessary.
  11. ^
    Thomas Nagel (1989). «Freedom». The View From Nowhere. Oxford University Press. p. 112. ISBN 978-0-19-505644-0. Nothing that might be a solution has yet been described. This is not a case where there are several possible candidate solutions and we don’t know which is correct. It is a case where nothing believable has (to my knowledge) been proposed.
  12. ^
    John R Searle (2013). «The problem of free will». Freedom and Neurobiology: Reflections on Free Will, Language, and Political Power. Columbia University Press. p. 37. ISBN 978-0-231-51055-4. The persistence of the traditional free will problem in philosophy seems to me something of a scandal. After all these centuries…it does not seem to me that we have made very much progress.
  13. ^
    Gregg D Caruso (2012). Free Will and Consciousness: A Determinist Account of the Illusion of Free Will. Lexington Books. p. 8. ISBN 978-0-7391-7136-3. One of the strongest supports for the free choice thesis is the unmistakable intuition of virtually every human being that he is free to make the choices he does and that the deliberations leading to those choices are also free flowing..
  14. ^
    Corliss Lamont (1969). Freedom of choice affirmed. Beacon Press. p. 38. ISBN 9780826404763.
  15. ^ a b c d e Azim F Shariff; Jonathan Schooler; Kathleen D Vohs (2008). «The hazards of claiming to have solved the hard problem of free will». In John Baer; James C. Kaufman; Roy F. Baumeister (eds.). Are We Free? Psychology and Free Will. Oxford University Press. pp. 183, 190–93. ISBN 978-0-19-518963-6.
  16. ^
    TW Clark (1999). «Fear of mechanism: A compatibilist critique of The Volitional Brain«. Journal of Consciousness Studies. 6 (8–9): 279–93. Feelings or intuitions per se never count as self-evident proof of anything. Quoted by Shariff, Schooler & Vohs: The hazards of claiming to have solved the hard problem of free will For full text on line see this Archived 2013-05-05 at the Wayback Machine.
  17. ^ a b Max Velmans (2002). «How Could Conscious Experiences Affect Brains?». Journal of Consciousness Studies. 9 (11): 2–29.
  18. ^ William James (1896). «The dilemma of determinism». The Will to believe, and other essays in popular philosophy. Longmans, Green. pp. 145 ff.
  19. ^
    John A Bargh (2007-11-16). «Free will is un-natural» (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 2012-09-03. Retrieved 2012-08-21. Are behaviors, judgments, and other higher mental processes the product of free conscious choices, as influenced by internal psychological states (motives, preferences, etc.), or are those higher mental processes determined by those states? Also found in John A Bargh (2008). «Chapter 7: Free will is un-natural». In John Baer; James C. Kaufman; Roy F. Baumeister (eds.). Are We Free? Psychology and Free Will. Oxford University Press. pp. 128 ff. ISBN 978-0-19-518963-6.
  20. ^
    Paul Russell (2002). «Chapter 1: Logic, «liberty», and the metaphysics of responsibility». Freedom and Moral Sentiment: Hume’s Way of Naturalizing Responsibility. Oxford University Press. p. 14. ISBN 978-0-19-515290-6. …the well-known dilemma of determinism. One horn of this dilemma is the argument that if an action was caused or necessitated, then it could not have been done freely, and hence the agent is not responsible for it. The other horn is the argument that if the action was not caused, then it is inexplicable and random, and thus it cannot be attributed to the agent, and hence, again, the agent cannot be responsible for it…. Whether we affirm or deny necessity and determinism, it is impossible to make any coherent sense of moral freedom and responsibility.
  21. ^ Azim F Shariff; Jonathan Schooler; Kathleen D Vohs (2008). «Chapter 9: The hazards of claiming to have solved the hard problem of free will». In John Baer; James C. Kaufman; Roy F. Baumeister (eds.). Are We Free? Psychology and Free Will. Oxford University Press. p. 193. ISBN 978-0-19-518963-6.
  22. ^
    Max Velmans (2009). Understanding Consciousness (2nd ed.). Taylor & Francis. p. 11. ISBN 978-0-415-42515-5.
  23. ^ Strawson, Galen (2011) [1998]. «Free will. In E. Craig (Ed.)». Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy. London: Routledge. Archived from the original on 26 August 2012. Retrieved 12 December 2012.
  24. ^ a b O’Connor, Timothy (Oct 29, 2010). «Free Will». In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition). Retrieved 2013-01-15.
  25. ^
    Joshua Greene; Jonathan Cohen (2011). «For the law, neuroscience changes nothing and everything». In Judy Illes; Barbara J. Sahakian (eds.). Oxford Handbook of Neuroethics. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-162091-1. Free will, compatibilists argue, is here to stay, and the challenge for science is to figure out exactly how it works and not to peddle silly arguments that deny the undeniable (Dennett 2003) referring to a critique of Libet’s experiments by DC Dennett (2003). «The self as a responding and responsible artifact» (PDF). Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences. 1001 (1): 39–50. Bibcode:2003NYASA1001…39D. doi:10.1196/annals.1279.003. PMID 14625354. S2CID 46156580. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2009-11-09.
  26. ^
    Walter J. Freeman (2000). How Brains Make Up Their Minds. Columbia University Press. p. 5. ISBN 978-0-231-12008-1. Instead of postulating a universal law of causality and then having to deny the possibility of choice, we start with the premise that freedom of choice exists, and then we seek to explain causality as a property of brains.
  27. ^ a b McKenna, Michael (2009). «Compatibilism». In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter ed.).
  28. ^ Libet, Benjamin (2003). «Can Conscious Experience affect brain Activity?». Journal of Consciousness Studies. 10 (12): 24–28. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.5.2852.
  29. ^ a b c d e Kane, Robert; John Martin Fischer; Derk Pereboom; Manuel Vargas (2007). Four Views on Free Will (Libertarianism). Oxford: Blackwell Publishing. p. 39. ISBN 978-1-4051-3486-6.
  30. ^ a b c Vihvelin, Kadri (2011). «Arguments for Incompatibilism». In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2011 ed.).
  31. ^ a b c d Zagzebski, Linda (2011). «Foreknowledge and Free Will». In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2011 ed.). See also McKenna, Michael (2009). «Compatibilism». In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2009 ed.).
  32. ^ a b van Invagen, P. (1983). An Essay on Free Will. Oxford: Clarendon Press. ISBN 0-19-824924-1.
  33. ^ a b c Pereboom, D. (2003). Living without Free Will. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-79198-4.
  34. ^ Fischer, J.M. (1983). «Incompatibilism». Philosophical Studies. 43: 121–37. doi:10.1007/BF01112527.
  35. ^ a b Dennett, D. (1984). Elbow Room: The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting. Bradford Books. ISBN 978-0-262-54042-1.
  36. ^ Kane, R. (1996). The Significance of Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-512656-4.
  37. ^ Campbell, C.A. (1957). On Selfhood and Godhood. London: George Allen and Unwin. ISBN 0-415-29624-2.
  38. ^ Sartre, J.P. (1943). Being and Nothingness (reprint 1993 ed.). New York: Washington Square Press. Sartre also provides a psychological version of the argument by claiming that if man’s actions are not his own, he would be in bad faith.
  39. ^ Fischer, R.M. (1994). The Metaphysics of Free Will. Oxford: Blackwell.
  40. ^ Bok, H. (1998). Freedom and Responsibility. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-01566-X.
  41. ^ Ginet, Carl (1966). «Might We Have No Choice». In Lehrer, Keith (ed.). Freedom and Determinisim. Random House. pp. 87–104.
  42. ^ a b van Inwagen, P.; Zimmerman, D. (1998). Metaphysics: The Big Questions. Oxford: Blackwell.
  43. ^ Inwagen, P., How to think about free will, p. 15, archived from the original on 2008-09-11
  44. ^ Lewis, D. (2008). «Are We Free to Break the Laws?». Theoria. 47 (3): 113–21. doi:10.1111/j.1755-2567.1981.tb00473.x. S2CID 170811962.
  45. ^ a b c
    Strawson, Galen (2010). Freedom and belief (Revised ed.). Oxford University Press. p. 6. ISBN 978-0-19-924750-9.
  46. ^ Fischer, John Martin (2009). «Chapter 2: Compatibilism». Four Views on Free Will (Great Debates in Philosophy). Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 44 ff. ISBN 978-1-4051-3486-6.
  47. ^
    Alex Rosenberg (2005). Philosophy Of Science: A Contemporary Introduction (2nd ed.). Psychology Press. p. 8. ISBN 978-0-415-34317-6.
  48. ^ a b Niels Bohr. «The Atomic Theory and the Fundamental Principles underlying the Description of Nature; Based on a lecture to the Scandinavian Meeting of Natural Scientists and published in Danish in Fysisk Tidsskrift in 1929. First published in English in 1934 by Cambridge University Press.«. The Information Philosopher, dedicated to the new information philosophy. Robert O. Doyle, publisher. Retrieved 2012-09-14. … any observation necessitates an interference with the course of the phenomena, which is of such a nature that it deprives us of the foundation underlying the causal mode of description.
  49. ^ a b
    Niels Bohr (April 1, 1933). Light and Life. Nature. Vol. 131. pp. 457–459. Bibcode:1933Natur.131..457B. doi:10.1038/131457a0. ISBN 978-0-444-89972-9. S2CID 4080545. For instance, it is impossible, from our standpoint, to attach an unambiguous meaning to the view sometimes expressed that the probability of the occurrence of certain atomic processes in the body might be under the direct influence of the will. In fact, according to the generalized interpretation of the psycho-physical parallelism, the freedom of the will must be considered a feature of conscious life that corresponds to functions of the organism that not only evade a causal mechanical description, but resist even a physical analysis carried to the extent required for an unambiguous application of the statistical laws of atomic mechanics. Without entering into metaphysical speculations, I may perhaps add that an analysis of the very concept of explanation would, naturally, begin and end with a renunciation as to explaining our own conscious activity. Full text on line at us.archive.org.
  50. ^ Lewis, E.R.; MacGregor, R.J. (2006). «On Indeterminism, Chaos, and Small Number Particle Systems in the Brain» (PDF). Journal of Integrative Neuroscience. 5 (2): 223–47. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.361.7065. doi:10.1142/S0219635206001112. PMID 16783870. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2011-06-08.
  51. ^ G.H.R. Parkinson (2012). «determinism». Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. Taylor & Francis. pp. 891–92. ISBN 978-0-415-00323-0. Retrieved 26 December 2012.
  52. ^ a b c Vihvelin, Kadri. «Arguments for Incompatibilism». In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2003 ed.).
  53. ^ a b c Raymond J. VanArragon (2010). Key Terms in Philosophy of Religion. Continuum International Publishing Group. p. 21. ISBN 978-1-4411-3867-5. Retrieved 22 December 2012.
  54. ^ a b Eshleman, Andrew (2009). «Moral Responsibility». In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2009 ed.).
  55. ^ Suppes, P. (1993). «The Transcendental Character of Determinism». Midwest Studies in Philosophy. 18: 242–57. doi:10.1111/j.1475-4975.1993.tb00266.x. S2CID 14586058.
  56. ^
    The view of scientific determinism goes back to Laplace: «We ought to regard the present state of the universe as the effect of its antecedent state.» For further discussion see John T Roberts (2006). «Determinism». In Sahotra Sarkar; Jessica Pfeifer; Justin Garson (eds.). The Philosophy of Science: An Encyclopedia. N–Z, Indeks, Volume 1. Psychology Press. pp. 197 ff. ISBN 978-0-415-93927-0.
  57. ^ Fischer, John Martin (1989). God, Foreknowledge and Freedom. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. ISBN 1-55786-857-3.
  58. ^ Watt, Montgomery (1948). Free-Will and Predestination in Early Islam. London: Luzac & Co.
  59. ^ a b c d Randolph, Clarke (2008). «Incompatibilist (Nondeterministic) Theories of Free Will». In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 ed.).
  60. ^ a b Robert Kane (2005). Free Will. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-514970-8. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  61. ^ Paul Henri Thiry, Baron d’Holbach, System of Nature; or, the Laws of the Moral and Physical World (London, 1797), Vol. 1, p. 92
  62. ^ Danko D. Georgiev (2021). «Quantum propensities in the brain cortex and free will». Biosystems. 208: 104474. arXiv:2107.06572. doi:10.1016/j.biosystems.2021.104474. ISSN 0303-2647. PMID 34242745. S2CID 235785726. Free will is the capacity of conscious agents to choose a future course of action among several available physical alternatives.
  63. ^ Christoph Lumer; Sandro Nannini (2007). Intentionality, Deliberation and Autonomy: The Action-Theoretic Basis of Practical Philosophy. Ashgate Publishing, Ltd. ISBN 978-0-7546-6058-3. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  64. ^ Hugh McCann (1998). The Works of Agency: On Human Action, Will, and Freedom. Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-0-8014-8583-1. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  65. ^ Laura Waddell Ekstrom (2000). Free Will: A Philosophical Study. Westview Press. ISBN 978-0-8133-9093-2. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  66. ^ Alfred R. Mele (2006). Free Will and Luck. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-530504-3. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  67. ^ Daniel Clement Dennett (1981). Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-54037-7. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  68. ^ L. Peterson, Michael; Fischer, John Martin (1995). «Libertarianism and Avoidability: A Reply to Widerker». Faith and Philosophy. 12: 119–25. doi:10.5840/faithphil199512123. ISSN 0739-7046.
  69. ^ Mark Balaguer (1999). «Libertarianism as a Scientifically Reputable View». Philosophical Studies. 93 (2): 189–211. doi:10.1023/a:1004218827363. S2CID 169483672.
  70. ^ Robert Nozick (1981). Philosophical Explanations. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-66479-1. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  71. ^ Richard Sorabji (1980). Necessity, Cause, and Blame: Perspectives on Aristotle’s Theory. Duckworth. ISBN 978-0-7156-1549-2. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  72. ^ Peter Van Inwagen (1983). An Essay on Free Will. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-824924-5. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  73. ^ Ted Honderich (1973). Essays on Freedom of Action:Towards a Reasonable Libertarianism. Routledge & Kegan Paul. pp. 33–61. ISBN 978-0-7100-7392-1. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  74. ^ John R. Searle (2001). Rationality in Action. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-69282-3. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  75. ^ Robert Kane (1996). The Significance of Free Will. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-510550-6. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  76. ^ Lewis, C.S. (1947). Miracles. p. 24. ISBN 978-0-688-17369-2.
  77. ^ Kane, Robert (2007). «Libertarianism». Four Views on Free Will (Great Debates in Philosophy). Wiley-Blackwell. p. 9. ISBN 978-1-4051-3486-6. It would seem that undetermined events in the brain or body would occur spontaneously and would be more likely to undermine our freedom rather than enhance it.
  78. ^ Roderick M. Chisholm (2004). Person And Object: A Metaphysical Study. Psychology Press. ISBN 978-0-415-29593-2. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  79. ^ Randolph Clarke (1996). «Agent Causation and Event Causation in the Production of Free Action». Philosophical Topics. 24 (2): 19–48. doi:10.5840/philtopics19962427.
  80. ^ Alan Donagan (1987). Choice: The Essential Element in Human Action. Routledge & Kegan Paul. ISBN 978-0-7102-1168-2. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  81. ^ Timothy O’Connor (2005). Robert Kane (ed.). Oxford Hb Of Free Will:Libertarian Views: Dualist and Agent-Causal Theories. Oxford Handbooks Online. pp. 337–355. ISBN 978-0-19-517854-8. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  82. ^ William L. Rowe (1991). Thomas Reid on Freedom and Morality. Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-0-8014-2557-8. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  83. ^ Richard Taylor (1966). Action and purpose. Prentice-Hall. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  84. ^ John Thorp (1980). Free will: a defence against neurophysiological determinism. Routledge & Kegan Paul. ISBN 9780710005656. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  85. ^ Michael J. Zimmerman (1984). An essay on human action. P. Lang. ISBN 978-0-8204-0122-5. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  86. ^ George Berkeley; Jonathan Dancy (1998). A treatise concerning the principles of human knowledge. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-875160-1. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  87. ^ Thomas Reid (2012). Essays on the Active Powers of the Human Mind; An Inquiry Into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense; And an Essay on Quantity. HardPress. ISBN 978-1-4077-2950-3. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  88. ^ Locke, J. (1689). An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1998, ed). Book II, Chap. XXI, Sec. 17. Penguin Classics, Toronto.
  89. ^ a b Strawson, G. (1998, 2004). «Free will». In E. Craig (ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge. Retrieved August 17, 2006, ((online)) Archived 2007-08-25 at the Wayback Machine
  90. ^ Groblacher, Simon; Paterek, Tomasz; Kaltenbaek, Rainer; Brukner, Caslav; Zukowski, Marek; Aspelmeyer, Markus; Zeilinger, Anton (2007). «An experimental test of non-local realism». Nature. 446 (7138): 871–75. arXiv:0704.2529. Bibcode:2007Natur.446..871G. doi:10.1038/nature05677. ISSN 0028-0836. PMID 17443179. S2CID 4412358.
  91. ^ Ben C. Blackwell (2011). Christosis: Pauline Soteriology in Light of Deification in Irenaeus and Cyril of Alexandria. Mohr Siebeck. p. 50. ISBN 978-3-16-151672-6. Retrieved 8 December 2012.
  92. ^ a b c McKewan, Jaclyn (2009). «Evolution, Chemical». In H. James Birx» (ed.). Predeterminism. Encyclopedia of Time: Science, Philosophy, Theology, & Culture. SAGE Publications. pp. 1035–36. doi:10.4135/9781412963961.n191. ISBN 978-1-4129-4164-8.
  93. ^ «Predeterminism». Oxford Dictionaries. Oxford Dictionaries. 2010. Archived from the original on September 4, 2012. Retrieved 20 December 2012.. See also «Predeterminism». Collins English Dictionary. Collins. Retrieved 20 December 2012.
  94. ^ «Some Varieties of Free Will and Determinism». Philosophy 302: Ethics. philosophy.lander.edu. 10 September 2009. Retrieved 19 December 2012. Predeterminism: the philosophical and theological view that combines God with determinism. On this doctrine events throughout eternity have been foreordained by some supernatural power in a causal sequence.
  95. ^ See for example Hooft, G. (2001). «How does god play dice? (Pre-)determinism at the Planck scale». arXiv:hep-th/0104219. Bibcode:2001hep.th….4219T. Predeterminism is here defined by the assumption that the experimenter’s ‘free will’ in deciding what to measure (such as his choice to measure the x- or the y-component of an electron’s spin), is in fact limited by deterministic laws, hence not free at all , and Sukumar, CV (1996). «A new paradigm for science and architecture». City. 1 (1–2): 181–83. doi:10.1080/13604819608900044. Quantum Theory provided a beautiful description of the behaviour of isolated atoms and nuclei and small aggregates of elementary particles. Modern science recognized that predisposition rather than predeterminism is what is widely prevalent in nature.
  96. ^ Borst, C. (1992). «Leibniz and the compatibilist account of free will». Studia Leibnitiana. 24 (1): 49–58. JSTOR 40694201. Leibniz presents a clear case of a philosopher who does not think that predeterminism requires universal causal determinism
  97. ^ Far Western Philosophy of Education Society (1971). Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Far Western Philosophy of Education Society. Far Western Philosophy of Education Society. p. 12. Retrieved 20 December 2012. «Determinism» is, in essence, the position holding that all behavior is caused by prior behavior. «Predeterminism» is the position holding that all behavior is caused by conditions predating behavior altogether (such impersonal boundaries as «the human conditions», instincts, the will of God, inherent knowledge, fate, and such).
  98. ^ «Predeterminism». Merriam-Webster Dictionary. Merriam-Webster, Incorporated. Retrieved 20 December 2012. See for example Ormond, A.T. (1894). «Freedom and psycho-genesis». Psychological Review. 1 (3): 217–29. doi:10.1037/h0065249. The problem of predeterminism is one that involves the factors of heredity and environment, and the point to be debated here is the relation of the present self that chooses to these predetermining agencies, and Garris, M.D.; et al. (1992). «A Platform for Evolving Genetic Automata for Text Segmentation (GNATS)». Science of Artificial Neural Networks. 1710: 714–24. Bibcode:1992SPIE.1710..714G. doi:10.1117/12.140132. S2CID 62639035. However, predeterminism is not completely avoided. If the codes within the genotype are not designed properly, then the organisms being evolved will be fundamentally handicapped.
  99. ^ Sherman, H. (1981). «Marx and determinism». Journal of Economic Issues. 15 (1): 61–71. doi:10.1080/00213624.1981.11503814. JSTOR 4224996. Many religions of the world have considered that the path of history is predetermined by God or Fate. On this basis, many believe that what will happen will happen, and they accept their destiny with fatalism.
  100. ^ Anne Lockyer Jordan; Anne Lockyer Jordan Neil Lockyer Edwin Tate; Neil Lockyer; Edwin Tate (2004). Philosophy of Religion for A Level OCR Edition. Nelson Thornes. p. 211. ISBN 978-0-7487-8078-5. Retrieved 22 December 2012.
  101. ^ A. Pabl Iannone (2001). «determinism». Dictionary of World Philosophy. Taylor & Francis. p. 194. ISBN 978-0-415-17995-9. Retrieved 22 December 2012.
  102. ^ Wentzel Van Huyssteen (2003). «theological determinism». Encyclopedia of science and religion. Vol. 1. Macmillan Reference. p. 217. ISBN 978-0-02-865705-9. Retrieved 22 December 2012.
  103. ^ Boethius. «Book V, Prose vi». The Consolation of Philosophy.
  104. ^ Aquinas, St. Thomas (1923). «Ia, q. 14, art 13.». Summa Theologica. See Summa Theologica
  105. ^ C.S. Lewis (1980). Mere Christianity. Touchstone:New York. p. 149.
  106. ^ Linda Trinkaus Zagzebski (1996). «chapter 6, section 2.1». The Dilemma of Freedom and Foreknowledge. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-510763-0. Retrieved 22 December 2012.
  107. ^ a b See for example: Sandro Nannini (2004). «Chapter 5: Mental causation and intentionality in a mind naturalizing theory». In Alberto Peruzzi (ed.). Mind and Causality. John Benjamins Publishing. pp. 69 ff. ISBN 978-1-58811-475-4.
  108. ^ Karl Raimund Popper (1999). «Notes of a realist on the body-mind problem». All Life is Problem Solving (A lecture given in Mannheim, 8 May 1972 ed.). Psychology Press. pp. 23 ff. ISBN 978-0-415-17486-2. The body-mind relationship…includes the problem of man’s position in the physical world…’World 1′. The world of conscious human processes I shall call ‘World 2’, and the world of the objective creations of the human mind I shall call ‘World 3’.
  109. ^
    See Josh Weisberg. «The hard problem of consciousness». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. or Robert Van Gulick (Jan 14, 2014). «Consciousness». In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). Consciousness: §9.9 Non-physical theories. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  110. ^
    E. Bruce Goldstein (2010). Sensation and Perception (12th ed.). Cengage Learning. p. 39. ISBN 978-0-495-60149-4.
  111. ^
    Quote from Tor Nørretranders (1998). «Preface». The user illusion: Cutting consciousness down to size (Jonathan Sydenham translation of Maerk verden 1991 ed.). Penguin Books. p. ix. ISBN 978-0-14-023012-3.
  112. ^ Meyer, Susan Sauve (2012). Aristotle on Moral Responsibility. Oxford.
  113. ^ Bobzien, Susanne, Freedom and Determinism in Stoic Philosophy, Oxford 1998, Chapter 6.
  114. ^ a b McKenna, Michael. «Compatibilism». In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 200 ed.).
  115. ^ a b Frankfurt, H. (1971). «Freedom of the Will and the Concept of the Person». Journal of Philosophy. 68 (1): 5–20. doi:10.2307/2024717. JSTOR 2024717.
  116. ^ Hobbes, T. (1651) Leviathan Chapter XXI.: «Of the liberty of subjects» (1968 edition). London: Penguin Books.
  117. ^ Hume, D. (1740). A Treatise of Human Nature Section VIII.: «Of liberty and necessity» (1967 edition). Oxford University Press, Oxford. ISBN 0-87220-230-5
  118. ^ a b Roy F Baumeister; Matthew T Galliot; Dianne M Tice (2008). «Chapter 23: Free Willpower: A limited resource theory of volition, choice and self-regulation». In Ezequiel Morsella; John A. Bargh; Peter M. Gollwitzer (eds.). Oxford Handbook of Human Action (Volume 2 of Social Cognition and Social Neuroscience ed.). Oxford University Press. pp. 487 ff. ISBN 978-0-19-530998-0. The nonconscious forms of self-regulation may follow different causal principles and do not rely on the same resources as the conscious and effortful ones.
  119. ^
    Roy F Baumeister; Matthew T Galliot; Dianne M Tice (2008). «Chapter 23: Free Willpower: A limited resource theory of volition, choice and self-regulation». In Ezequiel Morsella; John A. Bargh; Peter M. Gollwitzer (eds.). Oxford Handbook of Human Action (Volume 2 of Social Cognition and Social Neuroscience ed.). Oxford University Press. pp. 487 ff. ISBN 978-0-19-530998-0. Yet perhaps not all conscious volition is an illusion. Our findings suggest that the traditional folk notions of willpower and character strength have some legitimate basis in genuine phenomena.
  120. ^ Saul Smilansky (2000). Free Will and Illusion. Oxford University Press. p. 96. ISBN 978-0-19-825018-0. Retrieved 6 February 2013.
  121. ^ Gallagher, S. (2000). «Philosophical conceptions of the self: implications for cognitive science». Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 4 (1): 14–21. doi:10.1016/s1364-6613(99)01417-5. PMID 10637618. S2CID 451912.
  122. ^ Watson, D. (1982). Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press.
  123. ^ Fischer, John Martin; Ravizza, Mark (1998). Responsibility and Control: An Essay on Moral Responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  124. ^ a b Dennett, D. (2003) Freedom Evolves. Viking Books. ISBN 0-670-03186-0
  125. ^ Kane, R. The Oxford Handbook to Free Will. Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-513336-6.
  126. ^ A key exponent of this view was Willard van Orman Quine. See Hylton, Peter (Apr 30, 2010). «Willard van Orman Quine». In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2010 Edition).
  127. ^

    A thoughtful list of careful distinctions regarding the application of empirical science to these issues is found in Stoljar, Daniel (Sep 9, 2009). «Physicalism: §12 – Physicalism and the physicalist world picture». In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2009 Edition).

  128. ^
    Nora D Volkow; Joanna S Fowler; Gene-Jack Wang (2007). «The addicted human brain: insights from imaging studies». In Andrew R Marks; Ushma S Neill (eds.). Science In Medicine: The JCI Textbook Of Molecular Medicine. Jones & Bartlett Learning. pp. 1061 ff. ISBN 978-0-7637-5083-1.
  129. ^ Claudio Costa. Lines of Thought: Rethinking Philosophical Assumptions CSP, 2014, Ch. 7
  130. ^ Ridge, Michael (3 February 2014). «Moral Non-Naturalism». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 3 June 2019.
  131. ^ Lemos, John (2002). «Evolution and Free Will: A Defense of Darwinian Non–naturalism». Metaphilosophy. 33 (4): 468–482. doi:10.1111/1467-9973.00240. ISSN 1467-9973.
  132. ^ Nida-Rümelin, Julian (1 January 2019). «The Reasons Account of Free Will A Libertarian-Compatibilist Hybrid». Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosphie. 105 (1): 3–10. doi:10.25162/arsp-2019-0001. S2CID 155641763.
  133. ^ Stump, Eleonore (1996). «Libertarian Freedom and the Principle of Alternative Possibilities». In Howard-Snyder, Daniel; Jordan, Jeff (eds.). Faith, Freedom, and Rationality. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. pp. 73–88.
  134. ^ Honderich, T. (2001). «Determinism as True, Compatibilism and Incompatibilism as Both False and the Real Problem». In Kane, Robert (ed.). The Free Will Handbook. Oxford University Press.
  135. ^ Benedict de Spinoza (2008). «Part III: On the origin and nature of the emotions; Postulates (Proposition II, Note)». In R.H.M. Elwes, trans (ed.). The Ethics (Original work published 1677 ed.). Digireads.com Publishing. p. 54. ISBN 978-1-4209-3114-3.
  136. ^ Hume, D. (1765). An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Indianapolis: Hacket Publishing Co. Second edition. 1993. ISBN 0-87220-230-5
  137. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation, Vol. 1., trans. E. F. J. Payne, p. 113-114
  138. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur, On the Freedom of the Will, Oxford: Basil Blackwell ISBN 0-631-14552-4
  139. ^ Harris, Sam (6 March 2012). Free Will. Simon and Schuster. p. 5. ISBN 978-1451683400.
  140. ^ Steiner, Rudolf. «Arthur Schopenhauers sämtliche Werke in zwölf Bänden. Mit Einleitung von Dr. Rudolf Steiner, Stuttgart: Verlag der J.G. Cotta’schen Buchhandlung Nachfolger, o.J. (1894–96)» (in German). Archived from the original on 2018-10-06. Retrieved 2007-08-02.
  141. ^ Keimpe Algra (1999). «Chapter VI: The Chyrsippean notion of fate: soft determinism». The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. p. 529. ISBN 978-0-521-25028-3.
  142. ^ Steiner, R. (1964). Rudolf Steiner Press, London, 1964, 1970, 1972, 1979, 230 pp., translated from the 12th German edition of 1962 by Michael Wilson. ((online))
  143. ^ See Bricklin, Jonathan, «A Variety of Religious Experience: William James and the Non-Reality of Free Will», in Libet (1999), The Volitional Brain: Toward a Neuroscience of Free Will (Thorverton UK: Imprint Academic).
  144. ^ a b James, W. (1907) Pragmatism (1979 edition). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
  145. ^
    Robert Kane (1998). «Notes to pages 74–81, note 22». The significance of free will (Paperback ed.). Oxford University Press. p. 226. ISBN 978-0-19-512656-3.
  146. ^ CM Lorkowski (November 7, 2010). «David Hume: Causation». Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  147. ^ Kant argued that, in order that human life is not just a «dream» (a random or projected by subjects juxtaposition of moments), the temporality of event A as before or after B must submit to a rule. An established order then implies the existence of some necessary conditions and causes, that is: sufficient bases (a so-called sufficient reason is the coincidence of all the necessary conditions). Without established causality, both in subject and in the external world, the passing of time would be impossible, because it is essentially directional. See online text of his proof
  148. ^ Schopenhauer, who by the way continued and simplified Kant’s system, argued (among others basing on optical illusions and the «initial processing») that it is the intellect or even the brain what generates the image of the world out of something else, by concluding from effects, e.g. optical, about appropriate causes, e.g. concrete physical objects. Intellect in his works is strictly connected with recognizing causes and effects and associating them, it is somewhat close to the contemporary view of cerebral cortex and formation of associations. The intellectuality of all perception implied then of course that causality is rooted in the world, precedes and enables experience. See online text of his proof
  149. ^
    R Kevin Hill (2003). «Chapter 7: The critique of morality: The three pillars of Kantian ethics». Nietzsche’s Critiques: The Kantian Foundations of His Thought (Paperback ed.). pp. 196–201. ISBN 978-0-19-928552-5.
  150. ^
    Herbert James Paton (1971). «§2 Moral judgements are a priori«. The Categorical Imperative: A Study in Kant’s Moral Philosophy. University of Pennsylvania Press. p. 20. ISBN 978-0-8122-1023-1.
  151. ^ Freeman, Walter J. (2009). «Consciousness, intentionality and causality». In Susan Pockett; WP Banks; Shaun Gallagher (eds.). Does Consciousness Cause Behavior?. MIT Press. p. 88. ISBN 978-0-262-51257-2. Circular causality departs so strongly from the classical tenets of necessity, invariance, and precise temporal order that the only reason to call it that is to satisfy the human habitual need for causes…. The very strong appeal of agency to explain events may come from the subjective experience of cause and effect that develops early in human life, before the acquisition of language…the question I raise here is whether brains share this property with other material objects in the world.
  152. ^ Staley, Kevin M. (2005). «Aquinas: Compatibilist or Libertarian» (PDF). The Saint Anselm Journal. 2 (2): 74. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2015-12-21. Retrieved 2015-12-09.
  153. ^ Hartung, Christopher (May 2013). Thomas Aquinas on Free Will (Thesis). University of Delaware. Retrieved 2015-12-09.
  154. ^

    A discussion of the roles of will, intellect and passions in Aquinas’ teachings is found in Stump, Eleonore (2003). «Intellect and will». Aquinas, Arguments of the philosophers series. Routledge (Psychology Press). pp. 278 ff. ISBN 978-0-415-02960-5.

  155. ^ Timothy O’Connor (Oct 29, 2010). «Free Will». In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition). The Metaphysics Research Lab Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University. Philosophers who distinguish freedom of action and freedom of will do so because our success in carrying out our ends depends in part on factors wholly beyond our control. Furthermore, there are always external constraints on the range of options we can meaningfully try to undertake. As the presence or absence of these conditions and constraints are not (usually) our responsibility, it is plausible that the central loci of our responsibility are our choices, or «willings».
  156. ^ «Catholic Encyclopedia: Appetite». Newadvent.org. 1907. Retrieved 2012-08-13.
  157. ^ «Summa Theologica: Free-will (Prima Pars, Q. 83)». Newadvent.org. Retrieved 2012-08-13.
  158. ^ Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, Q83 A1.
  159. ^ Further discussion of this compatibilistic theory can be found in Thomas’ Summa contra gentiles, Book III about Providence, c. 88–91 (260–267), where it is postulated that everything has its cause and it is again and again in detail referred also to all individual choices of man etc., even refuting opposite views. Here the online text of the Summa Archived 2017-11-23 at the Wayback Machine. In order to avoid, at least in concept, the absolution of man of any guilt he then notes the contingency of all that takes place, i.e. lack of direct necessity from God strictly with regard to a concrete («contingent») act. A typical choice was not separately ordained to be so-and-so by God; St. Thomas says the choice is not necessary, but in fact that apparently means it was contingent with regard to God and the law of nature (as a specific case that could have not existed in other circumstances), and necessary with regard to its direct previous cause in will and intellect. (The contingency, or fortuity, is even intuitive under modern chaos theory, where one can try to show that more and more developed products appearing in the evolution of a universe or, simpler, an automaton are chaotic with regard to its principles.)
  160. ^
    Paul Russell; Oisin Deery (2013). «I. The free will problem – real or illusory». The Philosophy of Free Will: Essential Readings from the Contemporary Debates. Oxford University Press. p. 5. ISBN 978-0-19-973339-2.
  161. ^ a b c Gier, Nicholas and Kjellberg, Paul. «Buddhism and the Freedom of the Will: Pali and Mahayanist Responses» in Freedom and Determinism. Campbell, Joseph Keim; O’Rourke, Michael; and Shier, David. 2004. MIT Press
  162. ^ Flood, Gavin (2004). The ascetic self: subjectivity, memory and tradition. Cambridge University Press. p. 73. ISBN 978-0-521-60401-7.
  163. ^ Koller, J. (2007). Asian Philosophies (5th ed.). Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0-13-092385-1.
  164. ^ a b c Swami Vivekananda (1907) «Sayings and utterances». ramakrishnavivekananda.info.
  165. ^ Boniolo, G.; Vidali, P. (1999). Filosofia della Scienza. Milan: Mondadori. ISBN 88-424-9359-7.
  166. ^ Hoefer, Carl (2008). «Causal Determinism». Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2008-11-01.
  167. ^ Vedral, Vlatko (2006-11-18). «Is the Universe Deterministic?». New Scientist. 192 (2578): 52–55. doi:10.1016/S0262-4079(06)61122-6. Physics is simply unable to resolve the question of free will, although, if anything, it probably leans towards determinism.
  168. ^ Honderich, E. «Determinism as True, Compatibilism and Incompatibilism as Both False, and the Real Problem». Ucl.ac.uk. Retrieved 2010-11-21.
  169. ^ «The Quantum Physics of Free Will». Scientific American.
  170. ^ «Infidels. «Metaphysical Freedom»«. Infidels.org. 25 August 2000. Retrieved 2010-11-21.
  171. ^ Pinel, P.J. (1990). Biopsychology. Prentice Hall Inc. ISBN 88-15-07174-1.
  172. ^ DeFries, J.C.; McGuffin, P.; McClearn, G.E.; Plomin, R. (2000). Behavioral Genetics (4th ed.). W.H. Freeman and Company.
  173. ^ Morris, D. (1967). The Naked Ape. New York: McGraw-Hill. ISBN 0-385-33430-3.
  174. ^ Dawkins, R. (1976). The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 88-04-39318-1.
  175. ^ Pinker, S. (2002). The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature’. London: Penguin. p. 179. ISBN 0-14-200334-4.
  176. ^ Lewontin, R. (2000). It Ain’t Necessarily So: The Dream of the Human Genome and other Illusions. New York: NYREV Inc. ISBN 88-420-6418-1.
  177. ^ Kornhuber & Deecke, 1965. Hirnpotentialänderungen bei Willkürbewegungen und passiven Bewegungen des Menschen: Bereitschaftspotential und reafferente Potentiale. Pflügers Arch 284: 1–17.
  178. ^ a b c Libet, Benjamin; Gleason, Curtis A.; Wright, Elwood W.; Pearl, Dennis K. (1983). «Time of Conscious Intention to Act in Relation to Onset of Cerebral Activity (Readiness-Potential)». Brain. 106 (3): 623–42. doi:10.1093/brain/106.3.623. PMID 6640273.
  179. ^ Libet, B. (1985). «Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action». Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 8 (4): 529–66. doi:10.1017/S0140525X00044903. S2CID 6965339.
  180. ^
    Benjamin Libet; et al. (1983). «Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activity (readiness-potential)» (PDF). Brain. 106 (3): 623–42. doi:10.1093/brain/106.3.623. PMID 6640273. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2013-05-26.
  181. ^ Lars Strother; Sukhvinder Singh Obhi (2009). «The conscious experience of action and intention» (PDF). Exp Brain Res. 198 (4): 535–39. doi:10.1007/s00221-009-1946-7. PMID 19641911. S2CID 43567513. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2014-12-17.
  182. ^ A brief discussion of possible interpretation of these results is found in David A. Rosenbaum (2009). Human Motor Control (2nd ed.). Academic Press. p. 86. ISBN 978-0-12-374226-1.
  183. ^ Gallagher, Shaun (2009). «Chapter 6: Where’s the action? Epiphenomenalism and the problem of free will». In Susan Pockett; William P. Banks; Shaun Gallagher (eds.). Does Consciousness Cause Behavior?. MIT Press. pp. 119–21. ISBN 978-0-262-51257-2.
  184. ^ Wegner, D. (2002). The Illusion of Conscious Will. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  185. ^ Kornhuber & Deecke, 2012. The will and its brain – an appraisal of reasoned free will. University Press of America, Lanham, MD, ISBN 978-0-7618-5862-1.
  186. ^ Flanagan, O.J. (1992). Consciousness Reconsidered. Bradford Books. MIT Press. p. 131. ISBN 978-0-262-56077-1. LCCN lc92010057.
  187. ^ Guggisberg, AG; Mottaz, A (2013). «Timing and awareness of movement decisions: does consciousness really come too late?». Front Hum Neurosci. 7: 385. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2013.00385. PMC 3746176. PMID 23966921.
  188. ^ Schurger, Aaron; Sitt, Jacobo D.; Dehaene, Stanislas (16 October 2012). «An accumulator model for spontaneous neural activity prior to self-initiated movement». PNAS. 109 (42): 16776–77. Bibcode:2012PNAS..109E2904S. doi:10.1073/pnas.1210467109. PMC 3479453. PMID 22869750.
  189. ^ Fried, Itzhak; Mukamel, Roy; Kreiman, Gabriel (2011). «Internally Generated Preactivation of Single Neurons in Human Medial Frontal Cortex Predicts Volition». Neuron. 69 (3): 548–62. doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2010.11.045. PMC 3052770. PMID 21315264.
  190. ^ Maoz, Uri; Yaffe, Gideon; Koch, Christof; Mudrik, Liad (2019-02-28). «Neural precursors of decisions that matter—an ERP study of deliberate and arbitrary choice». eLife. 8. doi:10.7554/elife.39787. PMC 6809608. PMID 31642807.
  191. ^ a b Tourette Syndrome Association. Definitions and Classification of Tic Disorders.. Retrieved 19 August 2006.
  192. ^ Zinner, S.H. (2000). «Tourette disorder». Pediatrics in Review. 21 (11): 372–83. doi:10.1542/pir.21-11-372. PMID 11077021. S2CID 7774922.
  193. ^ Kayser, A.S.; Sun, F.T.; D’Esposito, M. (2009). «A comparison of Granger causality and coherency in fMRI-based analysis of the motor system». Human Brain Mapping. 30 (11): 3475–94. doi:10.1002/hbm.20771. PMC 2767459. PMID 19387980.
  194. ^ Assal, F.; Schwartz, S.; Vuilleumier, P. (2007). «Moving with or without will: Functional neural correlates of alien hand syndrome». Annals of Neurology. 62 (3): 301–06. doi:10.1002/ana.21173. PMID 17638304. S2CID 14180577.
  195. ^ Doody, RS; Jankovic, J. (1992). «The alien hand and related signs». Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery, and Psychiatry. 55 (9): 806–10. doi:10.1136/jnnp.55.9.806. PMC 1015106. PMID 1402972.
  196. ^ Scepkowski, L.A.; Cronin-Golomb, A. (2003). «The alien hand: cases, categorizations, and anatomical correlates». Behavioral and Cognitive Neuroscience Reviews. 2 (4): 261–77. doi:10.1177/1534582303260119. PMID 15006289.
  197. ^ Bundick, T.; Spinella, M. (2000). «Subjective experience, involuntary movement, and posterior alien hand syndrome». Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery, and Psychiatry. 68 (1): 83–85. doi:10.1136/jnnp.68.1.83. PMC 1760620. PMID 10601408.
  198. ^ Schneider, K. (1959). Clinical Psychopathology. New York: Grune and Stratton.
  199. ^ Frith, CD; Blakemore, S; Wolpert, DM (2000). «Explaining the symptoms of schizophrenia: abnormalities in the awareness of action». Brain Research. Brain Research Reviews. 31 (2–3): 357–63. doi:10.1016/S0165-0173(99)00052-1. PMID 10719163. S2CID 206021496.
  200. ^ a b Wegener, Daniel Merton (2002). The Illusion of Conscious Will (PDF). MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-23222-7. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2018-12-12. Retrieved 2018-12-12.
  201. ^ Wegner, D.M.; Wheatley, T. (1999). «Apparent mental causation: sources of the experience of will». American Psychologist. 54 (7): 480–91. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.188.8271. doi:10.1037/0003-066X.54.7.480. PMID 10424155.
  202. ^ Aarts, H.; Custers, R.; Wegner, D. (2005). «On the inference of personal authorship: enhancing experienced agency by priming effect information». Consciousness and Cognition. 14 (3): 439–58. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2004.11.001. PMID 16091264. S2CID 13991023.
  203. ^ Kihlstrom, John (2004). «An unwarrantable impertinence». Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 27 (5): 666–67. doi:10.1017/S0140525X04300154. S2CID 144699878.
  204. ^ John Baer; James C. Kaufman; Roy F. Baumeister (2008). Are We Free? Psychology and Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 155–80. ISBN 978-0-19-518963-6.
  205. ^ Nahmias, Eddy (2002). «When consciousness matters: a critical review of Daniel Wegner’s The illusion of conscious will» (PDF). Philosophical Psychology. 15 (4): 527–41. doi:10.1080/0951508021000042049. S2CID 16949962. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2011-08-13.
  206. ^ Mele, Alfred R. (2009). Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will. US: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-538426-0. Archived from the original on 2011-11-13.
  207. ^ Pronin, Emily (2009). «The Introspection Illusion». In Mark P. Zanna (ed.). Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, Vol. 41. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology. Vol. 41. Academic Press. pp. 42–43. doi:10.1016/S0065-2601(08)00401-2. ISBN 978-0-12-374472-2.
  208. ^ Susan Pockett (2009). «The neuroscience of movement». In Susan Pockett; WP Banks; Shaun Gallagher (eds.). Does Consciousness Cause Behavior?. MIT Press. p. 19. ISBN 978-0-262-51257-2. …it is important to be clear about exactly what experience one wants one’s subjects to introspect. Of course, explaining to subjects exactly what the experimenter wants them to experience can bring its own problems–…instructions to attend to a particular internally generated experience can easily alter both the timing and the content of that experience and even whether or not it is consciously experienced at all.
  209. ^ Ebert, J.P.; Wegner, D.M. (2011). «March 1). Mistaking randomness for free will» (PDF). Consciousness and Cognition. 20 (3): 965–71. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.12.012. PMID 21367624. S2CID 19502601.
  210. ^ Feldman, G.; Baumeister, R.F.; Wong, K.F. (2014). «July 30). Free will is about choosing: The link between choice and the belief in free will». Journal of Experimental Social Psychology. 55: 239–45. doi:10.1016/j.jesp.2014.07.012.
  211. ^ Nettler, Gwynn (June 1959). «Cruelty, Dignity, and Determinism». American Sociological Review. 24 (3): 375–384. doi:10.2307/2089386. JSTOR 2089386.
  212. ^ Nahmias, Eddy; Stephen G Morris; Thomas Nadelhoffer; Jason Turner (2006-07-01). «Is Incompatibilism Intuitive?». Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 73 (1): 28–53. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.364.1083. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2006.tb00603.x. ISSN 1933-1592.
  213. ^ Feltz, Adam; Edward T. Cokely; Thomas Nadelhoffer (2009-02-01). «Natural Compatibilism versus Natural Incompatibilism: Back to the Drawing Board». Mind & Language. 24 (1): 1–23. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.2008.01351.x. ISSN 1468-0017.
  214. ^ Nichols, Shaun; Joshua Knobe (2007-12-01). «Moral Responsibility and Determinism: The Cognitive Science of Folk Intuitions». Noûs. 41 (4): 663–85. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.175.1091. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2007.00666.x.
  215. ^ Sarkissian, HAGOP; Amita Chatterjee; Felipe de Brigard; Joshua Knobe; Shaun Nichols; Smita Sirker (2010-06-01). «Is Belief in Free Will a Cultural Universal?». Mind & Language. 25 (3): 346–58. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.2010.01393.x. ISSN 1468-0017. S2CID 18837686.
  216. ^ Pronin, Emily; Matthew B. Kugler (2010-12-28). «People believe they have more free will than others». Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 107 (52): 22469–74. Bibcode:2010PNAS..10722469P. doi:10.1073/pnas.1012046108. PMC 3012523. PMID 21149703.
  217. ^ Feltz, Adam; Edward T. Cokely (March 2009). «Do judgments about freedom and responsibility depend on who you are? Personality differences in intuitions about compatibilism and incompatibilism». Consciousness and Cognition. 18 (1): 342–50. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2008.08.001. ISSN 1053-8100. PMID 18805023. S2CID 16953908.
  218. ^ a b c Baumeister, R.; Crescioni, A.W.; Alquist, J. (2009). «Free will as advanced action control for human social life and culture». Neuroethics. 4: 1–11. doi:10.1007/s12152-010-9058-4. S2CID 143223154.
  219. ^ Paulhus, D.L. and Margesson. A., (1994). Free Will and Determinism (FAD) scale. Unpublished manuscript, Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada: University of British Columbia.
  220. ^ Stillman, T.F., R.F. Baumeister, F.D. Fincham, T.E. Joiner, N.M. Lambert, A.R. Mele, and D.M. Tice. 2008. Guilty, free, and wise. Belief in free will promotes learning from negative emotions. Manuscript in preparation.
  221. ^ Bar-Hillel, M. 2007. Randomness is too important to trust to chance. Presented at the 2007 Summer Institute in Informed Patient Choice, Dartmouth Medical School, NH
  222. ^ Wagenaar, W.A. (1972). «Generation of random sequences by human subjects: A critical survey of literature». Psychological Bulletin. 77: 65–72. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.211.9085. doi:10.1037/h0032060.
  223. ^ «What Philosophers Believe: Results from the 2020 PhilPapers Survey». November 2021.
  224. ^ Gregory W. Graffin and William B. Provine, «Evolution, Religion, and Free Will,» American Scientist 95 (July–August 2007), 294–97; results of Cornell Evolution Project survey,
    http://faculty.bennington.edu/~sherman/Evolution%20in%20America/evol%20religion%20free%20will.pdf.
  225. ^ Vohs, K.D.; Schooler, J.W. (2008). «The value of believing in free will: Encouraging a belief in determinism increases cheating». Psychological Science. 19 (1): 49–54. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.2008.02045.x. PMID 18181791. S2CID 2643260.
  226. ^ a b Baumeister, R.F.; Masicampo, E.J.; DeWall, C.N. (2009). «Prosocial benefits of feeling free: Disbelief in free will increases aggression and reduces helpfulness». Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 35 (2): 260–68. doi:10.1177/0146167208327217. PMID 19141628. S2CID 16010829.
  227. ^ Monroe, Andrew E.; Brady, Garrett L.; Malle, Bertram F. (21 September 2016). «This Isn’t the Free Will Worth Looking For». Social Psychological and Personality Science. 8 (2): 191–199. doi:10.1177/1948550616667616. S2CID 152011660.
  228. ^ Crone, Damien L.; Levy, Neil L. (28 June 2018). «Are Free Will Believers Nicer People? (Four Studies Suggest Not)». Social Psychological and Personality Science. 10 (5): 612–619. doi:10.1177/1948550618780732. PMC 6542011. PMID 31249653.
  229. ^ Caspar, Emilie A.; Vuillaume, Laurène; Magalhães De Saldanha da Gama, Pedro A.; Cleeremans, Axel (17 January 2017). «The Influence of (Dis)belief in Free Will on Immoral Behavior». Frontiers in Psychology. 8: 20. doi:10.3389/FPSYG.2017.00020. PMC 5239816. PMID 28144228.
  230. ^ Nadelhoffer, Thomas; Shepard, Jason; Crone, Damien L.; Everett, Jim A.C.; Earp, Brian D.; Levy, Neil (October 2020). «Does encouraging a belief in determinism increase cheating? Reconsidering the value of believing in free will». Cognition. 203: 104342. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2020.104342. PMID 32593841. S2CID 220057834.
  231. ^ Buttrick, Nicholas R.; Aczel, Balazs; Aeschbach, Lena F.; Bakos, Bence E.; Brühlmann, Florian; Claypool, Heather M.; Hüffmeier, Joachim; Kovacs, Marton; Schuepfer, Kurt; Szecsi, Peter; Szuts, Attila; Szöke, Orsolya; Thomae, Manuela; Torka, Ann-Kathrin; Walker, Ryan J.; Wood, Michael J. (September 2020). «Many Labs 5: Registered Replication of Vohs and Schooler (2008), Experiment 1». Advances in Methods and Practices in Psychological Science. 3 (3): 429–438. doi:10.1177/2515245920917931. S2CID 227095775.
  232. ^ a b c d e f Holton, Richard (2011). «Response to ‘Free Will as Advanced Action Control for Human Social Life and Culture’ by Roy F. Baumeister, A. William Crescioni and Jessica L. Alquist» (PDF). Neuroethics. 4: 13–16. doi:10.1007/s12152-009-9046-8. hdl:1721.1/71223. S2CID 143687015.
  233. ^ Miles, J.B. (2011). «‘Irresponsible and a Disservice’: The integrity of social psychology turns on the free will dilemma». British Journal of Social Psychology. 52 (2): 205–18. doi:10.1111/j.2044-8309.2011.02077.x. PMC 3757306. PMID 22074173.
  234. ^ Some studies have been conducted indicating that people react strongly to the way in which mental determinism is described, when reconciling it with moral responsibility. Eddy Nahmias has noted that when people’s actions are framed with respect to their beliefs and desires (rather than their neurological underpinnings), they are more likely to dissociate determinism from moral responsibility. See Nahmias, Eddy; D. Justin Coates; Trevor Kvaran (2007-09-01). «Free Will, Moral Responsibility, and Mechanism: Experiments on Folk Intuitions». Midwest Studies in Philosophy. 31 (1): 214–42. doi:10.1111/j.1475-4975.2007.00158.x. ISSN 1475-4975. S2CID 15648622.
  235. ^ Epstude, K.; Roese, N. J. (2008). «The Functional Theory of Counterfactual Thinking». Personality and Social Psychology Review. 12 (2): 168–192. doi:10.1177/1088868308316091. PMC 2408534. PMID 18453477.
  236. ^ Stillman, Tyler F.; Roy F. Baumeister; Kathleen D. Vohs; Nathaniel M. Lambert; Frank D. Fincham; Lauren E. Brewer (2010-01-01). «Personal Philosophy and Personnel Achievement: Belief in Free Will Predicts Better Job Performance». Social Psychological and Personality Science. 1 (1): 43–50. doi:10.1177/1948550609351600. S2CID 3023336.
  237. ^ «The Battle of the Will, Part 4: John Wesley and Jonathan Edwards». The Gospel Coalition. Retrieved 6 August 2021.
  238. ^ Discipline of the Immanuel Missionary Church. Shoals, Indiana: Immanuel Missionary Church. 1986. p. 7.
  239. ^ Rambam Teshuvah 5:4
  240. ^ Rambam Teshuvah 5:5
  241. ^ Watt, Montgomery (1948). Free-Will and Predestination in Early Islam. London: Luzac & Co.
  242. ^ Wolfson, Harry (1976). The Philosophy of Kalam. Harvard University Press.
  243. ^ «Man and His Destiny». Al-islam.org. Retrieved 2010-11-21.
  244. ^ Tosun, Ender (2012). Guide to Understanding Islam (PDF). Istanbul. p. 209. ISBN 978-605-63198-1-5. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2013-05-28.
  245. ^ Jackson, Timothy P. (1998). «Arminian edification: Kierkegaard on grace and free will». Cambridge Companion to Kierkegaard. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  246. ^ Kierkegaard, Søren. (1848) Journals and Papers, vol. III. Reprinted in Indiana University Press, Bloomington, 1967–78.
  247. ^ Mackie, J.L. (1955) «Evil and Omnipotence», Mind, new series, vol. 64, pp. 200–12.
  248. ^ Ockham, William. Predestination, God’s Knowledge, and Future Contingents, early 14th century, trans. Marilyn McCord Adams and Norman Kretzmann 1982, Hackett, esp pp. 46–47
  249. ^ H.A. Wolfson, Philo, 1947 Harvard University Press; Religious Philosophy, 1961 Harvard University Press; and «St. Augustine and the Pelagian Controversy» in Religious Philosophy

Bibliography[edit]

  • Hawking, Stephen, and Mlodinow, Leonard, The Grand Design, New York, Bantam Books, 2010.
  • Horst, Steven (2011), Laws, Mind, and Free Will. (MIT Press) ISBN 0-262-01525-0
  • Sri Aurobindo about freedom and free will(PDF)
  • Cave, Stephen (June 2016). «There’s No Such Thing as Free Will». The Atlantic.

Further reading[edit]

  • Dennett, Daniel C. (2003). Freedom Evolves. New York: Viking Press ISBN 0-670-03186-0
  • Epstein J.M. (1999). Agent Based Models and Generative Social Science. Complexity, IV (5).
  • Gazzaniga, M. & Steven, M.S. (2004) Free Will in the 21st Century: A Discussion of Neuroscience and Law, in Garland, B. (ed.) Neuroscience and the Law: Brain, Mind and the Scales of Justice, New York: Dana Press, ISBN 1-932594-04-3, pp. 51–70.
  • Goodenough, O.R. (2004). «Responsibility and punishment». Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B. 359 (1451): 1805–09. doi:10.1098/rstb.2004.1548. PMC 1693460. PMID 15590621.
  • Harnad, Stevan (1982). «Consciousness: An Afterthought». Cognition and Brain Theory. 5: 29–47.
  • Harnad, Stevan (2001). «No Easy Way Out». The Sciences. 41 (2): 36–42. doi:10.1002/j.2326-1951.2001.tb03561.x.
  • Harnad, Stevan (2009) The Explanatory Gap #PhilPapers
  • Harris, Sam. 2012. Free Will. Free Press. ISBN 978-1-4516-8340-0
  • Hofstadter, Douglas. (2007) I Am A Strange Loop. Basic Books. ISBN 978-0-465-03078-1
  • Kane, Robert (1998). The Significance of Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press ISBN 0-19-512656-4
  • Lawhead, William F. (2005). The Philosophical Journey: An Interactive Approach. McGraw-Hill Humanities/Social Sciences/Languages ISBN 0-07-296355-7.
  • Libet, Benjamin; Anthony Freeman; and Keith Sutherland, eds. (1999). The Volitional Brain: Towards a Neuroscience of Free Will. Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic. Collected essays by scientists and philosophers.
  • Muhm, Myriam (2004). Abolito il libero arbitrio – Colloquio con Wolf Singer. L’Espresso 19.08.2004 larchivio.org
  • Nowak A., Vallacher R.R., Tesser A., Borkowski W. (2000). Society of Self: The emergence of collective properties in self-structure. Psychological Review. 107
  • Schopenhauer, Arthur (1839). On the Freedom of the Will., Oxford: Basil Blackwell ISBN 0-631-14552-4.
  • Stapp, Henry (2017). Quantum Theory and Free Will, New York: Springer ISBN: 978-3-319-58300-6
  • Tosun, Ender (2020). Free Will Under the Light of the Quran, ISBN 978-605-63198-2-2
  • Van Inwagen, Peter (1986). An Essay on Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press ISBN 0-19-824924-1.
  • Velmans, Max (2003) How Could Conscious Experiences Affect Brains? Exeter: Imprint Academic ISBN 0-907845-39-8.
  • Dick Swaab, Wij Zijn Ons Brein, Publishing Centre, 2010. ISBN 978-90-254-3522-6
  • Wegener, Daniel Merton (2002). The Illusion of Conscious Will (PDF). MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-23222-7. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2018-12-12. Retrieved 2018-12-12.
  • Williams, Clifford (1980). Free Will and Determinism: A Dialogue. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company
  • John Baer, James C. Kaufman, Roy F. Baumeister (2008). Are We Free? Psychology and Free Will. Oxford University Press, New York ISBN 0-19-518963-9
  • George Musser, «Is the Cosmos Random? (Einstein’s assertion that God does not play dice with the universe has been misinterpreted)», Scientific American, vol. 313, no. 3 (September 2015), pp. 88–93.

External links[edit]

This article incorporates material from the Citizendium article «Free will», which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 3.0 Unported License but not under the GFDL.

Encyclopedia Britannica

Encyclopedia Britannica

  • Entertainment & Pop Culture
  • Geography & Travel
  • Health & Medicine
  • Lifestyles & Social Issues
  • Literature
  • Philosophy & Religion
  • Politics, Law & Government
  • Science
  • Sports & Recreation
  • Technology
  • Visual Arts
  • World History
  • On This Day in History
  • Quizzes
  • Podcasts
  • Dictionary
  • Biographies
  • Summaries
  • Top Questions
  • Infographics
  • Demystified
  • Lists
  • #WTFact
  • Companions
  • Image Galleries
  • Spotlight
  • The Forum
  • One Good Fact
  • Entertainment & Pop Culture
  • Geography & Travel
  • Health & Medicine
  • Lifestyles & Social Issues
  • Literature
  • Philosophy & Religion
  • Politics, Law & Government
  • Science
  • Sports & Recreation
  • Technology
  • Visual Arts
  • World History
  • Britannica Explains
    In these videos, Britannica explains a variety of topics and answers frequently asked questions.
  • Britannica Classics
    Check out these retro videos from Encyclopedia Britannica’s archives.
  • Demystified Videos
    In Demystified, Britannica has all the answers to your burning questions.
  • #WTFact Videos
    In #WTFact Britannica shares some of the most bizarre facts we can find.
  • This Time in History
    In these videos, find out what happened this month (or any month!) in history.
  • Student Portal
    Britannica is the ultimate student resource for key school subjects like history, government, literature, and more.
  • COVID-19 Portal
    While this global health crisis continues to evolve, it can be useful to look to past pandemics to better understand how to respond today.
  • 100 Women
    Britannica celebrates the centennial of the Nineteenth Amendment, highlighting suffragists and history-making politicians.
  • Saving Earth
    Britannica Presents Earth’s To-Do List for the 21st Century. Learn about the major environmental problems facing our planet and what can be done about them!
  • SpaceNext50
    Britannica presents SpaceNext50, From the race to the Moon to space stewardship, we explore a wide range of subjects that feed our curiosity about space!

Free will is the power to exercise control over one’s decisions and actions. The interest of free will in philosophy primarily lies in whether free will exists. While hard determinism denies the existence of free will, other schools such as incompatibilism, soft determinism (or compatibilism), and libertarianism recognize it in some way or others. These various schools differ on whether all events are already determined or not (determinism versus indeterminism) and also on whether freedom can coexist with determinism or not (compatibilism versus incompatibilism). Philosophers are interested in free will also because free will is considered to be a requirement for moral responsibility. For example, it makes sense to punish criminals only if they choose their fates. But different schools naturally have different responses to the problem of moral responsibility.

The principle of free will has scientific and religious implications. For example, free will may be implied in the basic indeterminism of quantum mechanics. Also in neuroscience, it may imply that the actions of the body, including the brain and the mind, are not wholly determined by physical causality. In the religious realm, free will may imply that it is not totally determined by the causation of karma (Hinduism and Buddhism), or that its power over individual will and choices is not entirely controlled or predestined by an omnipotent divinity (monotheistic religions).

Given all the above positions and their variations, one fundamental issue which underlies them all perhaps with the exception of hard determinism is: Given their free will that may be in some tension with karma or with predestination, how are humans related to nature and God? Are they compatible or incompatible with nature and God? Open theism, a recent school of theology that was developed amongst some Evangelical Christians, stands for the compatibility of God, humans, and nature from the perspective of love that redefines the connection between divine omniscience and omnipotence and human free will.

Does Free Will Exist?

An Example of the problem

Before delving into the problem of whether free will exists, it will be helpful to present an example of the problem. So here is a simple one:

We often praise valedictorians for their intelligence or industriousness (or both). But some philosophers would argue that since no one can choose to become a valedictorian, no one deserves praise for becoming a valedictorian. For instance, if a person Jen is a valedictorian because she is very smart, then Jen’s genes, not Jen, determined her accomplishment. Furthermore, if Jen is a valedictorian because she is hard-working, then either her environment (e.g., her parents) or her genes determined her accomplishment—because these are the only causes of character traits. However, Jen did not choose her environment, and we already know that Jen did not choose her genes. Hence, Jen did not choose to become a valedictorian, it was determined from the day she was born.

Thus generalizing this reasoning to all of our actions poses a dilemma: that all of our actions might be determined. But just what does it mean for an action to be determined?

Determinism or indeterminism?

The debate over whether free will exists is a debate about the compatibility of free will with how the world’s events proceed. Two dominant philosophical views on how the world’s events proceed are determinism and indeterminism. Determinism claims that the laws of nature and all past events fix all future events. For example, according to Newtonian mechanics, which is a deterministic physical theory, after two elastic bodies A and B come into contact with initial momentums pA and pB, the final momentums of A and B are fixed from pA and pB and the law of conservation of linear momentum.

In contrast, indeterminism claims that it is not true that the laws of nature and all past events fix all future events. For example, according to the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics, which is an indeterministic physical theory, Heisenberg’s relations stipulate that the momentum and position of quantum particles are two physical quantities of which we cannot simultaneously assign values. Thus we cannot predict the momentum and position of an electron at a future time even if we knew its momentum and position at a past time.

Theories on free will and determinism

Major metaphysical theories on the compatibility of free will with how the world’s events proceed are outlined below:

  • Hard determinism. Determinism is true and free will does not exist.
  • Incompatibilism. If determinism is true, then free will does not exist.
  • Soft determinism (or compatibilism). Determinism is true and free will exists.
  • Libertarianism. Indeterminism is true and free will exists.

Discussion of the theories

Hard determinism

Hard determinism is the bold view that determinism is true and that, as a result, free will does not exist. Thus hard determinists are nothing more than incompatibilists who are also determinists. Some hard determinists believe that science (especially biology and psychology) shows that human behavior is ultimately reducible to mechanical events. For example, thinking is just neuron firing, and bodily movement is just muscle contraction, both of which reduce to certain chemical reactions, which themselves reduce to certain physical events. So, these hard determinists claim that if we could acquire all of the past facts about a human, then we could predict his or her future actions from the laws of nature.

Incompatibilism

Incompatibilism is a view about the inconsistency of free will and determinism. It is not a view about whether determinism or free will exists. So, an incompatibilist can believe that free will exists if she does not believe that determinism is true. Peter van Inwagen (1983) is a philosopher that holds an incompatibilist view. He defends incompatibilism with what he calls the «consequence argument.» He summarizes it as follows: «If determinism is true, then our acts are the consequences of the laws of nature and events in the remote past. But it is not up to us what went on before we were born, and neither is it up to us what the laws of nature are. Therefore, the consequences of these things (including our present acts) are not up to us.»[1]

Although Van Inwagen elaborates on the consequence argument, his main point is that compatibilism is incoherent because in order to have free will in a deterministic world, people must be able to violate the laws of nature, because we certainly cannot change past events. Since it is absurd to think that anyone (with the possible exception of God) can violate a law of nature, it is absurd to believe in compatibilism.

Soft determinism (or compatibilism)

Soft Determinism (or compatibilism) is the view that determinism is true, but free will exists nevertheless. Soft determinists have two critics: hard determinists and incompatibilists. Although the arguments against soft determinism seem insurmountable, there are several ways to reply to the critics. One way is to challenge the truth of incompatibilism. For example, some philosophers disagree that we would need to violate a law of nature in order to have free will. One such philosopher is David Lewis, who argues that we might be able to do things that require a law of nature to be broken without ourselves breaking a law of nature. Lewis calls such an action a «divergence miracle» because it requires that a miracle occurs, but not that we are the ones conducting the miracles. For example, God could render a law of nature false so that one of us can act in a way that violates a law of nature.[2]

Another way to reply to the critics is to argue that while determinism is true, the interpretation of it that leads to incompatibilism is not true. This reply answers hard determinists. Roderick Chisholm is one philosopher who takes this approach. He revives Aristotle’s (384-322 B.C.E.) view that not all events are caused by events, but rather, some events are caused by agents. In Aristotle’s words, «A staff moves a stone, and is moved by a hand, which is moved by a man.» Thus Chisholm claims that agents or events can determine events. He calls the former «agent causation» and the latter «event causation.» So, although determinism that assumes only event causation leads to incompatibilism, determinism that assumes event and agent causation leads to compatibilism.[3]

There is, however, a popular criticism against soft determinism inspired from the thesis of agent causation, and it is that this form of soft determinism is implausible because agent causation appears from nowhere. In short, science cannot explain how agent causation is possible because scientific laws apply to events. Specifically, how does a human being move a stone, as Aristotle claims, if not by a series of events such as muscle contraction and neuron firing? Hence agent causation is mysterious from a scientific point of view. Chisholm’s response to this concern is that this criticism applies equally well to event causation. For example, how do positively charged bodies cause negatively charged bodies to move toward them? There is no answer to this question because electromagnetic force is a fundamental—and thus inexplicable—physical cause. Thus causation between events is equally mysterious. Chisholm’s explanation of this dual mystery is that what is not well understood is causation. Thus all apparent problems about agent causation are really problems about causation itself.

As another philosophical compatibilist, Alfred North Whitehead (1861-1947) shifts the discussion to a different kind of distinction—the distinction between the «self-causation» of a subject by which the subject determines itself and the «efficient causation» from objects by which the subject is determined. According to him, both causations function harmoniously and compatibly because through the former causation the subject creatively incorporates the latter for the final constitution of itself. Whitehead applies this to all subjects called «actual entities» and analyzes the relations of God, humans, and nature in terms of compatible actual entities.[4]

Libertarianism

Philosophical libertarianism (not to be confused with political libertarianism), is the view that indeterminism rather than determinism is true, and as a result, free will exists. A major impetus of defending indeterminism instead of determinism is the advent of quantum mechanics. However, one should be aware that not all interpretations of quantum mechanics are indeterministic, such as Bohmian mechanics and other hidden-variable theories.

But more importantly, even if the world’s events are indeterministic, some philosophers argue that indeterminism is incompatible with free will. For example, J. J. C. Smart argues that libertarianism posits the absurd concept of «contra-causal freedom,» which is metaphysical freedom that exists in the absence of causes, since all undetermined events should occur by chance, instead of a cause, in an indeterministic world.[5]

Robert Kane, a well-known libertarian, claims that philosophers who attribute contra-causal freedom to libertarianism misunderstand the thesis of indeterminism because their view rests on the false assumption that the «luck principle» is true. The luck principle states that «If an action is undetermined at a time t, then its happening rather than not happening at t would be a matter of chance or luck, and so it could not be a free and responsible action,» but this principle is false according to Kane because indeterminism does not reject causation, only deterministic causation. In fact, some other philosophers such as Patrick Suppes and Wesley Salmon have constructed reasonable and detailed theories of probabilistic causation. To prove the possibility of indeterministic causation, Kane provides a «shaky assassin» counterexample to the luck principle:

Consider an assassin who is trying to kill the prime minister but might miss because of some undetermined events in his nervous system which might lead to a jerking or wavering of his arm. If he does hit his target, can he be held responsible? The answer (as J.L. Austin and Philippa Foot successfully argued decades ago) is «yes,» because he intentionally and voluntarily succeeded in doing what he was trying to do—kill the prime minister.[6]

Thus Kane argues that an indeterministic world does not undermine our control over our actions because we can voluntarily and intentionally cause events to happen even though we cannot guarantee their occurrence due to indeterminacy.

Moral Responsibility

Society generally holds people responsible for their actions, saying that they deserve praise or blame for what they do. However, many believe moral responsibility to require free will, in other words, the ability to do otherwise. Thus, the issue here is whether individuals are ever morally responsible, and if so, in what sense.

Incompatibilists tend to think that determinism is at odds with moral responsibility. After all, it seems impossible that one can hold someone responsible for an action that could be predicted from the beginning of time. Hard determinists may say «So much the worse for moral responsibility!» and discard the concept. Clarence Darrow famously used this argument to defend the murderers Leopold and Loeb. Conversely, libertarians may say «So much the worse for determinism!»

This issue also appears to be the heart of the dispute between hard determinists and compatibilists; hard determinists are forced to accept that individuals often have «free will» in the compatibilist sense, but they deny that this sense of free will truly matters, i.e., that it can ground moral responsibility. Just because an agent’s choices are uncoerced, hard determinists claim, does not change the fact that determinism robs the agent of responsibility. Compatibilists often argue that, on the contrary, determinism is a prerequisite for moral responsibility, i.e., that society cannot hold someone responsible unless his actions were determined by something. St. Paul, in his Epistle to the Romans addresses the question of moral responsibility as follows: «Hath not the potter power over the clay, of the same lump to make one vessel unto honour, and another unto dishonour?» (Romans 9:21, KJV). In this view, individuals can still be dishonored for their acts even though those acts were ultimately completely determined by God. A similar view has it that individual moral culpability lies in individual character. That is, a person with the character of a murderer has no choice other than to murder, but can still be punished because it is right to punish those of bad character.

If indeterminism is true, however, then those events that are not determined are random. One questions whether it is possible that one can blame or praise someone for performing an action that just spontaneously popped into his nervous system. Libertarians may reply that undetermined actions are not random at all, since they result from a substantive will whose decisions are undetermined, and that they, therefore, are morally culpable.

The Science of Free Will

Physics

Throughout history, people have made attempts at answering the question of free will using scientific principles. Early scientific thought often pictured the universe as deterministic, and some thinkers believed that it was simply a matter of gathering sufficient information to be able to predict future events with perfect accuracy. This encourages individuals to see free will as an illusion. Modern science is a mixture of deterministic and stochastic theories. For example, radioactive decay occurs with predictable probability, but it is not possible, even in theory, to tell exactly when a particular nucleus will decay. Quantum mechanics predicts observations only in terms of probabilities. This casts some doubt on whether the universe is deterministic at all. Some scientific determinists such as Albert Einstein believe in the «hidden variable theory» that beneath the probabilities of quantum mechanics there are set variables (see the EPR Paradox). This theory has had great doubt cast on it by the Bell Inequalities, which suggest that «God may really play dice» after all, perhaps casting into doubt the predictions of Laplace’s demon. The leading contemporary philosopher who has capitalized on the success of quantum mechanics and chaos theory in order to defend incompatibilist freedom is Robert Kane, in The Significance of Free Will and other writings.[7] Kane’s arguments apply equally well to any «unthinking» entity that behaves according to quantum mechanics.

Genetics

Like physicists, biologists have frequently addressed questions related to free will. One of the most heated debates in biology is that of «nature versus nurture,» concerning the relative importance of genetics and biology as compared to culture and environment in human behavior. The view of most researchers is that many human behaviors can be explained in terms of humans’ brains, genes, and evolutionary histories. This raises the fear that such attribution makes it impossible to hold others responsible for their actions. Steven Pinker’s view is that fear of determinism in the context of «genetics» and «evolution» is a mistake, and that it is «a confusion of explanation with exculpation.» Responsibility doesn’t require behavior to be uncaused, as long as behavior responds to praise and blame.[8] Moreover, it is not certain that environmental determination is any less threatening to free will than genetic determination.

Neuroscience

It has become possible to study the living brain, and researchers can now watch the decision-making «machinery» at work. A seminal experiment in this field was conducted by Benjamin Libet in the 1980s, wherein he asked subjects to choose a random moment to flick their wrist while he watched the associated activity in their brains. Libet found that the unconscious brain activity leading up to the conscious decision by the subject to flick his or her wrist began approximately half a second before the subject consciously decided to move.[9] This build-up of electrical charge has come to be called «readiness potential.» Libet’s findings suggest that decisions made by a subject are actually first being made on a subconscious level and only afterward being translated into a «conscious decision,» and that the subject’s belief that it occurred at the behest of their will was only due to their retrospective perspective on the event. However, Libet still finds room in his model for free will, in the notion of the power of veto: according to this model, unconscious impulses to perform a volitional act are open to suppression by the conscious efforts of the subject. It should be noted that this does not mean that Libet believes unconsciously impelled actions require the ratification of consciousness, but rather that consciousness retains the power to, as it were, deny the actualization of unconscious impulses.

A related experiment performed later by Alvaro Pascual-Leone involved asking subjects to choose at random which of their hands to move. He found that by stimulating different hemispheres of the brain using magnetic fields it was possible to strongly influence which hand the subject picked. Normally right-handed people would choose to move their right hand 60% of the time, for example, but when the right hemisphere was stimulated they would instead choose their left hand 80% of the time; the right hemisphere of the brain is responsible for the left side of the body, and the left hemisphere for the right. Despite the external influence on their decision-making, the subjects continued to report that they believed their choice of hand had been made freely.

Libet himself, however, does not interpret his experiment as evidence of the inefficacy of conscious free will—he points out that although the tendency to press a button may be building up for 500 milliseconds, the conscious will retains a right to veto that action in the last few milliseconds. A comparison is made with a golfer, who may swing a club several times before striking the ball. In this view, the action simply gets a rubber stamp of approval at the last millisecond.

Neurology and psychiatry

There are several brain-related conditions in which an individual’s actions are not felt to be entirely under his or her control. Although the existence of such conditions does not directly refute the existence of free will, the study of such conditions, like the neuroscientific studies above, is valuable in developing models of how the brain may construct our experience of free will.

In obsessive-compulsive disorder, a patient may feel an overwhelming urge to do something against his or her own will. Examples include washing hands many times a day, recognizing the desire as his or her own desire, although it seems to be against his or her will. In Tourette syndrome and related syndromes, patients will involuntarily make movements, such as tics, and utterances. In alien hand syndrome, the patient’s limb will make meaningful acts without the intention of the subject.

Experimental psychology

Experimental psychology’s contributions to the free will debate have come primarily through social psychologist Daniel M. Wegner’s work on conscious will. In his book, The Illusion of Conscious Will,[10] Wegner summarizes empirical evidence supporting that the human perception of conscious control is an illusion.

Wegner observes that one event is inferred to have caused a second event when two requirements are met: 1) that the first event immediately precedes the second event, and 2) that the first event is consistent with having caused the second event. If a person hears an explosion and sees a tree fall down, for example, that person is likely to infer that the explosion caused the tree to fall over. However, if the explosion occurs after the tree falls down (i.e., the first requirement is not met), or rather than an explosion, the person hears the ring of a telephone (i.e., the second requirement is not met), then that person is not likely to infer that either noise caused the tree to fall down.

Wegner has applied this principle to the inferences people make about their own conscious will. People typically experience a thought that is consistent with a behavior, and then they observe themselves performing this behavior. As a result, people infer that their thoughts must have caused the observed behavior. However, Wegner has been able to manipulate people’s thoughts and behaviors so as to conform to or violate the two requirements for causal inference. Through such work, Wegner has been able to show that people will often experience conscious will over behaviors that they have, in fact, not caused, and conversely, that people can be led to experience a lack of will over behaviors that they did cause. The implication for such work is that the perception of conscious will is not tethered to the execution of actual behaviors. Although many interpret this work as a blow against the argument for free will, Wegner has asserted that his work informs only of the mechanism for perceptions of control, not for control itself.

Free Will in Eastern Religions

Hinduism and Buddhism understand the haunting presence of karma that explains determinism. At the same time, they quite often acknowledge human free will. So, the question is how they can explain both together.

Hinduism

In Hinduism there is no one accepted view on the concept of free will. Within the predominant schools of Hindu philosophy there are two main opinions. The Advaita (monistic) schools generally believe in a fate-based approach, and the Dvaita (dualistic) schools are proponents for the theory of free will. Different schools’ understandings are based upon their conceptions of the nature of the Supreme being (see Brahman, Paramatma and Ishvara) and how the individual soul (atma or jiva) dictates, or is dictated by karma within the illusory existence of maya. In the Samkhya, matter is without any freedom, and soul lacks any ability to control the unfolding of matter. The only real freedom (kaivalya) consists in realizing the ultimate separateness of matter and self. The metaphysics of the Nyaya and Vaisheshika schools strongly suggest a belief in determinism, but do not seem to make explicit claims about determinism or free will. A quotation from Swami Vivekananda (1863-1902), a Vedantist, offers a good example of the worry about free will in the Hindu tradition:

Therefore we see at once that there cannot be any such thing as free-will; the very words are a contradiction, because will is what we know, and everything that we know is within our universe, and everything within our universe is moulded by conditions of time, space and causality…. To acquire freedom we have to get beyond the limitations of this universe; it cannot be found here.[11]

On the other hand, Mimamsa, Vedanta, and the more theistic versions of Hinduism such as Shaivism and Vaishnavism, have often emphasized the importance of free will. For example, in the Bhagavad Gita the living beings (jivas) are described as being of a higher nature who have the freedom to exploit the inferior material nature (prakrti).

To Hindus such as the Advaitin philosopher Chandrashekhara Bharati Swaminah, fate and free will are not contradictory but harmonious because the doctrine of karma requires both that we pay for our actions in the past, and that our actions in the present be free enough to allow us to deserve the future reward or punishment that we will receive for our present actions. Thus:

Fate is past karma, free-will is present karma. Both are really one, that is, karma, though they may differ in the matter of time. There can be no conflict when they are really one…. Fate, as I told you, is the resultant of the past exercise of your free-will. By exercising your free-will in the past, you brought on the resultant fate. By exercising your free-will in the present, I want you to wipe out your past record if it hurts you, or to add to it if you find it enjoyable. In any case, whether for acquiring more happiness or for reducing misery, you have to exercise your free-will in the present.[12]

Buddhism

Buddhism accepts both freedom and determinism (or something similar to it), but rejects the idea of an agent, and thus the idea that freedom is a free will belonging to an agent. In the words of the Buddha: «There is free action, there is retribution, but I see no agent that passes out from one set of momentary elements into another one, except the [connection] of those elements.»[13]

Buddhism believes in neither absolute free will, nor determinism. It preaches a middle doctrine called pratitya-samutpada in Sanskrit, which is often translated as «inter-dependent arising.» It is part of the theory of karma in Buddhism. The concept of karma in Buddhism is different from that in Hinduism. In Buddhism, the idea of karma is less deterministic. The Buddhist notion of karma is primarily focused on the cause and effect of moral actions in this life, while in Hinduism the concept of karma is more often connected with determining one’s destiny in future lives.

In Buddhism it is taught that the idea of absolute freedom of choice (i.e., that any human being could be completely free to make any choice) is foolish, because it denies the reality of one’s physical needs and circumstances. Equally incorrect is the idea that we have no choice in life or that our lives are pre-determined. To deny freedom would be to undermine the efforts of Buddhists to make moral progress (through our capacity to freely choose compassionate action).

Because Buddhists also reject agenthood, the traditional compatibilist strategies are closed to them as well. Instead, the Buddhist philosophical strategy is to examine the metaphysics of causality. Ancient India had many heated arguments about the nature of causality, with Jains, Nyayists, Samkhyists, Carvakans, and Buddhists all taking slightly different lines. In many ways, the Buddhist position is closer to a theory of «conditionality» than a theory of «causality,» especially as it is expounded by Nagarjuna in the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā.

A contemporary American monk, Thanissaro Bhikkhu, puts it this way:

The Buddha’s teachings on karma are interesting because it’s a combination of causality and free-will. If things were totally caused there would be no way you could develop a skill — your actions would be totally predetermined. If there was no causality at all skills would be useless because things would be constantly changing without any kind of rhyme or reason to them. But it’s because there is an element of causality and because there is this element of free-will you can develop skills in life.[14]

Free Will in Monotheistic Religions

Monotheistic religions talk about God’s omniscience and omnipotence, affirming a kind of determinism. At the same time, they also recognize human free will. Sometimes human free will is alleged to be in conflict with divine omniscience and omnipotence. How they can be reconciled is an issue these religions have been trying to address.

Judaism

The belief in free will (Hebrew: bechirah chofshith בחירה חפשית, bechirah בחירה) is axiomatic in Jewish thought, and is closely linked with the concept of reward and punishment. This is based on the Torah itself: Deuteronomy 30:19 states: «I [God] have set before you life and death, blessings and curses. Now choose life, so that you and your children may live» (NIV). Free will is therefore discussed at length in Jewish philosophy, firstly as regards God’s purpose in creation, and secondly as regards the closely related, resultant, paradox.

The traditional teaching regarding the purpose of creation, particularly as influenced by Jewish mysticism, is this: «Man was created for the sole purpose of rejoicing in God, and deriving pleasure from the splendor of His Presence… The place where this joy may truly be derived is the World to Come, which was expressly created to provide for it; but the path to the object of our desires is this world.»[15] Free will is thus required, so that humans may be given or denied good for actions over which they have control. It is further understood that in order for humans to have true free choice, they must not only have inner free will, but also an environment in which a choice between obedience and disobedience exists. God thus created the world such that both good and evil can operate freely.

In Rabbinic literature, there is much discussion as to the contradiction between God’s omniscience and free will. The representative view is Rabbi Akiba’s (c.50-c.135) classic formulation: «Everything is foreseen, yet freewill is given.»[16] Based on this understanding, the problem is formally described by Maimonides (1135-1204) as a paradox, beyond our understanding:

The Holy One, Blessed Be He, knows everything that will happen before it has happened. So does He know whether a particular person will be righteous or wicked, or not? If He does know, then it will be impossible for that person not to be righteous. If He knows that he will be righteous but that it is possible for him to be wicked, then He does not know everything that He has created. …[T]he Holy One, Blessed Be He, does not have any temperaments and is outside such realms, unlike people, whose selves and temperaments are two separate things. God and His temperaments are one, and God’s existence is beyond the comprehension of Man… [Thus] we do not have the capabilities to comprehend how the Holy One, Blessed Be He, knows all creations and events. [Nevertheless] know without doubt that people do what they want without the Holy One, Blessed Be He, forcing or decreeing upon them to do so…. It has been said because of this that a man is judged according to all his actions.[17]

Although the above represents the majority view in Rabbinic thought, there are several major thinkers who resolve the paradox by explicitly excluding human action from divine foreknowledge. Both Saadia Gaon (882 or 892-942) and Judah ha-Levi (c. 1075-1141) hold that «the decisions of man precede God’s knowledge.» Gersonides (1288-1344) holds that God knows, beforehand, the choices open to each individual, but does not know which choice the individual, in his freedom, will make. Isaiah Horowitz (1565-1630) takes the view that God cannot know which moral choices people will make, but that, nevertheless, this does not impair his perfection.

Islam

In Islam the theological issue is not usually how to reconcile free will with God’s foreknowledge, but with God’s jabr, or divine commanding power. Al-Ash’ari (874-936) developed an «acquisition» or «dual-agency» form of compatibilism, in which human free will and divine jabr were both asserted, and which became a cornerstone of the dominant Ash’ari position.[18] In Shia Islam, Ash’ari’s understanding of a higher balance toward predestination is challenged by most theologians. Free will, according to Shia doctrine, is the main factor for one’s accountability in one’s actions throughout life. All actions taken by one’s free will are said to be counted on the Day of Judgment because they are one’s own and not God’s.

Christianity

In Christian theology, God is described as not only omniscient but omnipotent. This postulate, some Christians believe, implies that not only has God always known what choices individuals will make tomorrow, but he actually determined those choices. That is, by virtue of God’s foreknowledge he knows what will influence individual choices, and by virtue of God’s omnipotence he controls those factors. This becomes especially important for the doctrines relating to salvation and predestination.

Catholics

Theologians of the Catholic Church universally embrace the idea of free will, but generally do not view free will as existing apart from or in contradiction to grace. Saint Augustine (354-430) and Saint Thomas Aquinas (c.1225-1274) wrote extensively on free will, with Augustine focusing on the importance of free will in his responses to the Manichaeans, and also on the limitations of a concept of unlimited free will as denial of grace, in his refutations of Pelagius. Catholic Christianity’s emphasis on free will and grace is often contrasted with predestination in Protestant Christianity, especially after the Counter-Reformation, but in understanding differing conceptions of free will, it is just as important to understand the differing conceptions of the nature of God. The key idea is that God can be all-powerful and all-knowing even while people continue to exercise free will, because God does not exist in time.

According to Boethius (480-524 or 525),[19] God’s knowledge is timeless and eternal because he transcends temporal categories. God sees past, present, and future altogether in his eternal present. So, his eternal knowledge of our future, for example, cannot be treated as if it were a temporal foreknowledge of the same. While God is indeed all-knowing, he does not foreknow the future as if he were present temporally. Thus, human free will can be completely secured. This view of Boethius has been widely influential in the Catholic Church as it has tried to address the problem of the tension between divine foreknowledge and human will.

Calvinists

Calvinists embrace the idea that God chose who would be saved from before the creation. They quote Ephesians 1:4 «For he chose us in him before the creation of the world to be holy and blameless in his sight» (NIV). One of the strongest defenders of this theological point of view was the Puritan-American preacher and theologian Jonathan Edwards (1703-1758). Edwards believed that indeterminism was incompatible with the individual’s dependence on God and hence with God’s sovereignty. He reasoned that if individuals’ responses to God’s grace are contra-causally free, then their salvation depends partly on them and therefore God’s sovereignty is not «absolute and universal.» Edwards’ book Freedom of the Will defends theological determinism. In this book, he attempts to show that libertarianism is incoherent. For example, he argues that by «self-determination» the libertarian must mean either that one’s actions including one’s acts of willing are preceded by an act of free will, or that one’s acts of will lack sufficient causes. The first leads to an infinite regress, while the second implies that acts of will happen accidentally and hence cannot make someone «better or worse, any more than a tree is better than other trees because it oftener happens to be lit upon by a swan or nightingale; or a rock more vicious than other rocks, because rattlesnakes have happened oftener to crawl over it.»[20]

It should not be thought that this view completely denies freedom of choice, however. It claims that one is free to act on one’s moral impulses and desires, but is not free to act contrary to them, or to change them. Proponents such as John L. Girardeau have indicated their belief that moral neutrality is impossible; that even if it were possible, and one were equally inclined to contrary options, one could make no choice at all; that if one is inclined, however slightly, toward one option, then they will necessarily chose that one over any others.

Arminians and Molinists

Arminians in Protestantism, named after Jacobus Arminius, the celebrated Dutch Reformed theologian (1560-1609), and Molinists in Catholicism, named after Luis de Molina, the Spanish Jesuit theologian (1535-1600), recognize the significant power of free will, although they believe that, given our original sin, free will can only function after divine grace is given us. As regards the relationship of free will with God’s foreknowledge, they maintain that there is no contradiction there. While we are genuinely free to do anything because of our will, God foreknows what our decisions and actions will be like in the end. So, while God’s plan is virtually conditional upon human decision (i.e., virtual priority of human decision), it can still be maintained that God wills what he foreknows we will choose to do. Arminians have been strongly criticized by Calvinists, just like Molinists were sharply criticized by the conservative Dominican, Domingo Báñez (1528-1604). In Protestantism the discord of Arminianism and Calvinism is allowed to exist, just like within Catholicism the disagreement of Molina and Báñez has been officially allowed to exist.

This Arminian-Molinist position can also be seen in the Eastern Orthodox tradition in general.

Methodists

Methodists are Arminian in their emphasis on free will. But they understand the relationship of free will with divine omniscience and omnipotence in terms of «synergism.» While God initiates his relationship with human beings by giving them «prevenient grace,» once the relationship starts, human beings assume the capability and responsibility of response to God’d grace. Thus God and humans cooperate with each other in the process of salvation. According to John Wesley (1703-1791), human beings «can» and «must» respond to God’s grace, «working together with» God in their deeds of piety and in their deeds of love.[21]

Open theists

Open theism is a rather new school of theology that was developed amongst some Evangelical Christians towards the end of the twentieth century. In the Arminian tradition it appreciates the free will of human beings, but it introduces a unique way of reconciling free will with divine omniscience and omnipotence. According to open theists such as John Sanders, God, of course, foreknows some future certainties such as those things which he himself ordains in his overarching plan for humanity (e.g., the coming of his Kingdom) and those things which are determined in the natural order of causation (i.e., the occurrence of an earthquake), but regarding future actions to be made by human beings that have free will, God foreknows only their possibilities and not their certainties.[22] The future regarding human actions exists only in terms of possibilities rather than certainties. Human beings make choices, and God can neither predict nor control them. But God is still omniscient and omnipotent, in that he knows and does everything that it is possible for him to know and do.

Here we can find a new, interesting definition of divine omniscience and omnipotence. Traditional theism has defined divine omniscience and omnipotence based on its belief that a perfect God is immutable. For open theists, however, the immutability of God should not be the criterion. Rather, the love of God should be the criterion to explain a perfect God and his omniscience and omnipotence. Therefore, an all-knowing and all-powerful God, by giving us free will, can change and learn because of love. An all-knowing and all-powerful God can choose to be related and to respond to his creation because of love. If you argue that God can do none of these, you end up limiting God.[23]

Conclusion

Hard determinism, which denies free will in its entirety, is a minority opinion. The other schools (incompatibilism, compatibilism, and libertarianism) admit of free will in one way or another. They raise two subsequent questions: 1) How is free will related to determinism or indeterminism? and 2) Does free will entail moral responsibility?

To answer the first question, a brief summary of what has been discussed so far would be useful. In philosophy and science, determinism usually refers to causation resulting from the laws of nature, while indeterminism refers to uncaused randomness and uncertainty in nature or free will in the human realm. When the discussion shifts to religion, then determinism means the causation of karma (Hinduism and Buddhism) or God’s omniscience and omnipotence (monotheistic religions), while indeterminism refers to human free will in face of karma (Hinduism and Buddhism) or God (monotheistic religions). So, the question is: How is human free will related to nature, whether nature is deterministic or indeterministic, and also how is human free will related to the determinism of karma and the determinism of God? More simply put, how are humans, while their free will is in tension with karma, related to nature and God? Given that kind of free will, are humans compatible or incompatible with nature and God?

In Eastern religions, the problem of karma, resulting from past human sinfulness, causes a difficulty to human free will. We can find its counterpart in monotheistic religions which also talk about the consequences of sin that limit our free will. Because of this, there have always been some reservations about the fully compatible relationship of God, humans, and nature. But, recent theology tends to go beyond sin to much more positively appreciate it. For example, Open theism among others maintains that God gave us free will because of his love for us. If so, our free will, when used properly, is expected not to separate us from God but to unite us with him. Also, our free will is understood to let us have a dominion of love and unity over nature on behalf of God. Hence open theism affirms human free will’s compatibility with God and also with nature. With this scenario, God is still all-knowing and all-powerful, given a new definition of the perfection of God centered on love. This more positive picture of the compatibility of God, humans, and nature, seems to be basically in agreement with the Whiteheadian thesis that all actual entities, including God, harmoniously determine one another, while at the same time they each have their own self-determination.

The second question of whether free will entails moral responsibility, is answered in the affirmative especially by compatibilists and libertarians. It can be observed that most religious people, regardless of the diversity of their religious and denominational affiliations, affirm moral responsibility as compatibilists.

Notes

  1. Peter van Inwagen. An Essay on Free Will. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983).
  2. David Lewis, «Are We Free to Break the Laws?» Theoria 47 (1981): 112-121.
  3. Roderick Chisholm. Human Freedom and the Self: Lindley Lecture. (Lawrence: University of Kansas, 1964).
  4. Alfred North Whitehead. Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology, corrected ed., ed. David Ray Griffin and Donald W. Sherburne. (New York: Free Press, 1978).
  5. J. J. C. Smart, «Free Will, Praise and Blame.» Mind 70 (1961): 291-306.
  6. Robert Kane, «Responsibility, Luck, and Chance: Reflections on Free Will and Indeterminism.» Journal of Philosophy 96 (5) (1999): 217-240.
  7. Robert Kane. The Significance of Free Will. (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996).
  8. Steven Pinker. The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature. (London: Penguin, 2002), 179.
  9. Benjamin Libet, «Unconscious Cerebral Initiative and the Role of Conscious Will in Voluntary Action,» Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1985): 529–566.
  10. Daniel M. Wegner. The Illusion of Conscious Will. (MIT Press, 2002).
  11. Swami Vivekananda, «Freedom,» in Karma-Yoga. (The Complete Works of Swami Vivekananda, vol. 1.)
  12. R. Krishnaswami Aiyar. Dialogues with the Guru. (Bombay: Chetana Limited, 1957.)
  13. Nicholas Gier and Paul Kjellberg, «Buddhism and the Freedom of the Will: Pali and Mahayanist Responses,» in Freedom and Determinism, ed. Joseph Keim Campbell, Michael O’Rourke, and David Shier (MIT Press, 2004).
  14. Thanissaro Bhikkhu. Dhammapada: A Translation. (Barre, MA: Dhamma Dana Publications, 1997).
  15. Moshe Chaim Luzzatto, Mesillat Yesharim (Path of the Just), chapt. 1.shechem.org. Retrieved July 30, 2007.
  16. [1] Pirkei Avoth 3:19. Retrieved July 30, 2007.
  17. Maimonides, «The Law of Repentance» 5:5, in Mishneh Torah. Retrieved July 31, 2007.
  18. Montgomery Watt. Free-Will and Predestination in Early Islam. (London: Luzac & Co., 1948); Harry Wolfson. The Philosophy of the Kalam. (Harvard University Press, 1976)
  19. Boethius. The Consolation of Philosophy, trans. P. G. Walsh. (Oxford University Press, 2000).
  20. Jonathan Edwards, Freedom of the Will 84. Retrieved July 31, 2007.
  21. John Wesley, «On Working Out Our Own Salvation,» in Wesley’s Works, 3rd ed., vol. 6. (Kansas City, Mo.: Beacon Hill Press, 1979), 506-513.
  22. Christopher A. Hall and John Sanders. Does God Have a Future?: A Debate on Divine Providence. (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 2003), 12-13.
  23. John Sanders. The God Who Risks: A Theology of Providence. 11, 225

References

ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Aiyar, R. Krishnaswami. Dialogues with the Guru. Bombay: Chetana Limited, 1977 (original 1957). ISBN 0856554820
  • Boethius. The Consolation of Philosophy, Translated by P. G. Walsh. Oxford University Press, 2000. ISBN 0192838830
  • Bohm, David. A Suggested Interpretation of the Quantum Theory in Terms of ‘Hidden’ Variables, I and II. Physical Review 85 (1952): 166-193.
  • Chisholm, Roderick. Human Freedom and the Self: Lindley Lecture. Lawrence: University of Kansas, 1964.
  • Frankfurt, Harry. «Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility.» Journal of Philosophy 66 (23) (1969): 829-839.
  • Hall, Christopher A., and John Sanders. Does God Have a Future?: A Debate on Divine Providence. Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 2003. ISBN 0801026040
  • James, William. Pragmatism. (from Lectures November and December, 1906, and in January, 1907), London: NuVision, 2007. ISBN 1595477977
  • Kane, Robert. The Significance of Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press, 1996. ISBN 0195105508
  • Kane, Robert. «Responsibility, Luck, and Chance: Reflections on Free Will and Indeterminism.» Journal of Philosophy 96 (5) (1999): 217-240.
  • Kant, Immanuel. Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, James W. Ellington, trans. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993 (original 1785).
  • Lewis, David. «Are We Free to Break the Laws?» Theoria 47 (1981): 112-121.
  • Libet, Benjamin. «Unconscious Cerebral Initiative and the Role of Conscious Will in Voluntary Action.» Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1985): 529–566.
  • Morris, T.V. ‘Perfection and Creation’ in E. Stump (ed.) Reasoned Faith. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1993.
  • Pinker, Steven. The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature. London: Penguin, 2002. ISBN 0142003344
  • Sanders, John. The God Who Risks: A Theology of Providence. IVP Academic; 2nd ed., 2007. ISBN 0830828370
  • Smart, J.J.C. «Free Will, Praise and Blame.» Mind 70 (1961) : 291-306.
  • Suppes, Patrick. A Probabilistic Theory of Causality. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publication Company, 1970.
  • van Inwagen, Peter. An Essay on Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983. ISBN 0198249245
  • Watson, Gary, (ed.). Free Will, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003. ISBN 019925494X
  • Wegner, Daniel M. The Illusion of Conscious Will. MIT Press, 2002. ISBN 0262232227
  • Wesley, John. «On Working Out Our Own Salvation,» in Wesley’s Works, 3rd ed. Vol. 6. Kansas City, MO: Beacon Hill Press, 1979.
  • Whitehead, Alfred North. Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology, Corrected ed. Edited by David Ray Griffin and Donald W. Sherburne. (Gifford Lectures Delivered in the University of Edinburgh During the Session 1927-28). New York: Free Press, 1979. ISBN 0029345707

External links

All links retrieved May 10, 2017.

  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry on Free Will

General Philosophy Sources

  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • Paideia Project Online
  • Project Gutenberg

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article
in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

  • Free_will  history
  • Free_will  history
  • Free_will_in_theology  history

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

  • History of «Free Will»

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.

Free will in theology is an important part of the debate on free will in general. Religions vary greatly in their response to the standard argument against free will and thus might appeal to any number of responses to the paradox of free will, the claim that omniscience and free will are incompatible.

Overview

Main article: Argument From Free Will

The theological doctrine of divine foreknowledge is often alleged to be in conflict with free will, particularly in Calvinistic circles: if God knows exactly what will happen (right down to every choice a person makes), it would seem that the “freedom” of these choices is called into question.

This problem is related to the Aristotelian problem of the sea battle: tomorrow either there will or will not be a sea battle. According to the Law of excluded middle, there seems to be two options. If there will be sea battle, then it seems that it was true even yesterday that there would be one. Thus it is necessary that the sea battle will occur. If there will not be one, then, by similar reasoning, it is necessary that it will not occur. That means that the future, whatever it is, is completely fixed by past truths: true propositions about the future (a deterministic conclusion is reached: things could not have been any other way).

However, some philosophers follow William of Ockham in holding that necessity and possibility are defined with respect to a given point in time and a given matrix of empirical circumstances, and so something that is merely possible from the perspective of one observer may be necessary from the perspective of an omniscient. Some philosophers follow Philo in holding that free will is a feature of a human’s soul, and thus that non-human animals lack free will.

Doors Choose Decision Opportunity Selection Input

Doors and your free will

Common defenses

Jewish philosophy stresses that free will is a product of the intrinsic human soul, using the word neshama (from the Hebrew root n.sh.m. or .נ.ש.מ meaning “breath”), but the ability to make a free choice is through Yechida(from Hebrew word “yachid”, יחיד, singular), the part of the soul that is united with God, the only being that is not hindered by or dependent on cause and effect (thus, freedom of will does not belong to the realm of the physical reality, and inability of natural philosophy to account for it is expected).

In Islam, the theological issue is not usually how to reconcile free will with God’s foreknowledge but with God’s jabr or divine commanding power. al-Ash’ari developed an “acquisition” or “dual-agency” form of compatibilism, in which human free will and divine jabr were both asserted, and which became a cornerstone of the dominant Ash’ari position. In Shia Islam, Ash’aris understanding of a higher balance toward predestination is challenged by most theologists.Free will, according to Islamic doctrine is the main factor for man’s accountability in his/her actions throughout life. All actions committed by man’s free will are said to be counted on the Day of Judgement because they are his/her own and not God’s.

The philosopher Søren Kierkegaard claimed that divine omnipotence cannot be separated from divine goodness. As a truly omnipotent and good being, God could create beings with true freedom over God. Furthermore, God would voluntarily do so because “the greatest good… which can be done for a being, greater than anything else that one can do for it, is to be truly free.” Alvin Plantinga’s “free will defense” is a contemporary expansion of this theme, adding how God, free will, and evil are consistent.

Christianity

In the Bible

The biblical ground for free will lies in the fall into sin by Adam and Eve that occurred in their “willfully chosen” disobedience to God.

“Freedom” and “free will” can be treated as one because the two terms are commonly used as synonyms. However, there are widespread disagreements in definitions of the two terms. Because of these disagreements, Mortimer Adler found that a delineation of three kinds of freedom is necessary for clarity on the subject, as follows:

(1) Circumstantial freedom is “freedom from coercion or restraint” that prevents acting as one wills.

  • In the Bible, circumstantial freedom was given to the Israelites in The Exodus from slavery in Egypt.

(2) Natural freedom (a.k.a. volitional freedom) is freedom to determine one’s own “decisions or plans.” Natural freedom is inherent in all people, in all circumstances, and “without regard to any state of mind or character which they may or may not acquire in the course of their lives.”

  • The Bible, paralleling Adler, views all humanity as naturally possessing the “free choice of the will.” If “free will” is taken to mean unconstrained and voluntary choice, the Bible assumes that all people, unregenerate and regenerate, possess it. For examples, “free will” is taught in Matthew 23:37 and Revelation 22:17.

(3) Acquired freedom is freedom “to live as [one] ought to live,” a freedom that requires a transformation whereby a person acquires a righteous, holy, healthy, etc. “state of mind or character.”

  • The Bible testifies to the need for acquired freedom because no one “is free for obedience and faith till he is freed from sin’s dominion.” People possess natural freedom but their “voluntary choices” serve sin until they acquire freedom from “sin’s dominion.” The New Bible Dictionary denotes this acquired freedom for “obedience and faith” as “free will” in a theological sense. Therefore, in biblical thinking, an acquired freedom from being “enslaved to sin” is needed “to live up to Jesus’ commandments to love God and love neighbor.”
  • Jesus told his hearers that they needed to be made “free indeed” (John 8:36). “Free indeed [ontós]” means “truly free” or “really free,” as it is in some translations. Being made “free indeed” means freedom from “bondage to sin.” This acquired freedom is “freedom to serve the Lord.” Being “free indeed” (i.e., true freedom) comes by “God’s changing our nature” to free us from being “slaves to sin.” and endowing us with “the freedom to choose to be righteous.”

Mark R. Talbot, a “classical Christian theist,” views this acquired “compatibilist freedom” as the freedom that “Scripture portrays as worth having.”

Open theism denies that classical theism’s compatibilist “freedom to choose to be righteous without the possibility of choosing otherwise.” qualifies as true freedom. For open theism, true libertarian freedom is incompatibilist freedom. Regardless of factors, a person has the freedom to choose opposite alternatives. In open theist William Hasker’s words, regarding any action it is always “within the agent’s power to perform the action and also in the agent’s power to refrain from the action.” Although open theism generally contradicts classical theism’s “freedom to choose to be righteous without the possibility of choosing otherwise,” Hasker allows that Jesus possessed and humans in heaven will possess such a freedom. Regarding Jesus, Hasker views Jesus as “a free agent,” but he also thinks that “it was not really possible” that Jesus would “abort the mission.” Regarding heaven, Hasker foresees that as the result of our choice we will be “unable to sin” because all sinful impulses will be gone.

Roman Catholic

Theologians of the Roman Catholic Church universally embrace the idea of free will, but generally do not view free will as existing apart from or in contradiction to grace. According to the Roman Catholic Church “To God, all moments of time are present in their immediacy. When therefore he establishes his eternal plan of “predestination”, he includes in it each person’s free response to his grace.” The Council of Trent declared that “the free will of man, moved and excited by God, can by its consent co-operate with God, Who excites and invites its action; and that it can thereby dispose and prepare itself to obtain the grace of justification. The will can resist grace if it chooses. It is not like a lifeless thing, which remains purely passive. Weakened and diminished by Adam’s fall, free will is yet not destroyed in the race (Sess. VI, cap. i and v).”

St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas wrote extensively on free will, with Augustine focusing on the importance of free will in his responses to the Manichaeans, and also on the limitations of a concept of unlimited free will as denial of grace, in his refutations of Pelagius.

The Catechism of the Roman Catholic Church asserts that “Freedom is the power, rooted in reason and will”. It goes on to say that “God created man a rational being, conferring on him the dignity of a person who can initiate and control his own actions. God willed that man should be ‘left in the hand of his own counsel,’ so that he might of his own accord seek his Creator and freely attain his full and blessed perfection by cleaving to him.”” The section concludes with the role that grace plays, “By the working of grace the Holy Spirit educates us in spiritual freedom in order to make us free collaborators in his work in the Church and in the world.”

Latin Christianity’s views on free will and grace are often contrasted with predestination in Reformed Protestant Christianity, especially after the Counter-Reformation, but in understanding differing conceptions of free will it is just as important to understand the differing conceptions of the nature of God, focusing on the idea that God can be all-powerful and all-knowing even while people continue to exercise free will, because God transcends time.

The papal encyclical on human freedom, Libertas Praestantissimum by Pope Leo XIII (1888), seems to leave the question unresolved as to the relation between free will and determinism: whether the correct notion is the compatibilist one or the libertarian one. The quotations supporting compatibilism include the one from St. Thomas (footnote 4) near the end of paragraph 6, regarding the cause of evil (“Whereas, when he sins, he acts in opposition to reason, is moved by another, and is the victim of foreign misapprehensions”), and a similar passus suggesting a natural, cause-and-effect function of human will (“harmony with his natural inclinations”, “Creator of will”, “by whom all things are moved in conformity with their nature”) near the end of paragraph 8 (when considering the problem of how grace can have effects on free will). On the other hand, metaphysical libertarianism – at least as a sort of possibility of reversing the direction of one’s acting – is suggested by the reference to the well-known philosophical term metaphysical freedom at the beginning of paragraph 3 and, to an extent, a contrasting comparison of animals, which always act “of necessity”, with human liberty, by means of which one can “either act or not act, do this or do that”.

Critique that seems more or less to support popular incompatibilistic views can be found in some papal documents especially in the 20th century, no explicit condemnation, however, of causal determinism in its most generic form can be found there. More often these documents focus on condemnation of physicalism/materialism and the stressing of significance of belief in soul, as a non-physical indivisible substance equipped with intellect and will, which decides human proceeding in a (perhaps imprecise) way.

Orthodox Christianity

Oriental Orthodox

The concept of free will is also of vital importance in the Oriental (or non-Chalcedonian) Churches, those in communion with the Coptic Orthodox Church of Alexandria. As in Judaism, free will is regarded as axiomatic. Everyone is regarded as having a free choice as to in what measure he or she will follow his or her conscience or arrogance, these two having been appointed for each individual. The more one follows one’s conscience, the more it brings one good results, and the more one follows one’s arrogance, the more it brings one bad results. Following only one’s arrogance is sometimes likened to the dangers of falling into a pit while walking in pitch darkness, without the light of conscience to illuminate the path. Very similar doctrines have also found written expression in the Dead Sea Scrolls “Manual of Discipline”, and in some religious texts possessed by the Beta Israel Jews of Ethiopia.

Eastern Orthodox

The Eastern (or Chalcedonian) Orthodox Church espouses a belief different from the Lutheran, Calvinist, and Arminian Protestant views. The difference is in the interpretation of original sin, alternatively known as “ancestral sin,” where the Orthodox do not believe in total depravity. The Orthodox reject the Pelagian view that the original sin did not damage human nature; they accept that the human nature is depraved, but despite man’s fallenness the divine image he bears has not been destroyed.

The Orthodox Church holds to the teaching of synergy (συνεργός, meaning working together), which says that man has the freedom to, and must if he wants to be saved, choose to accept and work with the grace of God. St. John Cassian, a 4th-century Church Father and pupil of St. John Chrysostom, articulated this view and all the Eastern Fathers embraced it. He taught that “Divine grace is necessary to enable a sinner to return unto God and live, yet man must first, of himself, desire and attempt to choose and obey God”, and that “Divine grace is indispensable for salvation, but it does not necessarily need to precede a free human choice, because, despite the weakness of human volition, the will can take the initiative toward God.”.

Some Orthodox Christians use the parable of a drowning man to plainly illustrate the teaching of synergy: God from the ship throws a rope to a drowning man, pulls him up, saving him, and the man, if he wants to be saved, must hold on tightly to the rope; explaining both that salvation is a gift from God and man cannot save himself, and that man must co-work (syn-ergo) with God in the process of salvation.

Fyodor Dostoevsky, the Russian Orthodox Christian novelist, suggested many arguments for and against free will. Famous arguments are found in “The Grand Inquisitor” chapter in The Brothers Karamazov, and in his work Notes from Underground. He also developed an argument that suicide, if irrational, is actually a validation of free will (see Kirilov in the Demons) novel. As for the argument presented in The Brothers Karamazov’s section “The Rebellion” that the suffering of innocents was not worth the price of free will, Dostoevsky appears to propose the idea of apocatastasis (or universal reconciliation) as one possible rational solution.

Roman Catholic teaching

Illustrating as it does that the human part in salvation (represented by holding on to the rope) must be preceded and accompanied by grace (represented by the casting and drawing of the rope), the image of the drowning man holding on to the rope cast and drawn by his rescuer corresponds closely to Roman Catholic teaching, which holds that God, who “destined us in love to be his sons” and “to be conformed to the image of his Son”,includes in his eternal plan of “predestination” each person’s free response to his grace.

The Roman Catholic Church holds to the teaching that “by free will, (the human person) is capable of directing himself toward his true good … man is endowed with freedom, an outstanding manifestation of the divine image’.” Man has free will either to accept or reject the grace of God, so that for salvation “there is a kind of interplay, or synergy, between human freedom and divine grace”. “Justification establishes cooperation between God’s grace and man’s freedom. On man’s part it is expressed by the assent of faith to the Word of God, which invites him to conversion, and in the cooperation of charity with the prompting of the Holy Spirit who precedes and preserves his assent: ‘When God touches man’s heart through the illumination of the Holy Spirit, man himself is not inactive while receiving that inspiration, since he could reject it; and yet, without God’s grace, he cannot by his own free will move himself toward justice in God’s sight’ (Council of Trent).”

God has freely chosen to associate man with the work of his grace. the fatherly action of God is first on his own initiative, and then follows man’s free acting through his collaboration. For Roman Catholics, therefore, human cooperation with grace is essential. When God establishes his eternal plan of ‘predestination’, he includes in it each person’s free response to his grace, whether it is positive or negative: “In this city, in fact, both Herod and Pontius Pilate, with the Gentiles and the peoples of Israel, gathered together against your holy servant Jesus, whom you anointed, to do whatever your hand and your plan had predestined to take place” (Acts 4:27-28).

The initiative comes from God, but it demands a free response from man: “God has freely chosen to associate man with the work of his grace. the fatherly action of God is first on his own initiative, and then follows man’s free acting through his collaboration”. “Since the initiative belongs to God in the order of grace, no one can merit the initial grace of forgiveness and justification, at the beginning of conversion. Moved by the Holy Spirit and by charity, we can then merit for ourselves and for others the graces needed for our sanctification, for the increase of grace and charity, and for the attainment of eternal life.”

Orthodox criticism of Roman Catholic theology

Orthodox theologian Vladimir Lossky has stated that the teaching of John Cassian, who in the East is considered a witness to Tradition, but who “was unable to make himself correctly understood”, “was interpreted, on the rational plane, as a semi-pelagianism, and was condemned in the West”. Where the Roman Catholic Church defends the concept of faith and free will these are questioned in the East by the conclusions of the Second Council of Orange. This council is not accepted by the Eastern churches and the Roman Catholic Church’s useof describing their position and St Cassian as Semi-Pelagian is also rejected.

Although the Roman Catholic Church explicitly teaches that “original sin does not have the character of a personal fault in any of Adam’s descendants”, some Eastern Orthodox nevertheless claim that Roman Catholicism professes the teaching, which they attribute to Saint Augustine, that everyone bears not only the consequence, but also the guilt of Adam’s sin.

Differences of view between Roman Catholic and Orthodox Churches

Various Roman Catholic theologians identify Cassian as a teacher of the semipelagian heresy which was condemned by the Council of Orange.While the Orthodox do not apply the term semipelagian to their theology, they criticize the Roman Catholics for rejecting Cassian whom they accept as fully orthodox, and for holding that human consent to God’s justifying action is itself an effect of grace, a position shared by Eastern Orthodox theologian Georges Florovsky, who says that the Eastern Orthodox Church “always understood that God initiates, accompanies, and completes everything in the process of salvation”, rejecting instead the Calvinist idea of irresistible grace.

Recently, some Roman Catholic theologians have argued that Cassian’s writings should not be considered semipelagian. And scholars of other denominations too have concluded that Cassian’s thought “is not Semi-Pelagian”, and that he instead taught that “salvation is, from beginning to end, the effect of God’s grace” and held that “God’s grace, not human free will, is responsible for ‘everything which pertains to salvation’ – even faith.”

The Orthodox Church holds to the teaching of synergy (συνεργός, meaning working together), which says that man has the freedom to, and must if he wants to be saved, choose to accept and work with the grace of God. Once baptised the experience of his salvation and relationship with God is called theosis. Mankind has free will to accept or reject the grace of God. Rejection of the gifts of God is called blasphemy of the Holy Spirit (gifts of grace, faith, life). The first who defined this teaching was John Cassian, 4th-century Church Father, and a pupil of John Chrysostom, and all Eastern Fathers accept it. He taught that “Divine grace is necessary to enable a sinner to return unto God and live, yet man must first, of himself, desire and attempt to choose and obey God”, and that “Divine grace is indispensable for salvation, but it does not necessarily need to precede a free human choice, because, despite the weakness of human volition, the will can take the initiative toward God.”.

Some Orthodox use an example of a drowning man to illustrate the teaching of synergy: God from the ship throws a rope to a drowning man, the man may take the rope if he wants to be saved, but he may decide not to take the rope and perish by his own will. Explaining both that salvation is a gift from God and man cannot save himself. That man must co-work (syn-ergo) with God in the process of salvation.

Protestant

Arminianism

Main article: History of Calvinist–Arminian debate

Christians who were influenced by the teachings of Jacobus Arminius (such as Methodists) believe that while God is all-knowing and always knows what choices each person will make, and he still gives them the ability to choose or not choose everything, regardless of whether there are any internal or external factors contributing to that choice.

Like John Calvin, Arminius affirmed total depravity, but Arminius believed that only prevenient grace allowed people to choose salvation:

Concerning grace and free will, this is what I teach according to the Scriptures and orthodox consent: Free will is unable to begin or to perfect any true and spiritual good, without grace…. This grace [prœvenit] goes before, accompanies, and follows; it excites, assists, operates that we will, and co operates lest we will in vain.

Prevenient grace is divine grace which precedes human decision. It exists prior to and without reference to anything humans may have done. As humans are corrupted by the effects of sin, prevenient grace allows persons to engage their God-given free will to choose the salvation offered by God in Jesus Christ or to reject that salvific offer.

Thomas Jay Oord offers perhaps the most cogent free will theology presupposing prevenient grace. What he calls “essential kenosis” says God acts preveniently to give freedom/agency to all creatures. This gift comes from God’s eternal essence, and is therefore necessary. God remains free in choosing how to love, but the fact that God loves and therefore gives freedom/agency to others is a necessary part of what it means to be divine.

This view is backed in the Bible with verses such as Luke 13:34, NKJV

O Jerusalem, Jerusalem, the one who kills the prophets and stones those who are sent to her! How often I wanted to gather your children together, as a hen gathers her brood under her wings, but you were not willing!”

Here we see Jesus lamenting that He is unable to save Jerusalem as they are not willing. We see that whilst Jesus wants to save Jerusalem He respects their choice to continue on in sin despite His will that they be saved.

Lutheranism

Main article: Lutheranism

A.C. Article 18: Of Free Will

A.C. Article 18: Of Free Will

Lutherans believe that although humans have free will concerning civil righteousness, they cannot work spiritual righteousness without the Holy Spirit, since righteousness in the heart cannot be wrought in the absence of the Holy Spirit. In other words, humanity is free to choose and act in every regard except for the choice of salvation.

Lutherans also teach that sinners, while capable of doing works that are outwardly “good,” are not capable of doing works that satisfy God’s justice. Every human thought and deed is infected with sin and sinful motives. For Luther himself, in his Bondage of the Will, people are by nature endowed with free-will/free choice in regard to “goods and possessions” with which a person “has the right of using, acting, and omitting according to his Free-will.” However, in “God-ward” things pertaining to “salvation or damnation” people are in bondage “either to the will of God, or to the will of Satan.”

As found in Paul Althaus’ study of Luther’s theology, sin’s infection of every human thought and deed began with Adam’s fall into sin, the Original Sin. Adam’s fall was a “terrible example” of what “free will” will do unless God constantly motivates it to virtuous behavior. Humanity inherits Adam’s sin. Thus, in our “natural condition,” we have an inborn desire to sin because that is the person we are by birth. As Luther noted, “Adam sinned willingly and freely and from him a will to sin has been born into us so that we cannot sin innocently but only voluntarily.”

The controversial term liberum arbitrium was translated “free-will” by Henry Cole and “free will” remains in general use. However, the Rupp/Watson study of Luther and Erasmus chose “free choice” as the translation and provided a rationale. Luther used “free choice” (or “free-will”) to denote the fact that humans act “spontaneously” and with “a desirous willingness.” He also allowed “Free-will” as that “power” by which humans “can be caught by the Spirit” of God. However, he deplored the use of the term “Free-will” because it is too “grand, copious, and full.” Therefore, Luther held that the inborn faculty of “willingness” should be “called by some other term.”

Although our wills are a function of and are in bondage to our inherited sinful desires, Luther insisted that we sin “voluntarily.” Voluntarily means that we sin of our own free will. We will to do what we desire. As long as we desire sin, our wills are only free for sin. This is Luther’s “bondage of the will” to sin. The sinner’s “will is bound, but it is and remains his will. He repeatedly and voluntarily acts according to it.” So it is, to be set free from sin and for righteousness requires a “rebirth through faith.” A rebirth of faith gives “true freedom from sin,” which is, wrote Luther, “a liberty [freedom] to do good.”

To use a biblical word important to Luther, to be set free from sin and for righteousness requires a metanoia. Luther used Jesus’ image of the good and bad trees to depict the necessity of changing the person to change what a person wills and does. In Jesus’ image, “a good tree cannot bear bad fruit, and a bad tree cannot bear good fruit” (Matthew 7:18). Like the bad tree that can only produce bad fruit, before a rebirth through faith, people are in bondage to the sinful desires of their hearts. They can only will to do sin, albeit “spontaneously and with a desirous willingness.” Given his view of the human condition, Luther concluded that, without a rebirth, the “free choice” that all humans possess is “not free at all” because it cannot of itself free itself from its inherent bondage to sin.

Thus, Luther distinguished between different kinds of freedom: (a) by nature, a freedom to act as we will and (b) by rebirth through faith, a freedom to act righteously.

God and creation

Orthodox Lutheran theology holds that God made the world, including humanity, perfect, holy and sinless. However, Adam and Eve chose to disobey God, trusting in their own strength, knowledge, and wisdom.Consequently, people are saddled with original sin, born sinful and unable to avoid committing sinful acts. For Lutherans, original sin is the “chief sin, a root and fountainhead of all actual sins.”

According to Lutherans, God preserves his creation, in doing so cooperates with everything that happens, and guides the universe. While God cooperates with both good and evil deeds, with evil deeds he does so only inasmuch as they are deeds, but not with the evil in them. God concurs with an act’s effect, but he does not cooperate in the corruption of an act or the evil of its effect. Lutherans believe everything exists for the sake of the Christian Church, and that God guides everything for its welfare and growth.

Predestination

Lutherans believe that the elect are predestined to salvation. Lutherans believe Christians should be assured that they are among the predestined. Lutherans believe that all who trust in Jesus alone can be certain of their salvation, for it is in Christ’s work and his promises in which their certainty lies. According to Lutheranism, the central final hope of the Christian is “the resurrection of the body and the life everlasting” as confessed in the Apostles’ Creed rather than predestination. Conversion or regeneration in the strict sense of the term is the work of divine grace and power by which man, born of the flesh, and void of all power to think, to will, or to do any good thing, and dead in sin is, through the gospel and holy baptism, taken from a state of sin and spiritual death under God’s wrath into a state of spiritual life of faith and grace, rendered able to will and to do what is spiritually good and, especially, led to accept the benefits of the redemption which is in Christ Jesus.

Lutherans disagree with those that make predestination the source of salvation rather than Christ’s suffering, death, and resurrection. Lutherans reject the Calvinist doctrine of the perseverance of the saints. Like both Calvinist camps, Lutherans view the work of salvation as monergistic in that “the natural [that is, corrupted and divinely unrenewed] powers of man cannot do anything or help towards salvation” (Formula of Concord: Solid Declaration, art. ii, par. 71), and Lutherans go further along the same lines as the Free Grace advocates to say that the recipient of saving grace need not cooperate with it. Hence, Lutherans believe that a true Christian (that is, a genuine recipient of saving grace) can lose his or her salvation, “[b]ut the cause is not as though God were unwilling to grant grace for perseverance to those in whom He has begun the good work… [but that these persons] wilfully turn away…” (Formula of Concord: Solid Declaration, art. xi, par. 42). Unlike Calvinists, Lutherans do not believe in a predestination to damnation. Instead, Lutherans teach eternal damnation is a result of the unbeliever’s sins, rejection of the forgiveness of sins, and unbelief.

Anabaptism

The Anabaptist movement was characterized by the fundamental belief in the free will of man. Many earlier movements such as Waldensians and others likewise held this viewpoint. Denominations today representing this view include Old Order Mennonites, Amish, and Conservative Mennonites.

Calvinism

Main article: Calvinism

John Calvin ascribed “free will” to all people in the sense that they act “voluntarily, and not by compulsion.” He elaborated his position by allowing “that man has choice and that it is self-determined” and that his actions stem from “his own voluntary choosing.”

The free will that Calvin ascribed to all people is what Mortimer Adler calls the “natural freedom” of the will. This freedom to will what one desires is inherent in all people.

Calvin held this kind of inherent/natural free will in disesteem because unless people acquire the freedom to live as they ought by being transformed, they will desire and voluntarily choose to sin. “Man is said to have free will,” wrote Calvin, “because he acts voluntarily, and not by compulsion. This is perfectly true: but why should so small a matter have been dignified with so proud a title?” The glitch in this inherent/natural freedom of the will is that although all people have the “faculty of willing,” by nature they are unavoidably (and yet voluntarily without compulsion) under “the bondage of sin.”

The kind of free will that Calvin esteems is what Adler calls “acquired freedom” of the will, the freedom/ability “to live as [one] ought.” To possess acquired free will requires a change by which a person acquires a desire to live a life marked by virtuous qualities. As Calvin describes the change required for acquired freedom, the will “must be wholly transformed and renovated.”

Calvin depicts this transformation as “a new heart and a new spirit (Ezek. 18:31).” It sets one free from “bondage to sin” and enables “piety towards God, and love towards men, general holiness and purity of life.”

Calvinist Protestants embrace the idea of predestination, namely, that God chose who would be saved and who would be not saved prior to the creation. They quote Ephesians 1:4 “For he chose us in him before the creation of the world to be holy and blameless in his sight” and also 2:8 “For it is by grace you are saved, through faith, and this not of yourselves, it is the gift of God.” One of the strongest defenders of this theological point of view was the American Puritan preacher and theologian Jonathan Edwards.

Edwards believed that indeterminism was incompatible with individual dependence on God and hence with his sovereignty. He reasoned that if individuals’ responses to God’s grace are contra-causally free, then their salvation depends partly on them and therefore God’s sovereignty is not “absolute and universal.” Edwards’ book Freedom of the Will defends theological determinism. In this book, Edwards attempts to show that libertarianism is incoherent. For example, he argues that by ‘self-determination’ the libertarian must mean either that one’s actions including one’s acts of willing are preceded by an act of free will or that one’s acts of will lack sufficient causes. The first leads to an infinite regress while the second implies that acts of will happen accidentally and hence can’t make someone “better or worse, any more than a tree is better than other trees because it oftener happens to be lit upon by a swan or nightingale; or a rock more vicious than other rocks, because rattlesnakes have happened oftener to crawl over it.”

It should not be thought that this view completely denies freedom of choice, however. It claims that man is free to act on his strongest moral impulse and volition, which is externally determined, but is not free to act contrary to them, or to alter them. Proponents, such as John L. Girardeau, have indicated their belief that moral neutrality is impossible; that even if it were possible, and one were equally inclined to contrary options, one could make no choice at all; that if one is inclined, however slightly, toward one option, then that person will necessarily choose that one over any others.

Some non-Calvinist Christians attempt a reconciliation of the dual concepts of predestination and free will by pointing to the situation of God as Christ. In taking the form of a man, a necessary element of this process was that Jesus Christ lived the existence of a mortal. When Jesus was born he was not born with the omniscient power of God the Creator, but with the mind of a human child – yet he was still God in essence. The precedent this creates is that God is able to will the abandonment of His knowledge, or ignore knowledge, while remaining fully God. Thus it is not inconceivable that although omniscience demands that God knows what the future holds for individuals, it is within his power to deny this knowledge in order to preserve individual free will. Other theologians argue that the Calvinist-Edwardsean view suggests that if all human volitions are predetermined by God, then all actions dictated by fallen will of man necessarily satisfy His sovereign decree. Hence, it is impossible to act outside of God’s perfect will, a conclusion some non-Calvinists claim poses a serious problem for ethics and moral theology.

An early proposal toward such a reconciliation states that God is, in fact, not aware of future events, but rather, being eternal, He is outside time, and sees the past, present, and future as one whole creation. Consequently, it is not as though God would know “in advance” that Jeffrey Dahmer would become guilty of homicide years prior to the event as an example, but that He was aware of it from all eternity, viewing all time as a single present. This was the view offered by Boethius in Book V of The Consolation of Philosophy.

Calvinist theologian Loraine Boettner argued that the doctrine of divine foreknowledge does not escape the alleged problems of divine foreordination. He wrote that “what God foreknows must, in the very nature of the case, be as fixed and certain as what is foreordained; and if one is inconsistent with the free agency of man, the other is also. Foreordination renders the events certain, while foreknowledge presupposes that they are certain.” Some Christian theologians, feeling the bite of this argument, have opted to limit the doctrine of foreknowledge if not do away with it altogether, thus forming a new school of thought, similar to Socinianism and process theology, called open theism.

Comparison of Protestants

This table summarizes three classical Protestant beliefs about free will.

John Calvin Martin Luther Jacob Arminius
For Calvin, humanity possesses “free will,” but it is in bondage to sin, unless it is “transformed.” For Luther, humanity possesses free-will/free choice in regard to “goods and possessions,” but regarding “salvation or damnation” people are in bondage either to God or Satan.” For Arminius, humanity possesses freedom from necessity, but not “freedom from sin” unless enabled by “prevenient grace.”

Church of Jesus Christ of Latter-day Saints

Main article: Agency In LDS Church

Mormons or Latter-day Saints, believe that God has given all humans the gift of moral agency. Moral agency includes free will and agency. Proper exercise of unfettered choice leads to the ultimate goal of returning to God’s presence. Having the choice to do right or wrong was important, because God wants a society of a certain type—those that comply with eternal laws. Before this Earth was created, this dispute over agency rose to the level that there was a “war in heaven.” Lucifer (who favored no agency) and his followers were cast out of heaven for rebelling against God’s will. Many Mormon leaders have also taught that the battle in Heaven over agency is now being carried out on earth, where dictators, influenced by Satan, fight against freedom (or free agency) in governments contrary to the will of God.

Mormons also believe in a limited form of foreordination — not in deterministic, unalterable decrees, but rather in callings from God for individuals to perform specific missions in mortality. Those who are foreordained can reject the foreordination, either outright or by transgressing the laws of God and becoming unworthy to fulfill the call.

New Church

The New Church, or Swedenborgianism, teaches that every person has complete freedom to choose heaven or hell. Emanuel Swedenborg, upon whose writings the New Church is founded, argued that if God is love itself, people must have free will. If God is love itself, then He desires no harm to come to anyone: and so it is impossible that he would predestine anyone to hell. On the other hand, if God is love itself, then He must love things outside of Himself; and if people do not have the freedom to choose evil, they are simply extensions of God, and He cannot love them as something outside of Himself. In addition, Swedenborg argues that if a person does not have free will to choose goodness and faith, then all of the commandments in the Bible to love God and the neighbor are worthless, since no one can choose to do them – and it is impossible that a God who is love itself and wisdom itself would give impossible commandments.

Hinduism

As Hinduism is primarily a conglomerate of different religious traditions, there is no one accepted view on the concept of free will. Within the predominant schools of Hindu philosophy there are two main opinions. The Advaita (monistic) schools generally believe in a fate-based approach, and the Dvaita (dualistic) schools are proponents for the theory of free will. The different schools’ understandings are based upon their conceptions of the nature of the supreme Being (see Brahman, Paramatma and Ishvara) and how the individual soul (atma or jiva) dictates, or is dictated by karma within the illusory existence of maya.

In both Dvaita and Advaita schools, and also in the many other traditions within Hinduism, there is a strong belief in destiny and that both the past and future are known, or viewable, by certain saints or mystics as well as by the supreme being (Ishvara) in traditions where Ishvara is worshipped as an all-knowing being. In the Bhagavad Gita, the Avatar, Krishna says to Arjuna:

  • I know everything that has happened in the past, all that is happening in the present, and all things that are yet to come.

However, this belief in destiny is not necessarily believed to rule out the existence of free will, as in some cases both free will and destiny are believed to exist simultaneously.

The Bhagavad Gita also states:

Nor does the Supreme Lord assume anyone’s sinful or pious activities (Bhagavad Gita 5.15)
From wherever the mind wanders due to its flickering and unsteady nature, one must certainly withdraw it and bring it back under the control of the self (Bhagavad Gita 6.26), indicating that God does not control anyone’s will, and that it is possible to control the mind.

Different approaches

The six orthodox (astika) schools of thought in Hindu philosophy give differing opinions: In the Samkhya, for instance, matter is without any freedom, and soul lacks any ability to control the unfolding of matter. The only real freedom (kaivalya) consists in realizing the ultimate separateness of matter and self. For the Yoga school, only Ishvara is truly free, and its freedom is also distinct from all feelings, thoughts, actions, or wills, and is thus not at all a freedom of will. The metaphysics of the Nyaya and Vaisheshika schools strongly suggest a belief in determinism, but do not seem to make explicit claims about determinism or free will.

A quotation from Swami Vivekananda, a Vedantist, offers a good example of the worry about free will in the Hindu tradition.

Therefore, we see at once that there cannot be any such thing as free-will; the very words are a contradiction, because will is what we know, and everything that we know is within our universe, and everything within our universe is moulded by conditions of time, space and causality. … To acquire freedom we have to get beyond the limitations of this universe; it cannot be found here.

However, Vivekananda’s above quote can’t be taken as a literal refutation of all free will, as Vivekanda’s teacher, Ramakrishna Paramahansa used to teach that man is like a goat tied to a stake – the karmic debts and human nature bind him and the amount of free will he has is analogous to the amount of freedom the rope allows; as one progresses spiritually, the rope becomes longer.

On the other hand, Mimamsa, Vedanta, and the more theistic versions of Hinduism such as Shaivism and Vaishnavism have often emphasized the importance of free will. For example, in the Bhagavad Gita the living beings (jivas) are described as being of a higher nature who have the freedom to exploit the inferior material nature (prakrti):

Besides these, O mighty-armed Arjuna, there is another, superior energy of Mine, which comprises the living entities who are exploiting the resources of this material, inferior nature.

The doctrine of Karma in Hinduism requires both that we pay for our actions in the past, and that our actions in the present be free enough to allow us to deserve the future reward or punishment that we will receive for our present actions. The Advaitin philosopher Chandrashekhara Bharati Swaminah puts it this way:

Fate is past karma, free-will is present karma. Both are really one, that is, karma, though they may differ in the matter of time. There can be no conflict when they are really one. Fate, as I told you, is the resultant of the past exercise of your free-will. By exercising your free-will in the past, you brought on the resultant fate. By exercising your free-will in the present, I want you to wipe out your past record if it hurts you, or to add to it if you find it enjoyable. In any case, whether for acquiring more happiness or for reducing misery, you have to exercise your free-will in the present.

Islam

See also: Predestination in Islam

Disputes about free will in Islam began with the Mu’tazili vs Hanbali disputes, with the Mu’tazili arguing that humans had qadar, the capacity to do right or wrong, and thus deserved the reward or punishment they received, whereas Hanbali insisted on God’s jabr, or total power and initiative in managing all events. Schools that developed around earlier thinkers such as Abu Hanifa and al-Ash’ari searched for ways to explain how both human qadar and divine jabr could be asserted at the same time. Ash’ari develops a “dual agency” or “acquisition” account of free will in which every human action has two distinct agents. God creates the possibility of a human action with his divine jabr, but then the human follows through and “acquires” the act, making it theirs and taking responsibility for it using their human qadar.

Judaism

The belief in free will (Hebrew: bechirah chofshit בחירה חפשית, bechirah בחירה) is axiomatic in Jewish thought, and is closely linked with the concept of reward and punishment, based on the Torah itself: “I [God] have set before you life and death, blessing and curse: therefore choose life” ( Deuteronomy 30:19).

Free will is therefore discussed at length in Jewish philosophy, firstly as regards God’s purpose in creation, and secondly as regards the closely related, resultant, paradox. The topic is also often discussed in connection with Negative theology, Divine simplicity and Divine Providence, as well as Jewish principles of faith in general.

Free will and creation

The traditional teaching regarding the purpose of creation, particularly as influenced by Jewish mysticism, is that “This world is like a corridor to the World to Come”. “Man was created for the sole purpose of rejoicing in God, and deriving pleasure from the splendor of His Presence… The place where this joy may truly be derived is the World to Come, which was expressly created to provide for it; but the path to the object of our desires is this world…” Free will is thus required by God’s justice, “otherwise, Man would not be given or denied good for actions over which he had no control”.

It is further understood that in order for Man to have true free choice, he must not only have inner free will, but also an environment in which a choice between obedience and disobedience exists. God thus created the world such that both good and evil can operate freely, this is the meaning of the rabbinic maxim, “All is in the hands of Heaven except the fear of Heaven”.

According to Maimonides,

Free will is granted to every man. If he desires to incline towards the good way and be righteous, he has the power to do so; and if he desires to incline towards the unrighteous way and be a wicked man, he also has the power to do so. Give no place in your minds to that which is asserted by many of the ignorant: namely that the Holy One, blessed be He, decrees that a man from his birth should be either righteous or wicked. Since the power of doing good or evil is in our own hands, and since all the wicked deeds which we have committed have been committed with our full consciousness, it befits us to turn in penitence and to forsake our evil deed.

The paradox of free will

Main article: Argument From Free Will

In rabbinic literature, there is much discussion as to the apparent contradiction between God’s omniscience and free will. The representative view is that “Everything is foreseen; yet free will is given”. Based on this understanding, the problem is formally described as a paradox, beyond our understanding.

The Holy One, Blessed Be He, knows everything that will happen before it has happened. So does He know whether a particular person will be righteous or wicked, or not? If He does know, then it will be impossible for that person not to be righteous. If He knows that he will be righteous but that it is possible for him to be wicked, then He does not know everything that He has created. …[T]he Holy One, Blessed Be He, does not have any temperaments and is outside such realms, unlike people, whose selves and temperaments are two separate things. God and His temperaments are one, and God’s existence is beyond the comprehension of Man… [Thus] we do not have the capabilities to comprehend how the Holy One, Blessed Be He, knows all creations and events. [Nevertheless] know without doubt that people do what they want without the Holy One, Blessed Be He, forcing or decreeing upon them to do so… It has been said because of this that a man is judged according to all his actions.

— Maimonides, Mishneh Torah

The paradox is explained, but not resolved, by observing that God exists outside of time, and therefore, his knowledge of the future is exactly the same as his knowledge of the past and present. Just as his knowledge of the past does not interfere with man’s free will, neither does his knowledge of the future. This distinction, between foreknowledge and predestination, is in fact discussed by Abraham ibn Daud.

One analogy here is that of time travel. The time traveller, having returned from the future, knows in advance what x will do, but while he knows what x will do, that knowledge does not cause x to do so: x had free will, even while the time traveller had foreknowledge. One objection raised against this analogy – and ibn Daud’s distinction – is that if x truly has free will, he may choose to act otherwise when the event in question comes to pass, and therefore the time traveller (or God) merely has knowledge of a possible event: even having seen the event, there is no way to know with certainty what x will do; see the view of Gersonides below. Further, the presence of the time traveller, may have had some chaotic effect on x’s circumstances and choice, absent when the event comes to pass in the present.)

Alternate approaches

Although the above discussion of the paradox represents the majority Rabbinic view, there are several major thinkers who resolve the issue by explicitly excluding human action from divine foreknowledge.

Both Saadia Gaon and Judah ha-Levi hold that “the decisions of man precede God’s knowledge”. Gersonides holds that God knows, beforehand, the choices open to each individual, but does not know which choice the individual, in his freedom, will make. Isaiah Horowitz takes the view that God cannot know which moral choices people will make, but that, nevertheless, this does not impair his perfection.

In line with this thinking, the teaching from Pirkei Avoth above, is then to be read as: “Everything is observed (while – and no matter where – it happens), and (since the actor is unaware of being observed) free will is given “.

Kabbalistic thought

The existence of free will, and the paradox above (as addressed by either approach), is closely linked to the concept of TzimtzumTzimtzum entails the idea that God “constricted” his infinite essence, to allow for the existence of a “conceptual space” in which a finite, independent world could exist. This “constriction” made free will possible, and hence the potential to earn the World to Come.

Further, according to the first approach, it is understood that the Free-will Omniscience paradox provides a temporal parallel to the paradox inherent within Tzimtzum. In granting free will, God has somehow “constricted” his foreknowledge, to allow for Man’s independent action; He thus has foreknowledge and yet free will exists. In the case of Tzimtzum, God has “constricted” his essence to allow for Man’s independent existence; He is thus immanent and yet transcendent.

Adapted from Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Adjective



a freewill confession of guilt made by the suspect during police interrogation



our office staff made a freewill offering for UNESCO

Noun



He argues that all humans have free will.



all of the workers at the homeless shelter are unpaid and are there of their own free will

Recent Examples on the Web



Coach for Men captures the never-resting energy of the city that never sleeps and the freewill spontaneity of all those who call it home.


Dallas News, 30 Nov. 2022





All, too, will take place without a live audience and include links for freewill donations to nonprofits supporting Cleveland-area musicians and musical programs during coronavirus.


Zachary Lewis, cleveland, 2 June 2020





The free community event is sponsored by Spiritual Church of Escondido; freewill offering will be accepted.


San Diego Union-Tribune, 29 Aug. 2019





Admission for the event sponsored by the Friends of the Rancho Bernardo Library is free; freewill donations will be accepted for musicians.


Linda Mcintosh, sandiegouniontribune.com, 30 Apr. 2018





There is no charge for this concert; freewill donations for musicians are encouraged.


Linda Mcintosh, sandiegouniontribune.com, 9 Apr. 2018





The series’ third and final concert holds chamber works by French composers of Les Six. 4 p.m. Sunday, Southminster Presbyterian Church, 916 E. Central Road, Arlington Heights; freewill donation; 847-902-0733.


John Von Rhein, chicagotribune.com, 1 June 2017





Freewill offerings will benefit the Georgetown Ministry Center, which aids service-resistant, chronically homeless individuals and advocates for the homeless.


Gerri Marmer, Washington Post, 5 May 2017




Jebb also added that junk advertising may undermine people’s free will due to its influence.


Emma Ogao, ABC News, 18 Jan. 2023





The mantra gave animators a bit of free will in reimagining Carlo Collodi’s classic novel with brilliant detail without an overtly, flawless feeling — an impression that subliminally infuses Del Toro’s twisting narrative.


Daron James, Los Angeles Times, 2 Jan. 2023





Chestertonian notions of tradition, the importance of old-fashioned nuclear families, the notion of free will, the respect for life, the stigma and guilt that help mitigate bad personal behavior — and the forgiveness afforded those who fall — are all quite appealing concepts.


David Harsanyi, National Review, 2 Dec. 2021





Inspired by The Adventures of Pinocchio, this heartfelt saga offers a lively look at identity, free will and love.


Amy Brady, Scientific American, 14 Mar. 2023





Moreover, while the ancestors’ machinations are ingrained in Yoruba beliefs, the notion that Tara and her family could, of their own free will, find faith in themselves and each other is worth pondering.


David L. Coddoncontributor, San Diego Union-Tribune, 24 Feb. 2023





Auerbach’s new work emerged from no less heady a quandary than the existence of free will.


Julia Felsenthal, New York Times, 16 Mar. 2023





Kang wrestles against himself, forcing us to consider the struggle between free will and destiny.


Joe George, Men’s Health, 16 Feb. 2023





Unfortunately, our current responsibility practices, premised on the ideal of free will and retributive justice, does nothing to seriously address this trauma.


John Danaher, WIRED, 2 Feb. 2023



See More

These examples are programmatically compiled from various online sources to illustrate current usage of the word ‘freewill.’ Any opinions expressed in the examples do not represent those of Merriam-Webster or its editors. Send us feedback about these examples.

Понравилась статья? Поделить с друзьями:
  • The meaning of the word fox about a cunning person is
  • The meaning of the word associate
  • The meaning of the word force
  • The meaning of the word assistant
  • The meaning of the word follow up