Origin of the word reason

This article is about the human faculty of reason and rationality. For other uses, see Reason (disambiguation).

Reason is the capacity of consciously applying logic by drawing conclusions from new or existing information, with the aim of seeking the truth.[1][2] It is closely[how?] associated with such characteristically human activities as philosophy, science, language, mathematics, and art, and is normally considered to be a distinguishing ability possessed by humans.[3] Reason is sometimes referred to as rationality.[4]

Reasoning is associated with the acts of thinking and cognition, and involves the use of one’s intellect. The field of logic studies the ways in which humans can use formal reasoning to produce logically valid arguments.[5] Reasoning may be subdivided into forms of logical reasoning, such as deductive reasoning, inductive reasoning, and abductive reasoning. Aristotle drew a distinction between logical discursive reasoning (reason proper), and intuitive reasoning,[6] in which the reasoning process through intuition—however valid—may tend toward the personal and the subjectively opaque. In some social and political settings logical and intuitive modes of reasoning may clash, while in other contexts intuition and formal reason are seen as complementary rather than adversarial. For example, in mathematics, intuition is often necessary for the creative processes involved with arriving at a formal proof, arguably the most difficult of formal reasoning tasks.

Reasoning, like habit or intuition, is one of the ways by which thinking moves from one idea to a related idea. For example, reasoning is the means by which rational individuals understand sensory information from their environments, or conceptualize abstract dichotomies such as cause and effect, truth and falsehood, or ideas regarding notions of good or evil. Reasoning, as a part of executive decision making, is also closely identified with the ability to self-consciously change, in terms of goals, beliefs, attitudes, traditions, and institutions, and therefore with the capacity for freedom and self-determination.[7]

In contrast to the use of «reason» as an abstract noun, a reason is a consideration given which either explains or justifies events, phenomena, or behavior.[8] Reasons justify decisions, reasons support explanations of natural phenomena; reasons can be given to explain the actions (conduct) of individuals.

Using reason, or reasoning, can also be described more plainly as providing good, or the best, reasons. For example, when evaluating a moral decision, «morality is, at the very least, the effort to guide one’s conduct by reason—that is, doing what there are the best reasons for doing—while giving equal [and impartial] weight to the interests of all those affected by what one does.»[9]

Psychologists and cognitive scientists have attempted to study and explain how people reason, e.g. which cognitive and neural processes are engaged, and how cultural factors affect the inferences that people draw. The field of automated reasoning studies how reasoning may or may not be modeled computationally. Animal psychology considers the question of whether animals other than humans can reason.

Etymology and related words[edit]

In the English language and other modern European languages, «reason», and related words, represent words which have always been used to translate Latin and classical Greek terms in the sense of their philosophical usage.

  • The original Greek term was «λόγος» logos, the root of the modern English word «logic» but also a word which could mean for example «speech» or «explanation» or an «account» (of money handled).[10]
  • As a philosophical term logos was translated in its non-linguistic senses in Latin as ratio. This was originally not just a translation used for philosophy, but was also commonly a translation for logos in the sense of an account of money.[11]
  • French raison is derived directly from Latin, and this is the direct source of the English word «reason».[8]

The earliest major philosophers to publish in English, such as Francis Bacon, Thomas Hobbes, and John Locke also routinely wrote in Latin and French, and compared their terms to Greek, treating the words «logos«, «ratio«, «raison» and «reason» as interchangeable. The meaning of the word «reason» in senses such as «human reason» also overlaps to a large extent with «rationality» and the adjective of «reason» in philosophical contexts is normally «rational», rather than «reasoned» or «reasonable».[12] Some philosophers, Thomas Hobbes for example, also used the word ratiocination as a synonym for «reasoning».

Philosophical history[edit]

The proposal that reason gives humanity a special position in nature has been argued to be a defining characteristic of western philosophy and later western modern science, starting with classical Greece. Philosophy can be described as a way of life based upon reason, and in the other direction, reason has been one of the major subjects of philosophical discussion since ancient times. Reason is often said to be reflexive, or «self-correcting», and the critique of reason has been a persistent theme in philosophy.[13] It has been defined in different ways, at different times, by different thinkers about human nature.

Classical philosophy[edit]

For many classical philosophers, nature was understood teleologically, meaning that every type of thing had a definitive purpose that fit within a natural order that was itself understood to have aims. Perhaps starting with Pythagoras or Heraclitus, the cosmos is even said to have reason.[14] Reason, by this account, is not just one characteristic that humans happen to have, and that influences happiness amongst other characteristics. Reason was considered of higher stature than other characteristics of human nature, such as sociability, because it is something humans share with nature itself, linking an apparently immortal part of the human mind with the divine order of the cosmos itself. Within the human mind or soul (psyche), reason was described by Plato as being the natural monarch which should rule over the other parts, such as spiritedness (thumos) and the passions. Aristotle, Plato’s student, defined human beings as rational animals, emphasizing reason as a characteristic of human nature. He defined the highest human happiness or well being (eudaimonia) as a life which is lived consistently, excellently, and completely in accordance with reason.[15]

The conclusions to be drawn from the discussions of Aristotle and Plato on this matter are amongst the most debated in the history of philosophy.[16] But teleological accounts such as Aristotle’s were highly influential for those who attempt to explain reason in a way that is consistent with monotheism and the immortality and divinity of the human soul. For example, in the neoplatonist account of Plotinus, the cosmos has one soul, which is the seat of all reason, and the souls of all individual humans are part of this soul. Reason is for Plotinus both the provider of form to material things, and the light which brings individuals souls back into line with their source.[17]

Christian and Islamic philosophy[edit]

The classical view of reason, like many important Neoplatonic and Stoic ideas, was readily adopted by the early Church [18] as the Church Fathers saw Greek Philosophy as an indispensable instrument given to mankind so that we may understand revelation.[19] For example, the greatest among the early saint Church Fathers and Doctors of the Church such as Augustine of Hippo, Basil of Caesarea and Gregory of Nyssa were as much Neoplatonic philosophers as they were Christian theologians and adopted the Neoplatonic view of human reason together with the associated implications for our relationship to creation, to ourselves and to God. Such Neoplatonist accounts of the rational part of the human soul were also standard amongst medieval Islamic philosophers and remain important in Iranian philosophy.[16] As European intellectualism recovered from the post-Roman Dark Ages, the Christian Patristic heritage and the influence of the great Islamic scholars such as Averroes and Avicenna produced the Scholastic (see Scholasticism) view of reason from which our modern idea of this concept has developed.[20] Among the Scholastics who relied on the classical concept of reason for the development of their doctrines, none were more influential than Saint Thomas Aquinas, who put this concept at the heart of his Natural Law. In this doctrine, Thomas concludes that because humans have reason and because reason is a spark of the divine, every single human life is invaluable, all humans are equal and every human is born with an intrinsic and permanent set of basic rights.[21] On this foundation, the idea of human rights would later be constructed by Spanish theologians at the School of Salamanca. Other Scholastics, such as Roger Bacon and Albertus Magnus, following the example of Islamic scholars such as Alhazen, emphasised reason an intrinsic human ability to decode the created order and the structures that underlie our experienced physical reality. This interpretation of reason was instrumental to the development of the scientific method in the early Universities of the high Middle Ages.[22]

Subject-centred reason in early modern philosophy[edit]

The early modern era was marked by a number of significant changes in the understanding of reason, starting in Europe. One of the most important of these changes involved a change in the metaphysical understanding of human beings. Scientists and philosophers began to question the teleological understanding of the world.[23] Nature was no longer assumed to be human-like, with its own aims or reason, and human nature was no longer assumed to work according to anything other than the same «laws of nature» which affect inanimate things. This new understanding eventually displaced the previous world view that derived from a spiritual understanding of the universe.

Accordingly, in the 17th century, René Descartes explicitly rejected the traditional notion of humans as «rational animals», suggesting instead that they are nothing more than «thinking things» along the lines of other «things» in nature. Any grounds of knowledge outside that understanding was, therefore, subject to doubt.

In his search for a foundation of all possible knowledge, Descartes deliberately decided to throw into doubt all knowledge – except that of the mind itself in the process of thinking:

At this time I admit nothing that is not necessarily true. I am therefore precisely nothing but a thinking thing; that is a mind, or intellect, or understanding, or reason – words of whose meanings I was previously ignorant.[24]

This eventually became known as epistemological or «subject-centred» reason, because it is based on the knowing subject, who perceives the rest of the world and itself as a set of objects to be studied, and successfully mastered by applying the knowledge accumulated through such study. Breaking with tradition and many thinkers after him, Descartes explicitly did not divide the incorporeal soul into parts, such as reason and intellect, describing them as one indivisible incorporeal entity.

A contemporary of Descartes, Thomas Hobbes described reason as a broader version of «addition and subtraction» which is not limited to numbers.[25] This understanding of reason is sometimes termed «calculative» reason. Similar to Descartes, Hobbes asserted that «No discourse whatsoever, can end in absolute knowledge of fact, past, or to come» but that «sense and memory» is absolute knowledge.[26]

In the late 17th century, through the 18th century, John Locke and David Hume developed Descartes’s line of thought still further. Hume took it in an especially skeptical direction, proposing that there could be no possibility of deducing relationships of cause and effect, and therefore no knowledge is based on reasoning alone, even if it seems otherwise.[27][28]

Hume famously remarked that, «We speak not strictly and philosophically when we talk of the combat of passion and of reason. Reason is, and ought only to be the slave of the passions, and can never pretend to any other office than to serve and obey them.»[29] Hume also took his definition of reason to unorthodox extremes by arguing, unlike his predecessors, that human reason is not qualitatively different from either simply conceiving individual ideas, or from judgments associating two ideas,[30] and that «reason is nothing but a wonderful and unintelligible instinct in our souls, which carries us along a certain train of ideas, and endows them with particular qualities, according to their particular situations and relations.»[31] It followed from this that animals have reason, only much less complex than human reason.

In the 18th century, Immanuel Kant attempted to show that Hume was wrong by demonstrating that a «transcendental» self, or «I», was a necessary condition of all experience. Therefore, suggested Kant, on the basis of such a self, it is in fact possible to reason both about the conditions and limits of human knowledge. And so long as these limits are respected, reason can be the vehicle of morality, justice, aesthetics, theories of knowledge (epistemology), and understanding.

Substantive and formal reason[edit]

In the formulation of Kant, who wrote some of the most influential modern treatises on the subject, the great achievement of reason (German: Vernunft) is that it is able to exercise a kind of universal law-making. Kant was able therefore to reformulate the basis of moral-practical, theoretical and aesthetic reasoning, on «universal» laws.

Here practical reasoning is the self-legislating or self-governing formulation of universal norms, and theoretical reasoning the way humans posit universal laws of nature.[32]

Under practical reason, the moral autonomy or freedom of human beings depends on their ability to behave according to laws that are given to them by the proper exercise of that reason. This contrasted with earlier forms of morality, which depended on religious understanding and interpretation, or nature for their substance.[33]

According to Kant, in a free society each individual must be able to pursue their goals however they see fit, so long as their actions conform to principles given by reason. He formulated such a principle, called the «categorical imperative», which would justify an action only if it could be universalized:

Act only according to that maxim whereby you can, at the same time, will that it should become a universal law.[34]

In contrast to Hume then, Kant insists that reason itself (German Vernunft) has natural ends, the solution to the metaphysical problems, especially the discovery of the foundations of morality. Kant claimed that this problem could be solved with his «transcendental logic» which unlike normal logic is not just an instrument, which can be used indifferently, as it was for Aristotle, but a theoretical science in its own right and the basis of all the others.[35]

According to Jürgen Habermas, the «substantive unity» of reason has dissolved in modern times, such that it can no longer answer the question «How should I live?» Instead, the unity of reason has to be strictly formal, or «procedural». He thus described reason as a group of three autonomous spheres (on the model of Kant’s three critiques):

  1. Cognitive–instrumental reason is the kind of reason employed by the sciences. It is used to observe events, to predict and control outcomes, and to intervene in the world on the basis of its hypotheses;
  2. Moral–practical reason is what we use to deliberate and discuss issues in the moral and political realm, according to universalizable procedures (similar to Kant’s categorical imperative); and
  3. Aesthetic reason is typically found in works of art and literature, and encompasses the novel ways of seeing the world and interpreting things that those practices embody.

For Habermas, these three spheres are the domain of experts, and therefore need to be mediated with the «lifeworld» by philosophers. In drawing such a picture of reason, Habermas hoped to demonstrate that the substantive unity of reason, which in pre-modern societies had been able to answer questions about the good life, could be made up for by the unity of reason’s formalizable procedures.[36]

The critique of reason[edit]

Hamann, Herder, Kant, Hegel, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, Heidegger, Foucault, Rorty, and many other philosophers have contributed to a debate about what reason means, or ought to mean. Some, like Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, and Rorty, are skeptical about subject-centred, universal, or instrumental reason, and even skeptical toward reason as a whole. Others, including Hegel, believe that it has obscured the importance of intersubjectivity, or «spirit» in human life, and attempt to reconstruct a model of what reason should be.

Some thinkers, e.g. Foucault, believe there are other forms of reason, neglected but essential to modern life, and to our understanding of what it means to live a life according to reason.[13]

In the last several decades, a number of proposals have been made to «re-orient» this critique of reason, or to recognize the «other voices» or «new departments» of reason:

For example, in opposition to subject-centred reason, Habermas has proposed a model of communicative reason that sees it as an essentially cooperative activity, based on the fact of linguistic intersubjectivity.[37]

Nikolas Kompridis has proposed a widely encompassing view of reason as «that ensemble of practices that contributes to the opening and preserving of openness» in human affairs, and a focus on reason’s possibilities for social change.[38]

The philosopher Charles Taylor, influenced by the 20th century German philosopher Martin Heidegger, has proposed that reason ought to include the faculty of disclosure, which is tied to the way we make sense of things in everyday life, as a new «department» of reason.[39]

In the essay «What is Enlightenment?», Michel Foucault proposed a concept of critique based on Kant’s distinction between «private» and «public» uses of reason. This distinction, as suggested, has two dimensions:

  • Private reason is the reason that is used when an individual is «a cog in a machine» or when one «has a role to play in society and jobs to do: to be a soldier, to have taxes to pay, to be in charge of a parish, to be a civil servant».
  • Public reason is the reason used «when one is reasoning as a reasonable being (and not as a cog in a machine), when one is reasoning as a member of reasonable humanity». In these circumstances, «the use of reason must be free and public.»[40]

[edit]

Compared to logic[edit]

The terms logic or logical are sometimes used as if they were identical with the term reason or with the concept of being rational, or sometimes logic is seen as the most pure or the defining form of reason: «Logic is about reasoning—about going from premises to a conclusion. … When you do logic, you try to clarify reasoning and separate good from bad reasoning.»[41] In modern economics, rational choice is assumed to equate to logically consistent choice.[42]

Reason and logic can however be thought of as distinct, although logic is one important aspect of reason. Author Douglas Hofstadter, in Gödel, Escher, Bach, characterizes the distinction in this way: Logic is done inside a system while reason is done outside the system by such methods as skipping steps, working backward, drawing diagrams, looking at examples, or seeing what happens if you change the rules of the system.[43] Psychologists Mark H. Bickard and Robert L. Campbell argued that «rationality cannot be simply assimilated to logicality»; they noted that «human knowledge of logic and logical systems has developed» over time through reasoning, and logical systems «can’t construct new logical systems more powerful than themselves», so reasoning and rationality must involve more than a system of logic.[44][45] Psychologist David Moshman, citing Bickhard and Campbell, argued for a «metacognitive conception of rationality» in which a person’s development of reason «involves increasing consciousness and control of logical and other inferences».[45][46]

Reason is a type of thought, and logic involves the attempt to describe a system of formal rules or norms of appropriate reasoning.[45] The oldest surviving writing to explicitly consider the rules by which reason operates are the works of the Greek philosopher Aristotle, especially Prior Analysis and Posterior Analysis.[47][non-primary source needed] Although the Ancient Greeks had no separate word for logic as distinct from language and reason, Aristotle’s newly coined word «syllogism» (syllogismos) identified logic clearly for the first time as a distinct field of study.[48] When Aristotle referred to «the logical» (hē logikē), he was referring more broadly to rational thought.[49]

Reason compared to cause-and-effect thinking, and symbolic thinking[edit]

As pointed out by philosophers such as Hobbes, Locke and Hume, some animals are also clearly capable of a type of «associative thinking», even to the extent of associating causes and effects. A dog once kicked, can learn how to recognize the warning signs and avoid being kicked in the future, but this does not mean the dog has reason in any strict sense of the word. It also does not mean that humans acting on the basis of experience or habit are using their reason.[50]

Human reason requires more than being able to associate two ideas, even if those two ideas might be described by a reasoning human as a cause and an effect, perceptions of smoke, for example, and memories of fire. For reason to be involved, the association of smoke and the fire would have to be thought through in a way which can be explained, for example as cause and effect. In the explanation of Locke, for example, reason requires the mental use of a third idea in order to make this comparison by use of syllogism.[51]

More generally, reason in the strict sense requires the ability to create and manipulate a system of symbols, as well as indices and icons, according to Charles Sanders Peirce, the symbols having only a nominal, though habitual, connection to either smoke or fire.[52] One example of such a system of artificial symbols and signs is language.

The connection of reason to symbolic thinking has been expressed in different ways by philosophers. Thomas Hobbes described the creation of «Markes, or Notes of remembrance» (Leviathan Ch. 4) as speech. He used the word speech as an English version of the Greek word logos so that speech did not need to be communicated.[53] When communicated, such speech becomes language, and the marks or notes or remembrance are called «Signes» by Hobbes. Going further back, although Aristotle is a source of the idea that only humans have reason (logos), he does mention that animals with imagination, for whom sense perceptions can persist, come closest to having something like reasoning and nous, and even uses the word «logos» in one place to describe the distinctions which animals can perceive in such cases.[54]

Reason, imagination, mimesis, and memory[edit]

Reason and imagination rely on similar mental processes.[55] Imagination is not only found in humans. Aristotle, for example, stated that phantasia (imagination: that which can hold images or phantasmata) and phronein (a type of thinking that can judge and understand in some sense) also exist in some animals.[56] According to him, both are related to the primary perceptive ability of animals, which gathers the perceptions of different senses and defines the order of the things that are perceived without distinguishing universals, and without deliberation or logos. But this is not yet reason, because human imagination is different.

The recent modern writings of Terrence Deacon and Merlin Donald, writing about the origin of language, also connect reason connected to not only language, but also mimesis.[57] More specifically they describe the ability to create language as part of an internal modeling of reality specific to humankind. Other results are consciousness, and imagination or fantasy. In contrast, modern proponents of a genetic predisposition to language itself include Noam Chomsky and Steven Pinker, to whom Donald and Deacon can be contrasted.

As reason is symbolic thinking, and peculiarly human, then this implies that humans have a special ability to maintain a clear consciousness of the distinctness of «icons» or images and the real things they represent. Starting with a modern author, Merlin Donald writes[58]

A dog might perceive the «meaning» of a fight that was realistically play-acted by humans, but it could not reconstruct the message or distinguish the representation from its referent (a real fight). […] Trained apes are able to make this distinction; young children make this distinction early – hence, their effortless distinction between play-acting an event and the event itself

In classical descriptions, an equivalent description of this mental faculty is eikasia, in the philosophy of Plato.[59] This is the ability to perceive whether a perception is an image of something else, related somehow but not the same, and therefore allows humans to perceive that a dream or memory or a reflection in a mirror is not reality as such. What Klein refers to as dianoetic eikasia is the eikasia concerned specifically with thinking and mental images, such as those mental symbols, icons, signes, and marks discussed above as definitive of reason. Explaining reason from this direction: human thinking is special in the way that we often understand visible things as if they were themselves images of our intelligible «objects of thought» as «foundations» (hypothēses in Ancient Greek). This thinking (dianoia) is «…an activity which consists in making the vast and diffuse jungle of the visible world depend on a plurality of more ‘precise’ noēta«.[60]

Both Merlin Donald and the Socratic authors such as Plato and Aristotle emphasize the importance of mimesis, often translated as imitation or representation. Donald writes[61]

Imitation is found especially in monkeys and apes [… but …] Mimesis is fundamentally different from imitation and mimicry in that it involves the invention of intentional representations. […] Mimesis is not absolutely tied to external communication.

Mimēsis is a concept, now popular again in academic discussion, that was particularly prevalent in Plato’s works, and within Aristotle, it is discussed mainly in the Poetics. In Michael Davis’s account of the theory of man in this work.[62]

It is the distinctive feature of human action, that whenever we choose what we do, we imagine an action for ourselves as though we were inspecting it from the outside. Intentions are nothing more than imagined actions, internalizings of the external. All action is therefore imitation of action; it is poetic…[63]

Donald like Plato (and Aristotle, especially in On Memory and Recollection), emphasizes the peculiarity in humans of voluntary initiation of a search through one’s mental world. The ancient Greek anamnēsis, normally translated as «recollection» was opposed to mneme or memory. Memory, shared with some animals,[64] requires a consciousness not only of what happened in the past, but also that something happened in the past, which is in other words a kind of eikasia[65] «…but nothing except man is able to recollect.»[66] Recollection is a deliberate effort to search for and recapture something once known. Klein writes that, «To become aware of our having forgotten something means to begin recollecting.»[67] Donald calls the same thing autocueing, which he explains as follows:[68] «Mimetic acts are reproducible on the basis of internal, self-generated cues. This permits voluntary recall of mimetic representations, without the aid of external cues – probably the earliest form of representational thinking

In a celebrated paper in modern times, the fantasy author and philologist J.R.R. Tolkien wrote in his essay «On Fairy Stories» that the terms «fantasy» and «enchantment» are connected to not only «….the satisfaction of certain primordial human desires….» but also «…the origin of language and of the mind».

Logical reasoning methods and argumentation[edit]

A subdivision of philosophy is logic. Logic is the study of reasoning. Looking at logical categorizations of different types of reasoning, the traditional main division made in philosophy is between deductive reasoning and inductive reasoning. Formal logic has been described as the science of deduction.[69] The study of inductive reasoning is generally carried out within the field known as informal logic or critical thinking.

Deductive reasoning[edit]

Deduction is a form of reasoning in which a conclusion follows necessarily from the stated premises. A deduction is also the conclusion reached by a deductive reasoning process. One classic example of deductive reasoning is that found in syllogisms like the following:

  • Premise 1: All humans are mortal.
  • Premise 2: Socrates is a human.
  • Conclusion: Socrates is mortal.

The reasoning in this argument is deductively valid because there is no way in which the premises, 1 and 2, could be true and the conclusion, 3, be false.

Inductive reasoning[edit]

Induction is a form of inference producing propositions about unobserved objects or types, either specifically or generally, based on previous observation. It is used to ascribe properties or relations to objects or types based on previous observations or experiences, or to formulate general statements or laws based on limited observations of recurring phenomenal patterns.

Inductive reasoning contrasts strongly with deductive reasoning in that, even in the best, or strongest, cases of inductive reasoning, the truth of the premises does not guarantee the truth of the conclusion. Instead, the conclusion of an inductive argument follows with some degree of probability. Relatedly, the conclusion of an inductive argument contains more information than is already contained in the premises. Thus, this method of reasoning is ampliative.

A classic example of inductive reasoning comes from the empiricist David Hume:

  • Premise: The sun has risen in the east every morning up until now.
  • Conclusion: The sun will also rise in the east tomorrow.

Analogical reasoning[edit]

Analogical reasoning is a form of inductive reasoning from a particular to a particular. It is often used in case-based reasoning, especially legal reasoning.[70] An example follows:

  • Premise 1: Socrates is human and mortal.
  • Premise 2: Plato is human.
  • Conclusion: Plato is mortal.

Analogical reasoning is a weaker form of inductive reasoning from a single example, because inductive reasoning typically uses a large number of examples to reason from the particular to the general.[71] Analogical reasoning often leads to wrong conclusions. For example:

  • Premise 1: Socrates is human and male.
  • Premise 2: Ada Lovelace is human.
  • Conclusion: Ada Lovelace is male.

Abductive reasoning[edit]

Abductive reasoning, or argument to the best explanation, is a form of reasoning that doesn’t fit in deductive or inductive, since it starts with incomplete set of observations and proceeds with likely possible explanations so the conclusion in an abductive argument does not follow with certainty from its premises and concerns something unobserved. What distinguishes abduction from the other forms of reasoning is an attempt to favour one conclusion above others, by subjective judgement or attempting to falsify alternative explanations or by demonstrating the likelihood of the favoured conclusion, given a set of more or less disputable assumptions. For example, when a patient displays certain symptoms, there might be various possible causes, but one of these is preferred above others as being more probable.

Fallacious reasoning[edit]

Flawed reasoning in arguments is known as fallacious reasoning. Bad reasoning within arguments can be because it commits either a formal fallacy or an informal fallacy.

Formal fallacies occur when there is a problem with the form, or structure, of the argument. The word «formal» refers to this link to the form of the argument. An argument that contains a formal fallacy will always be invalid.

An informal fallacy is an error in reasoning that occurs due to a problem with the content, rather than mere structure, of the argument.

Traditional problems raised concerning reason[edit]

Philosophy is sometimes described as a life of reason, with normal human reason pursued in a more consistent and dedicated way than usual. Two categories of problem concerning reason have long been discussed by philosophers concerning reason, essentially being reasonings about reasoning itself as a human aim, or philosophizing about philosophizing. The first question is concerning whether we can be confident that reason can achieve knowledge of truth better than other ways of trying to achieve such knowledge. The other question is whether a life of reason, a life that aims to be guided by reason, can be expected to achieve a happy life more so than other ways of life (whether such a life of reason results in knowledge or not).

Reason versus truth, and «first principles»[edit]

Since classical times a question has remained constant in philosophical debate (which is sometimes seen as a conflict between movements called Platonism and Aristotelianism) concerning the role of reason in confirming truth. People use logic, deduction, and induction, to reach conclusions they think are true. Conclusions reached in this way are considered, according to Aristotle, more certain than sense perceptions on their own.[72] On the other hand, if such reasoned conclusions are only built originally upon a foundation of sense perceptions, then, our most logical conclusions can never be said to be certain because they are built upon the very same fallible perceptions they seek to better.[73]

This leads to the question of what types of first principles, or starting points of reasoning, are available for someone seeking to come to true conclusions. In Greek, «first principles» are archai, «starting points»,[74] and the faculty used to perceive them is sometimes referred to in Aristotle[75] and Plato[76] as nous which was close in meaning to awareness or consciousness.[77]

Empiricism (sometimes associated with Aristotle[78] but more correctly associated with British philosophers such as John Locke and David Hume, as well as their ancient equivalents such as Democritus) asserts that sensory impressions are the only available starting points for reasoning and attempting to attain truth. This approach always leads to the controversial conclusion that absolute knowledge is not attainable. Idealism, (associated with Plato and his school), claims that there is a «higher» reality, from which certain people can directly arrive at truth without needing to rely only upon the senses, and that this higher reality is therefore the primary source of truth.

Philosophers such as Plato, Aristotle, Al-Farabi, Avicenna, Averroes, Maimonides, Aquinas and Hegel are sometimes said to have argued that reason must be fixed and discoverable—perhaps by dialectic, analysis, or study. In the vision of these thinkers, reason is divine or at least has divine attributes. Such an approach allowed religious philosophers such as Thomas Aquinas and Étienne Gilson to try to show that reason and revelation are compatible. According to Hegel, «…the only thought which Philosophy brings with it to the contemplation of History, is the simple conception of reason; that reason is the Sovereign of the World; that the history of the world, therefore, presents us with a rational process.»[79]

Since the 17th century rationalists, reason has often been taken to be a subjective faculty, or rather the unaided ability (pure reason) to form concepts. For Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz, this was associated with mathematics. Kant attempted to show that pure reason could form concepts (time and space) that are the conditions of experience. Kant made his argument in opposition to Hume, who denied that reason had any role to play in experience.

Reason versus emotion or passion[edit]

After Plato and Aristotle, western literature often treated reason as being the faculty that trained the passions and appetites.[citation needed] Stoic philosophy, by contrast, claimed most emotions were merely false judgements.[80][81] According to the stoics the only good is virtue, and the only evil is vice, therefore emotions that judged things other than vice to be bad (such as fear or distress), or things other than virtue to be good (such as greed) were simply false judgements and should be discarded (though positive emotions based on true judgements, such as kindness, were acceptable).[80][81][82] After the critiques of reason in the early Enlightenment the appetites were rarely discussed or conflated with the passions.[citation needed] Some Enlightenment camps took after the Stoics to say Reason should oppose Passion rather than order it, while others like the Romantics believed that Passion displaces Reason, as in the maxim «follow your heart».[citation needed]

Reason has been seen as cold, an «enemy of mystery and ambiguity»,[83] a slave, or judge, of the passions, notably in the work of David Hume, and more recently of Freud.[citation needed] Reasoning which claims that the object of a desire is demanded by logic alone is called rationalization.[citation needed]

Rousseau first proposed, in his second Discourse, that reason and political life is not natural and possibly harmful to mankind.[84] He asked what really can be said about what is natural to mankind. What, other than reason and civil society, «best suits his constitution»? Rousseau saw «two principles prior to reason» in human nature. First we hold an intense interest in our own well-being. Secondly we object to the suffering or death of any sentient being, especially one like ourselves.[85] These two passions lead us to desire more than we could achieve. We become dependent upon each other, and on relationships of authority and obedience. This effectively puts the human race into slavery. Rousseau says that he almost dares to assert that nature does not destine men to be healthy. According to Richard Velkley, «Rousseau outlines certain programs of rational self-correction, most notably the political legislation of the Contrat Social and the moral education in Émile. All the same, Rousseau understands such corrections to be only ameliorations of an essentially unsatisfactory condition, that of socially and intellectually corrupted humanity.»

This quandary presented by Rousseau led to Kant’s new way of justifying reason as freedom to create good and evil. These therefore are not to be blamed on nature or God. In various ways, German Idealism after Kant, and major later figures such Nietzsche, Bergson, Husserl, Scheler, and Heidegger, remain preoccupied with problems coming from the metaphysical demands or urges of reason.[86] The influence of Rousseau and these later writers is also large upon art and politics. Many writers (such as Nikos Kazantzakis) extol passion and disparage reason. In politics modern nationalism comes from Rousseau’s argument that rationalist cosmopolitanism brings man ever further from his natural state.[87]

Another view on reason and emotion was proposed in the 1994 book titled Descartes’ Error by Antonio Damasio. In it, Damasio presents the «Somatic Marker Hypothesis» which states that emotions guide behavior and decision-making. Damasio argues that these somatic markers (known collectively as «gut feelings») are «intuitive signals» that direct our decision making processes in a certain way that cannot be solved with rationality alone. Damasio further argues that rationality requires emotional input in order to function.

Reason versus faith or tradition[edit]

There are many religious traditions, some of which are explicitly fideist and others of which claim varying degrees of rationalism. Secular critics sometimes accuse all religious adherents of irrationality, since they claim such adherents are guilty of ignoring, suppressing, or forbidding some kinds of reasoning concerning some subjects (such as religious dogmas, moral taboos, etc.).[88] Though the theologies and religions such as classical monotheism typically do not admit to be irrational, there is often a perceived conflict or tension between faith and tradition on the one hand, and reason on the other, as potentially competing sources of wisdom, law and truth.[89][90]

Religious adherents sometimes respond by arguing that faith and reason can be reconciled, or have different non-overlapping domains, or that critics engage in a similar kind of irrationalism:

  • Reconciliation: Philosopher Alvin Plantinga argues that there is no real conflict between reason and classical theism because classical theism explains (among other things) why the universe is intelligible and why reason can successfully grasp it.[91][92]
  • Non-overlapping magisteria: Evolutionary biologist Stephen Jay Gould argues that there need not be conflict between reason and religious belief because they are each authoritative in their own domain (or «magisterium»).[93][94] If so, reason can work on those problems over which it has authority while other sources of knowledge or opinion can have authority on the big questions.[95]
  • Tu quoque: Philosophers Alasdair MacIntyre and Charles Taylor argue that those critics of traditional religion who are adherents of secular liberalism are also sometimes guilty of ignoring, suppressing, and forbidding some kinds of reasoning about subjects.[96][97] Similarly, philosophers of science such as Paul Feyarabend argue that scientists sometimes ignore or suppress evidence contrary to the dominant paradigm.
  • Unification: Theologian Joseph Ratzinger, later Benedict XVI, asserted that «Christianity has understood itself as the religion of the Logos, as the religion according to reason,» referring to John 1:Ἐν ἀρχῇ ἦν ὁ λόγος, usually translated as «In the beginning was the Word (Logos).» Thus, he said that the Christian faith is «open to all that is truly rational», and that the rationality of Western Enlightenment «is of Christian origin».[98]

Some commentators have claimed that Western civilization can be almost defined by its serious testing of the limits of tension between «unaided» reason and faith in «revealed» truths—figuratively summarized as Athens and Jerusalem, respectively.[99][100] Leo Strauss spoke of a «Greater West» that included all areas under the influence of the tension between Greek rationalism and Abrahamic revelation, including the Muslim lands. He was particularly influenced by the great Muslim philosopher Al-Farabi. To consider to what extent Eastern philosophy might have partaken of these important tensions, Strauss thought it best to consider whether dharma or tao may be equivalent to Nature (by which we mean physis in Greek). According to Strauss the beginning of philosophy involved the «discovery or invention of nature» and the «pre-philosophical equivalent of nature» was supplied by «such notions as ‘custom’ or ‘ways«, which appear to be really universal in all times and places. The philosophical concept of nature or natures as a way of understanding archai (first principles of knowledge) brought about a peculiar tension between reasoning on the one hand, and tradition or faith on the other.[101]

Although there is this special history of debate concerning reason and faith in the Islamic, Christian and Jewish traditions, the pursuit of reason is sometimes argued to be compatible with the other practice of other religions of a different nature, such as Hinduism, because they do not define their tenets in such an absolute way.[102]

Reason in particular fields of study[edit]

Psychology and cognitive science[edit]

Scientific research into reasoning is carried out within the fields of psychology and cognitive science. Psychologists attempt to determine whether or not people are capable of rational thought in a number of different circumstances.

Assessing how well someone engages in reasoning is the project of determining the extent to which the person is rational or acts rationally. It is a key research question in the psychology of reasoning and cognitive science of reasoning. Rationality is often divided into its respective theoretical and practical counterparts.

Behavioral experiments on human reasoning[edit]

Experimental cognitive psychologists carry out research on reasoning behaviour. Such research may focus, for example, on how people perform on tests of reasoning such as intelligence or IQ tests, or on how well people’s reasoning matches ideals set by logic (see, for example, the Wason test).[103] Experiments examine how people make inferences from conditionals e.g., If A then B and how they make inferences about alternatives, e.g., A or else B.[104] They test whether people can make valid deductions about spatial and temporal relations, e.g., A is to the left of B, or A happens after B, and about quantified assertions, e.g., All the A are B.[105] Experiments investigate how people make inferences about factual situations, hypothetical possibilities, probabilities, and counterfactual situations.[106]

Developmental studies of children’s reasoning[edit]

Developmental psychologists investigate the development of reasoning from birth to adulthood. Piaget’s theory of cognitive development was the first complete theory of reasoning development. Subsequently, several alternative theories were proposed, including the neo-Piagetian theories of cognitive development.[107]

Neuroscience of reasoning[edit]

The biological functioning of the brain is studied by neurophysiologists, cognitive neuroscientists and neuropsychologists. Research in this area includes research into the structure and function of normally functioning brains, and of damaged or otherwise unusual brains. In addition to carrying out research into reasoning, some psychologists, for example, clinical psychologists and psychotherapists work to alter people’s reasoning habits when they are unhelpful.

Computer science[edit]

Automated reasoning[edit]

In artificial intelligence and computer science, scientists study and use automated reasoning for diverse applications including automated theorem proving the formal semantics of programming languages, and formal specification in software engineering.

Meta-reasoning[edit]

Meta-reasoning is reasoning about reasoning. In computer science, a system performs meta-reasoning when it is reasoning about its own operation.[108] This requires a programming language capable of reflection, the ability to observe and modify its own structure and behaviour.

Evolution of reason[edit]

[icon]

This section needs expansion. You can help by adding to it. (August 2017)

Dan Sperber believes that reasoning in groups is more effective and promotes their evolutionary fitness.

A species could benefit greatly from better abilities to reason about, predict and understand the world. French social and cognitive scientists Dan Sperber and Hugo Mercier argue that there could have been other forces driving the evolution of reason. They point out that reasoning is very difficult for humans to do effectively, and that it is hard for individuals to doubt their own beliefs (confirmation bias). Reasoning is most effective when it is done as a collective – as demonstrated by the success of projects like science. They suggest that there are not just individual, but group selection pressures at play. Any group that managed to find ways of reasoning effectively would reap benefits for all its members, increasing their fitness. This could also help explain why humans, according to Sperber, are not optimized to reason effectively alone. Their argumentative theory of reasoning claims that reason may have more to do with winning arguments than with the search for the truth.[109][110]

Reason in political philosophy and ethics[edit]

Aristotle famously described reason (with language) as a part of human nature, which means that it is best for humans to live «politically» meaning in communities of about the size and type of a small city state (polis in Greek). For example…

It is clear, then, that a human being is more of a political [politikon = of the polis] animal [zōion] than is any bee or than any of those animals that live in herds. For nature, as we say, makes nothing in vain, and humans are the only animals who possess reasoned speech [logos]. Voice, of course, serves to indicate what is painful and pleasant; that is why it is also found in other animals, because their nature has reached the point where they can perceive what is painful and pleasant and express these to each other. But speech [logos] serves to make plain what is advantageous and harmful and so also what is just and unjust. For it is a peculiarity of humans, in contrast to the other animals, to have perception of good and bad, just and unjust, and the like; and the community in these things makes a household or city [polis]. […] By nature, then, the drive for such a community exists in everyone, but the first to set one up is responsible for things of very great goodness. For as humans are the best of all animals when perfected, so they are the worst when divorced from law and right. The reason is that injustice is most difficult to deal with when furnished with weapons, and the weapons a human being has are meant by nature to go along with prudence and virtue, but it is only too possible to turn them to contrary uses. Consequently, if a human being lacks virtue, he is the most unholy and savage thing, and when it comes to sex and food, the worst. But justice is something political [to do with the polis], for right is the arrangement of the political community, and right is discrimination of what is just. (Aristotle’s Politics 1253a 1.2. Peter Simpson’s translation, with Greek terms inserted in square brackets.)

The concept of human nature being fixed in this way, implied, in other words, that we can define what type of community is always best for people. This argument has remained a central argument in all political, ethical and moral thinking since then, and has become especially controversial since firstly Rousseau’s Second Discourse, and secondly, the Theory of Evolution. Already in Aristotle there was an awareness that the polis had not always existed and had needed to be invented or developed by humans themselves. The household came first, and the first villages and cities were just extensions of that, with the first cities being run as if they were still families with Kings acting like fathers.[111]

Friendship [philia] seems to prevail [in] man and woman according to nature [kata phusin]; for people are by nature [tēi phusei] pairing [sunduastikon] more than political [politikon = of the polis], in as much as the household [oikos] is prior [proteron = earlier] and more necessary than the polis and making children is more common [koinoteron] with the animals. In the other animals, community [koinōnia] goes no further than this, but people live together [sumoikousin] not only for the sake of making children, but also for the things for life; for from the start the functions [erga] are divided, and are different [for] man and woman. Thus they supply each other, putting their own into the common [eis to koinon]. It is for these [reasons] that both utility [chrēsimon] and pleasure [hēdu] seem to be found in this kind of friendship. (Nicomachean Ethics, VIII.12.1162a. Rough literal translation with Greek terms shown in square brackets.)

Rousseau in his Second Discourse finally took the shocking step of claiming that this traditional account has things in reverse: with reason, language and rationally organized communities all having developed over a long period of time merely as a result of the fact that some habits of cooperation were found to solve certain types of problems, and that once such cooperation became more important, it forced people to develop increasingly complex cooperation—often only to defend themselves from each other.

In other words, according to Rousseau, reason, language and rational community did not arise because of any conscious decision or plan by humans or gods, nor because of any pre-existing human nature. As a result, he claimed, living together in rationally organized communities like modern humans is a development with many negative aspects compared to the original state of man as an ape. If anything is specifically human in this theory, it is the flexibility and adaptability of humans. This view of the animal origins of distinctive human characteristics later received support from Charles Darwin’s Theory of Evolution.

The two competing theories concerning the origins of reason are relevant to political and ethical thought because, according to the Aristotelian theory, a best way of living together exists independently of historical circumstances. According to Rousseau, we should even doubt that reason, language and politics are a good thing, as opposed to being simply the best option given the particular course of events that lead to today. Rousseau’s theory, that human nature is malleable rather than fixed, is often taken to imply, for example by Karl Marx, a wider range of possible ways of living together than traditionally known.

However, while Rousseau’s initial impact encouraged bloody revolutions against traditional politics, including both the French Revolution and the Russian Revolution, his own conclusions about the best forms of community seem to have been remarkably classical, in favor of city-states such as Geneva, and rural living.

See also[edit]

  • Argument
  • Argumentation theory
  • Confirmation bias
  • Conformity
  • Critical thinking
  • Logic and rationality
  • Outline of thought – topic tree that identifies many types of thoughts/thinking, types of reasoning, aspects of thought, related fields, and more.
  • Outline of human intelligence – topic tree presenting the traits, capacities, models, and research fields of human intelligence, and more.
  • Common sense

References[edit]

  1. ^ Proudfoot, Michael (2010). The Routledge dictionary of philosophy. A. R. Lacey, A. R.. Lacey (4th ed.). London: Routledge. p. 341. ISBN 978-0-203-42846-7. OCLC 503050369. Reason: A general faculty common to all or nearly all humans…this faculty has seemed to be of two sorts, a faculty of intuition by which one ‘sees’ truths or abstract things (‘essences’ or universals, etc.), and a faculty of reasoning, i.e. passing from premises to a conclusion (discursive reason). The verb ‘reason is confined to this latter sense, which is now anyway the commonest for the noun too
  2. ^ Rescher, Nicholas (2005). The Oxford companion to philosophy. Ted Honderich (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 791. ISBN 978-0-19-153265-8. OCLC 62563098. reason. The general human ‘faculty’ or capacity for truth-seeking and problem solving
  3. ^ Mercier, Hugo; Sperber, Dan (2017). The Enigma of Reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. p. 2. ISBN 9780674368309. OCLC 959650235. Enhanced with reason, cognition can secure better knowledge in all domains and adjust action to novel and ambitious goals, or so the story goes. […] Understanding why only a few species have echolocation is easy. Understanding why only humans have reason is much more challenging. Compare: MacIntyre, Alasdair (1999). Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues. The Paul Carus Lectures. Vol. 20. Open Court Publishing. ISBN 9780812693973. OCLC 40632451. Retrieved 2014-12-01. […] the exercise of independent practical reasoning is one essential constituent to full human flourishing. It is not—as I have already insisted—that one cannot flourish at all, if unable to reason. Nonetheless not to be able to reason soundly at the level of practice is a grave disability.
  4. ^ See, for example:
    • Amoretti, Maria Cristina; Vassallo, Nicla, eds. (2013). Reason and Rationality. Philosophische Analyse / Philosophical Analysis. Vol. 48. Berlin: De Gruyter. doi:10.1515/9783110325867. ISBN 9783868381634. OCLC 807032616.
    • Audi, Robert (2001). The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and Substance of Rationality. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195158427.001.0001. ISBN 0195141121. OCLC 44046914.
    • Eze, Emmanuel Chukwudi (2008). On Reason: Rationality in a World of Cultural Conflict and Racism. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. doi:10.1215/9780822388777. ISBN 9780822341789. OCLC 180989486.
    • Rescher, Nicholas (1988). Rationality: A Philosophical Inquiry into the Nature and the Rationale of Reason. Clarendon Library of Logic and Philosophy. Oxford; New York: Clarendon Press; Oxford University Press. ISBN 0198244355. OCLC 17954516.

  5. ^ Hintikka, J. «Philosophy of logic». Encyclopædia Britannica. Encyclopædia Britannica, Inc. Retrieved 12 November 2013.
  6. ^ «The Internet Classics Archive – Nicomachean Ethics by Aristotle, Book VI, Translated by W. D. Ross». classics.mit.edu. Retrieved 25 May 2020.
  7. ^ Michel Foucault, «What is Enlightenment?» in The Essential Foucault, eds. Paul Rabinow and Nikolas Rose, New York: The New Press, 2003, 43–57. See also Nikolas Kompridis, «The Idea of a New Beginning: A Romantic Source of Normativity and Freedom,» in Philosophical Romanticism, New York: Routledge, 2006, 32–59; «So We Need Something Else for Reason to Mean», International Journal of Philosophical Studies 8: 3, 271–295.
  8. ^ a b Merriam-Webster.com Merriam-Webster Dictionary definition of reason
  9. ^ Rachels, James. The Elements of Moral Philosophy, 4th ed. McGraw Hill, 2002
  10. ^ Liddell, Henry George; Scott, Robert, «logos», A Greek–English Lexicon. For etymology of English «logic» see any dictionary such as the Merriam Webster entry for logic.
  11. ^ Lewis, Charlton; Short, Charles, «ratio», A Latin Dictionary
  12. ^ See Merriam Webster «rational» and Merriam Webster «reasonable».
  13. ^ a b Habermas, Jürgen (1990). The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  14. ^ Kirk; Raven; Schofield (1983), The Presocratic Philosophers (second ed.), Cambridge University Press. See pp. 204 & 235.
  15. ^ Nicomachean Ethics Book 1.
  16. ^ a b Davidson, Herbert (1992), Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Averroes, on Intellect, Oxford University Press, p. 3.
  17. ^ Moore, Edward, «Plotinus», Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  18. ^ «Plato», Catholic Encyclopedia
  19. ^ «Catholic Culture», Hellenism
  20. ^ «Reason», Catholic Encyclopedia
  21. ^ «Natural Law», Catholic Encyclopedia
  22. ^ «Religion and Science», Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, 2021
  23. ^ Dreyfus, Hubert. «Telepistemology: Descartes’ Last Stand». socrates.berkeley.edu. Retrieved February 23, 2011.
  24. ^ Descartes, «Second Meditation».
  25. ^ Hobbes, Thomas (1839), Molesworth (ed.), De Corpore, London, J. Bohn: «We must not therefore think that computation, that is, ratiocination, has place only in numbers, as if man were distinguished from other living creatures (which is said to have been the opinion of Pythagoras) by nothing but the faculty of numbering; for magnitude, body, motion, time, degrees of quality, action, conception, proportion, speech and names (in which all the kinds of philosophy consist) are capable of addition and substraction [sic]. Now such things as we add or substract, that is, which we put into an account, we are said to consider, in Greek λογίζεσθαι [logizesthai], in which language also συλλογίζεσθι [syllogizesthai] signifies to compute, reason, or reckon
  26. ^ Hobbes, Thomas, «VII. Of the ends, or resolutions of discourse», The English Works of Thomas Hobbes, vol. 3 (Leviathan) and Hobbes, Thomas, «IX. Of the several subjects of knowledge», The English Works of Thomas Hobbes, vol. 3 (Leviathan)
  27. ^ Locke, John (1824) [1689], «XXVII On Identity and Diversity», An Essay concerning Human Understanding Part 1, The Works of John Locke in Nine Volumes (12th ed.), Rivington
  28. ^ Hume, David, «I.IV.VI. Of Personal Identity», A Treatise of Human Nature
  29. ^ Hume, David, «II.III.III. Of the influencing motives of the will.», A Treatise of Human Nature
  30. ^ Hume, David, «I.III.VII (footnote) Of the Nature of the Idea Or Belief», A Treatise of Human Nature
  31. ^ Hume, David, «I.III.XVI. Of the reason of animals», A Treatise of Human Nature
  32. ^ Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason; Critique of Practical Reason.
  33. ^ Michael Sandel, Justice: What’s the Right Thing to Do?, New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2009.
  34. ^ Kant, Immanuel; translated by James W. Ellington [1785] (1993). Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals 3rd ed. Hackett. p. 30. ISBN 978-0-87220-166-8.
  35. ^ See Velkley, Richard (2002), «On Kant’s Socratism», Being After Rousseau, University of Chicago Press and Kant’s own first preface to The Critique of Pure Reason.
  36. ^ Jürgen Habermas, Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995.
  37. ^ Jürgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action: Reason and the Rationalization of Society, translated by Thomas McCarthy. Boston: Beacon Press, 1984.
  38. ^ Nikolas Kompridis, Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory between Past and Future, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2006. See also Nikolas Kompridis, «So We Need Something Else for Reason to Mean», International Journal of Philosophical Studies 8:3, 271–295.
  39. ^ Charles Taylor, Philosophical Arguments (Harvard University Press, 1997), 12; 15.
  40. ^ Michel Foucault, «What is Enlightenment?», The Essential Foucault, New York: The New Press, 2003, 43–57.
  41. ^ Gensler, Harry J. (2010). Introduction to Logic (2nd ed.). New York: Routledge. p. 1. doi:10.4324/9780203855003. ISBN 9780415996501. OCLC 432990013.
  42. ^ Gächter, Simon (2013). «Rationality, social preferences, and strategic decision-making from a behavioral economics perspective». In Wittek, Rafael; Snijders, T. A. B.; Nee, Victor (eds.). The Handbook of Rational Choice Social Research. Stanford, CA: Stanford Social Sciences, an imprint of Stanford University Press. pp. 33–71 (33). doi:10.1515/9780804785501-004. ISBN 9780804784184. OCLC 807769289. S2CID 242795845. The central assumption of the rational choice approach is that decision-makers have logically consistent goals (whatever they are), and, given these goals, choose the best available option.
  43. ^ Hofstadter, Douglas R. (1999) [1979]. Gödel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid (20th anniversary ed.). New York: Basic Books. ISBN 0394756827. OCLC 40724766.
  44. ^ Bickhard, Mark H.; Campbell, Robert L. (July 1996). «Developmental aspects of expertise: rationality and generalization». Journal of Experimental & Theoretical Artificial Intelligence. 8 (3–4): 399–417. doi:10.1080/095281396147393.
  45. ^ a b c Moshman, David (May 2004). «From inference to reasoning: the construction of rationality». Thinking & Reasoning. 10 (2): 221–239. doi:10.1080/13546780442000024. S2CID 43330718.
  46. ^ Ricco, Robert B. (2015). «The development of reasoning». In Lerner, Richard M. (ed.). Handbook of Child Psychology and Developmental Science. Vol. 2. Cognitive Processes (7th ed.). Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons. pp. 519–570 (534). doi:10.1002/9781118963418.childpsy213. ISBN 9781118136850. OCLC 888024689. Moshman’s (1990, 1998, 2004, 2013a) theory of the development of deductive reasoning considers changes in metacognition to be the essential story behind the development of deductive (and inductive) reasoning. In his view, reasoning involves explicit conceptual knowledge regarding inference (metalogical knowledge) and metacognitive awareness of, and control over, inference.
  47. ^ Aristotle, Complete Works (2 volumes), Princeton, 1995, ISBN 0-691-09950-2
  48. ^ Smith, Robin (2020), «Aristotle’s Logic», in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2020 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2022-06-08
  49. ^ See this Perseus search, and compare English translations. and see LSJ dictionary entry for λογικός, section II.2.b.
  50. ^ See the Treatise of Human Nature of David Hume, Book I, Part III, Sect. XVI.
  51. ^ Locke, John (1824) [1689], «XVII Of Reason», An Essay concerning Human Understanding Part 2 and Other Writings, The Works of John Locke in Nine Volumes, vol. 2 (12th ed.), Rivington
  52. ^ Terrence Deacon, The Symbolic Species: The Co-Evolution of Language and the Brain, W.W. Norton & Company, 1998, ISBN 0-393-31754-4
  53. ^ Leviathan Chapter IV Archived 2006-06-15 at the Wayback Machine: «The Greeks have but one word, logos, for both speech and reason; not that they thought there was no speech without reason, but no reasoning without speech»
  54. ^ Posterior Analytics II.19.
  55. ^ See for example Ruth M.J. Byrne (2005). The Rational Imagination: How People Create Counterfactual Alternatives to Reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  56. ^ De Anima III.i–iii; On Memory and Recollection, On Dreams
  57. ^ Mimesis in modern academic writing, starting with Erich Auerbach, is a technical word, which is not necessarily exactly the same in meaning as the original Greek. See Mimesis.
  58. ^ Origins of the Modern Mind p. 172
  59. ^ Jacob Klein A Commentary on the Meno Ch.5
  60. ^ Jacob Klein A Commentary on the Meno p. 122
  61. ^ Origins of the Modern Mind p. 169
  62. ^ «Introduction» to the translation of Poetics by Davis and Seth Benardete p. xvii, xxviii
  63. ^ Davis is here using «poetic» in an unusual sense, questioning the contrast in Aristotle between action (praxis, the praktikē) and making (poēsis, the poētikē): «Human [peculiarly human] action is imitation of action because thinking is always rethinking. Aristotle can define human beings as at once rational animals, political animals, and imitative animals because in the end the three are the same.»
  64. ^ Aristotle On Memory 450a 15–16.
  65. ^ Jacob Klein A Commentary on the Meno p. 109
  66. ^ Aristotle Hist. Anim. I.1.488b.25–26.
  67. ^ Jacob Klein A Commentary on the Meno p. 112
  68. ^ The Origins of the Modern Mind p. 173 see also A Mind So Rare pp. 140–141
  69. ^ Jeffrey, Richard. 1991. Formal logic: its scope and limits, (3rd ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill:1.
  70. ^ Walton, Douglas N. (2014). «Argumentation schemes for argument from analogy». In Ribeiro, Henrique Jales (ed.). Systematic approaches to argument by analogy. Argumentation library. Vol. 25. Cham; New York: Springer Verlag. pp. 23–40. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-06334-8_2. ISBN 978-3-319-06333-1. OCLC 884441074.
  71. ^ Vickers, John (2009). «The Problem of Induction». The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  72. ^ Example: Aristotle Metaphysics 981b: τὴν ὀνομαζομένην σοφίαν περὶ τὰ πρῶτα αἴτια καὶ τὰς ἀρχὰς ὑπολαμβάνουσι πάντες: ὥστε, καθάπερ εἴρηται πρότερον, ὁ μὲν ἔμπειρος τῶν ὁποιανοῦν ἐχόντων αἴσθησιν εἶναι δοκεῖ σοφώτερος, ὁ δὲ τεχνίτης τῶν ἐμπείρων, χειροτέχνου δὲ ἀρχιτέκτων, αἱ δὲ θεωρητικαὶ τῶν ποιητικῶν μᾶλλον. English: «…what is called Wisdom is concerned with the primary causes and principles, so that, as has been already stated, the man of experience is held to be wiser than the mere possessors of any power of sensation, the artist than the man of experience, the master craftsman than the artisan; and the speculative sciences to be more learned than the productive.»
  73. ^ Metaphysics 1009b ποῖα οὖν τούτων ἀληθῆ ἢ ψευδῆ, ἄδηλον: οὐθὲν γὰρ μᾶλλον τάδε ἢ τάδε ἀληθῆ, ἀλλ᾽ ὁμοίως. διὸ Δημόκριτός γέ φησιν ἤτοι οὐθὲν εἶναι ἀληθὲς ἢ ἡμῖν γ᾽ ἄδηλον. English «Thus it is uncertain which of these impressions are true or false; for one kind is no more true than another, but equally so. And hence Democritus says that either there is no truth or we cannot discover it.»
  74. ^ For example Aristotle Metaphysics 983a: ἐπεὶ δὲ φανερὸν ὅτι τῶν ἐξ ἀρχῆς αἰτίων δεῖ λαβεῖν ἐπιστήμην (τότε γὰρ εἰδέναι φαμὲν ἕκαστον, ὅταν τὴν πρώτην αἰτίαν οἰώμεθα γνωρίζειν) English «It is clear that we must obtain knowledge of the primary causes, because it is when we think that we understand its primary cause that we claim to know each particular thing.»
  75. ^ Example: Nicomachean Ethics 1139b: ἀμφοτέρων δὴ τῶν νοητικῶν μορίων ἀλήθεια τὸ ἔργον. καθ᾽ ἃς οὖν μάλιστα ἕξεις ἀληθεύσει ἑκάτερον, αὗται ἀρεταὶ ἀμφοῖν. English The attainment of truth is then the function of both the intellectual parts of the soul. Therefore their respective virtues are those dispositions that will best qualify them to attain truth.
  76. ^ Example: Plato Republic 490b: μιγεὶς τῷ ὄντι ὄντως, γεννήσας νοῦν καὶ ἀλήθειαν, γνοίη English: «Consorting with reality really, he would beget intelligence and truth, attain to knowledge»
  77. ^ «This quest for the beginnings proceeds through sense perception, reasoning, and what they call noesis, which is literally translated by «understanding» or intellect,» and which we can perhaps translate a little bit more cautiously by «awareness,» an awareness of the mind’s eye as distinguished from sensible awareness.» «Progress or Return» in An Introduction to Political Philosophy: Ten Essays by Leo Strauss. (Expanded version of Political Philosophy: Six Essays by Leo Strauss, 1975.) Ed. Hilail Gilden. Detroit: Wayne State UP, 1989.
  78. ^ However, the empiricism of Aristotle must certainly be doubted. For example in Metaphysics 1009b, cited above, he criticizes people who think knowledge might not be possible because, «They say that the impression given through sense-perception is necessarily true; for it is on these grounds that both Empedocles and Democritus and practically all the rest have become obsessed by such opinions as these.»
  79. ^ G.W.F. Hegel The Philosophy of History, p. 9, Dover Publications Inc., ISBN 0-486-20112-0; 1st ed. 1899
  80. ^ a b Sharples, R. W. (2005). The Oxford companion to philosophy. Ted Honderich (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 896. ISBN 978-0-19-153265-8. OCLC 62563098. Moral virtue is the only good an wickedness the only evil…Emotions are interpreted in intellectual terms; those such as distress, pity (which is a species of distress), and fear which reflect false judgements about what is evil, are to be avoided (as also are those which reflect false judgement about what is good, such as love of honours or riches)…They did however allow the wise man such ‘good feelings’ as ‘watchfulness’ or kindness the difference being that these are based on sound (Stoic) reasoning concerning what matters and what does not.
  81. ^ a b Rufus, Musonius (2000). Concise Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy. Routledge. London: Routledge. p. 863. ISBN 0-203-16994-8. OCLC 49569365. Vice is founded on ‘passions’: these are at root false value judgements, in which we lose rational control by overvaluing things which are in fact indifferent. Virtue, a set of sciences governing moral choice, is the one thing of intrinsic worth and therefore genuinely ‘good’.
  82. ^ Baltzly, Dirk (2019), «Stoicism», in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2021-03-27
  83. ^ Radford, Benjamin; Frazier, Kendrick (January 2017). «The Edge of Reason: A Rational Skeptic in an Irrational World». Skeptical Inquirer. 41 (1): 60.
  84. ^ Velkley, Richard (2002), «Speech. Imagination, Origins: Rousseau and the Political Animal», Being after Rousseau: Philosophy and Culture in Question, University of Chicago Press
  85. ^ Rousseau (1997), «Preface», in Gourevitch (ed.), Discourse on the Origin and Foundations of Inequality Among Men or Second Discourse, Cambridge University Press
  86. ^ Velkley, Richard (2002), «Freedom, Teleology, and Justification of Reason», Being after Rousseau: Philosophy and Culture in Question, University of Chicago Press
  87. ^ Plattner, Marc (1997), «Rousseau and the Origins of Nationalism», The Legacy of Rousseau, University of Chicago Press
  88. ^ Dawkins, Richard (2008). The God Delusion (Reprint ed.). Mariner Books. ISBN 978-0-618-91824-9. Scientists… see the fight for evolution as only one battle in a larger war: a looming war between supernaturalism on the one side and rationality on the other.
  89. ^ Strauss, Leo, «Progress or Return», An Introduction to Political Philosophy
  90. ^ Locke, John (1824) [1689], «XVIII Of Faith and Reason, and their distinct Provinces.», An Essay concerning Human Understanding Part 2 and Other Writings, The Works of John Locke in Nine Volumes, vol. 2 (12th ed.), Rivington
  91. ^ Plantinga, Alvin (2011). Where the Conflict Really Lies: Science, Religion, and Naturalism (1 ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-981209-7.
  92. ^ Natural Signs and Knowledge of God: A New Look at Theistic Arguments (Reprint ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2012. ISBN 978-0-19-966107-7.
  93. ^ Stephen Jay Gould (1997). «Nonoverlapping Magisteria». www.stephenjaygould.org. Retrieved 2016-04-06. To say it for all my colleagues and for the umpteenth millionth time (from college bull sessions to learned treatises): science simply cannot (by its legitimate methods) adjudicate the issue of God’s possible superintendence of nature. We neither affirm nor deny it; we simply can’t comment on it as scientists.
  94. ^ Dawkins, Richard (2008). «4». The God Delusion (Reprint ed.). Mariner Books. ISBN 978-0-618-91824-9. This sounds terrific, right up until you give it a moment’s thought. You then realize that the presence of a creative deity in the universe is clearly a scientific hypothesis. Indeed, it is hard to imagine a more momentous hypothesis in all of science. A universe with a god would be a completely different kind of universe from one without, and it would be a scientific difference. God could clinch the matter in his favour at any moment by staging a spectacular demonstration of his powers, one that would satisfy the exacting standards of science. Even the infamous Templeton Foundation recognized that God is a scientific hypothesis — by funding double-blind trials to test whether remote prayer would speed the recovery of heart patients. It didn’t, of course, although a control group who knew they had been prayed for tended to get worse (how about a class action suit against the Templeton Foundation?) Despite such well-financed efforts, no evidence for God’s existence has yet appeared.
  95. ^ Seachris, Joshua W. (April 2009). «The Meaning of Life as Narrative: A New Proposal for Interpreting Philosophy’s ‘Primary’ Question – Joshua W. Seachris – Philo (Philosophy Documentation Center)». Philo. 12 (1): 5–23. doi:10.5840/philo20091211. Retrieved 2016-04-06.
  96. ^ Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry: Encyclopaedia, Genealogy, and Tradition (60067th ed.). University of Notre Dame Press. 1991. ISBN 978-0-268-01877-1.
  97. ^ Taylor, Charles (2007). A Secular Age (1st ed.). The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-02676-6.
  98. ^ «Cardinal Ratzinger on Europe’s Crisis of Culture».
  99. ^ When Athens Met Jerusalem: An Introduction to Classical and Christian Thought (58760th ed.). IVP Academic. 2009. ISBN 978-0-8308-2923-1.
  100. ^ Shestov, Lev (1968). «Athens and Jerusalem». Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences. 950 (1): 17. Bibcode:2001NYASA.950…17P. doi:10.1111/j.1749-6632.2001.tb02124.x. S2CID 21347905.
  101. ^ «Progress or Return» in An Introduction to Political Philosophy: Ten Essays by Leo Strauss. (Expanded version of Political Philosophy: Six Essays by Leo Strauss, 1975.) Ed. Hilail Gilden. Detroit: Wayne State UP, 1989.
  102. ^ Bhagavad Gita, Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan: «Hinduism is not just a faith. It is the union of reason and intuition that can not be defined but is only to be experienced.»
  103. ^ Manktelow, K.I. 1999. Reasoning and Thinking (Cognitive Psychology: Modular Course.). Hove, Sussex:Psychology Press
  104. ^ Johnson-Laird, P.N. & Byrne, R.M.J. (1991). Deduction. Hillsdale: Erlbaum
  105. ^ Johnson-Laird, P.N. (2006). How we reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press
  106. ^ Byrne, R.M.J. (2005). The Rational Imagination: How People Create Counterfactual Alternatives to Reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
  107. ^ Demetriou, A. (1998). Cognitive development. In A. Demetriou, W. Doise, K.F.M. van Lieshout (Eds.), Life-span developmental psychology (pp. 179–269). London: Wiley.
  108. ^ Costantini, Stefania (2002), «Meta-reasoning: A Survey», Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 2408/2002 (65): 253–288, doi:10.1007/3-540-45632-5_11, ISBN 978-3-540-43960-8
  109. ^ Mercier, Hugo; Sperber, Dan (2011). «Why Do Humans Reason? Arguments for an Argumentative Theory». Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 34 (2): 57–74. doi:10.1017/S0140525X10000968. PMID 21447233. S2CID 5669039.
  110. ^ Mercier, Hugo; Sperber, Dan (2017). The Enigma of Reason. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-36830-9.
  111. ^ Politics I.2.1252b15

Further reading[edit]

Look up reason in Wiktionary, the free dictionary.

Wikiquote has quotations related to Reason.

  • Reason at PhilPapers
  • Beer, Francis A., «Words of Reason», Political Communication 11 (Summer, 1994): 185–201.
  • Gilovich, Thomas (1991), How We Know What Isn’t So: The Fallibility of Human Reason in Everyday Life, New York: The Free Press, ISBN 978-0-02-911705-7

English[edit]

Etymology[edit]

From Middle English resoun, reson, from Anglo-Norman raisun (Old French raison), from Latin ratiō, from ratus, past participle of reor (reckon), ultimately from Proto-Indo-European *h₂reh₁- (to think), reanalysed root of *h₂er- (to put together). Doublet of ration and ratio.

Pronunciation[edit]

  • IPA(key): /ˈɹiːzən/
  • Rhymes: -iːzən
  • Hyphenation: rea‧son

Noun[edit]

reason (countable and uncountable, plural reasons)

  1. A cause:
    1. That which causes something: an efficient cause, a proximate cause.

      The reason this tree fell is that it had rotted.

      • 1996, Daniel Clement Dennett, Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life, page 198:
        There is a reason why so many should be symmetrical: The selective advantage in a symmetrical complex is enjoyed by all the subunits []
    2. A motive for an action or a determination.

      The reason I robbed the bank was that I needed the money.

      If you don’t give me a reason to go with you, I won’t.

      • 1806, Anonymous, Select Notes to Book XXI, in, Alexander Pope, translator, The Odyssey of Homer, volume 6 (London, F.J. du Roveray), page 37:
        This is the reason why he proposes to offer a libation, to atone for the abuse of the day by their diversions.
      • 1908, Henry James, chapter 10, in The Portrait of a Lady (The Novels and Tales of Henry James), volume (please specify |volume=I or II), New York edition, Boston, Mass.; New York, N.Y.: Charles Scribner’s Sons, →OCLC; republished as The Portrait of a Lady (EBook #283), United States: Project Gutenberg, 1 September 2001:

        Ralph Touchett, for reasons best known to himself, had seen fit to say that Gilbert Osmond was not a good fellow []

    3. An excuse: a thought or a consideration offered in support of a determination or an opinion; that which is offered or accepted as an explanation.
      • 1966, Graham Greene, The Comedians, Penguin Classics, →ISBN, page 14:

        I have forgotten the reason he gave for not travelling by air. I felt sure that it was not the correct reason, and that he suffered from a heart trouble which he kept to himself.

    4. (logic) A premise placed after its conclusion.
  2. (uncountable) Rational thinking (or the capacity for it); the cognitive faculties, collectively, of conception, judgment, deduction and intuition.

    Mankind should develop reason above all other virtues.

    • 1898, H.G. Wells, The War of the Worlds, London: William Heinemann, page 113:

      The tremendous tragedy in which he had been involved — it was evident he was a fugitive from Weybridge — had driven him to the very verge of his reason.

    • 1970, Hannah Arendt, On Violence, →ISBN, page 62:

      And the specific distinction between man and beast is now, strictly speaking, no longer reason (the lumen naturale of the human animal) but science []

    • 2014 June 21, “Magician’s brain”, in The Economist, volume 411, number 8892:

      The [Isaac] Newton that emerges from the [unpublished] manuscripts is far from the popular image of a rational practitioner of cold and pure reason. The architect of modern science was himself not very modern. He was obsessed with alchemy.

  3. (obsolete) Something reasonable, in accordance with thought; justice.
    • 16th century Edmund Spenser, Lines on his Promised Pension
      I was promised, on a time, To have reason for my rhyme.
  4. (mathematics, obsolete) Ratio; proportion.
    • 1734, Isaac Barrow, “Lecture XVII. Of the Names and Diversities of the Twofold Kind of Reason or Proportion, viz. Arithmetical and Geometrical”, in John Kirkby, transl., The Usefulness of Mathematical Learning Explained and Demonstrated: Being Mathematical Lectures Read in the Publick Schools at the University of Cambridge. [], London: [] Stephen Austen, [], →OCLC, pages 323–324:

      [I]f two Quantities repreſented by the Numbers 20 and 4 be compared, by dividing the Antecedent 20 by the Conſequent 4, the Quotient is 5; but inverting the Terms, by dividing 4 by 20 the Quotient is {displaystyle {tfrac {4}{20}}={tfrac {1}{5}}}. By which Quotients are declared the Geometrical Reaſons of the propoſed Quantities, becauſe if the Quotient found be multiplied by the Conſequent, the Product is equal to the Antecedent; for in the former Compariſon {displaystyle 5times 4=20}, in the latter {displaystyle {tfrac {1}{5}}times 20=4}; as Things again are referred to Equality.

Synonyms[edit]

  • (that which causes): cause
  • (motive for an action): rationale, motive
  • (thought offered in support): excuse

Derived terms[edit]

  • age of reason
  • by reason of
  • for no good reason
  • for some reason
  • for XYZ reasons
  • have reason
  • in reason
  • instrumental reason
  • reasonability
  • reasonable
  • reasonableness
  • reasonist
  • reasonless
  • rhyme or reason
  • stand to reason
  • unreason
  • with reason
  • within reason

Translations[edit]

that which causes: a cause

  • Aghwan: 𐕗𐔰𐕊𐔰𐕙 (ṗač̣ar)
  • Albanian: arsye (sq) f, shkak (sq)
  • Arabic: سَبَب‎ m (sabab)
    Egyptian Arabic: سبب‎ m (sabab)
    South Levantine Arabic: سبب‎ m (sábab)
  • Armenian: պատճառ (hy) (patčaṙ)
  • Assamese: কাৰণ (karon)
  • Avar: сабаб (sabab)
  • Azerbaijani: səbəb (az)
  • Bashkir: сәбәп (säbäp)
  • Basque: arrazoi
  • Belarusian: прычы́на f (pryčýna)
  • Bengali: কারণ (bn) (karon)
  • Bulgarian: причи́на (bg) f (pričína)
  • Burmese: ဟိတ် (my) (hit)
  • Chichewa: chifukwa
  • Chinese:
    Cantonese: 理由 (lei5 jau4), 原因 (jyun4 jan1)
    Mandarin: 理由 (zh) (lǐyóu), 原因 (zh) (yuányīn)
  • Crimean Tatar: sebep
  • Czech: příčina (cs) f
  • Danish: årsag (da) c
  • Dutch: oorzaak (nl) f, reden (nl) f, grond (nl) m
  • Estonian: põhjus
  • Finnish: syy (fi)
  • French: raison (fr) f, cause (fr) f
  • Galician: razón (gl) f
  • Georgian: მიზეზი (mizezi), საბაბი (sababi)
  • German: Grund (de) m, Ursache (de) f
  • Greek: λόγος (el) m (lógos)
    Ancient: αἰτία f (aitía)
  • Hebrew: סיבה סִבָּה (he) f (sibá)
  • Hindi: कारण (hi) m (kāraṇ), वजह (hi) f (vajah)
  • Hungarian: ok (hu)
  • Icelandic: ástæða (is) f
  • Indonesian: alasan (id), sebab (id)
  • Irish: ábhar (ga) m, fáth m
    Old Irish: accuis f, adbar n
  • Italian: ragione (it), causa (it), perché (it)
  • Japanese: 理由 (ja) (りゆう, riyū), 原因 (ja) (げんいん, gen’in)
  • Kapampangan: sangkan
  • Kazakh: себеп (kk) (sebep)
  • Khmer: ករណី (km) (kaʼraʼnəy), ហេតុ (km) (haet)
  • Korean: 이유(理由) (ko) (iyu), 원인(原因) (ko) (wonin)
  • Kyrgyz: себеп (ky) (sebep)
  • Lao: ເຫດຜົນ (lo), ສາເຫດ (lo)
  • Latin: causa (la) f
  • Latvian: cēlonis m
  • Lithuanian: priežastis (lt) m
  • Macedonian: при́чина f (príčina)
  • Malay: sebab (ms), alasan
  • Malayalam: കാരണം (ml) (kāraṇaṃ), -കൊണ്ട് (-koṇṭŭ) (suffix)
  • Mongolian: учир (mn) (učir), шалтгаан (mn) (šaltgaan)
  • Norwegian:
    Bokmål: årsak (no) m or f
  • Old English: intinga m
  • Pashto: سبب (ps) m (sabáb), دليل (ps) m (dalíl)
  • Persian: دلیل (fa) (dalil), سبب (fa) (sabab)
  • Polish: przyczyna (pl) f
  • Portuguese: causa (pt) f, motivo (pt) m, razão (pt) f
  • Romanian: cauză (ro) f
  • Russian: причи́на (ru) f (pričína)
  • Serbo-Croatian:
    Cyrillic: разлог m, узрок m
    Roman: razlog (sh) m, ùzrok (sh) m
  • Slovak: príčina f, dôvod
  • Slovene: vzrok m, razlog (sl) m
  • Spanish: razón (es) f, causa (es) f
  • Swedish: anledning (sv) c, skäl (sv) n, orsak (sv) c
  • Tajik: сабаб (tg) (sabab)
  • Tamil: காரணம் (ta) (kāraṇam)
  • Tatar: сәбәп (tt) (säbäp)
  • Thai: เหตุผล (th) (hèet-pǒn), สาเหตุ (th) (săa-hèet), เหตุ (th) (hèet)
  • Turkish: neden (tr), sebep (tr)
  • Turkmen: sebäp
  • Ukrainian: причи́на (uk) f (pryčýna)
  • Urdu: وجہ(waja), سبب(sabab), باعث(bāis)
  • Uyghur: سەۋەب(seweb)
  • Uzbek: sabab (uz)
  • Venetian: rexon (vec) f
  • Vietnamese: lý do (vi), nguyên nhân (vi)

motive for an action or determination

  • Armenian: պատճառ (hy) (patčaṙ), դրդապատճառ (hy) (drdapatčaṙ)
  • Bulgarian: основание (bg) n (osnovanie), мотив (bg) m (motiv)
  • Chinese:
    Cantonese: 理由 (lei5 jau4), 道理 (dou6 lei5), 原因 (jyun4 jan1)
    Mandarin: 理由 (zh) (lǐyóu)
  • Czech: důvod (cs) m
  • Dutch: reden (nl) f
  • Finnish: syy (fi)
  • French: raison (fr) f
  • Georgian: მიზეზი (mizezi), საბაბი (sababi)
  • German: Grund (de) m
  • Greek:
    Ancient: αἰτία f (aitía)
  • Hungarian: indíték (hu)
  • Indonesian: alasan (id), motif (id)
  • Irish: ábhar (ga) m, fáth m
    Old Irish: adbar n
  • Italian: motivo (it), ragione (it)
  • Japanese: 理由 (ja) (りゆう, riyū)
  • Latin: ratio (la)
  • Polish: powód (pl) m
  • Portuguese: motivo (pt) m
  • Romanian: motiv (ro) n, rațiune (ro) f
  • Russian: причи́на (ru) f (pričína), резо́н (ru) m (rezón), моти́в (ru) m (motív), по́вод (ru) m (póvod)
  • Slovak: dôvod
  • Swedish: anledning (sv) c, skäl (sv) n, motiv (sv)
  • Turkish: neden (tr), sebep (tr)
  • Venetian: motivo m

excuse, explanation: thought or consideration offered in support of a determination

  • Armenian: պատճառաբանություն (hy) (patčaṙabanutʿyun)
  • Azerbaijani: əsas (az), bəhanə (az)
  • Belarusian: ра́цыя f (rácyja)
  • Bulgarian: оправдание (bg) n (opravdanie)
  • Czech: důvod (cs) m
  • Dutch: reden (nl) f
  • Finnish: syy (fi), tekosyy (fi)
  • French: raison (fr) f
  • German: Grund (de) m
  • Greek: λόγος (el) m (lógos), δικαιολογία (el) f (dikaiología)
  • Hungarian: indok (hu)
  • Irish: ábhar (ga) m, fáth m
    Old Irish: adbar n
  • Italian: scusa (it) f, pretesa (it) f
  • Polish: racja (pl) f, powód (pl) m
  • Russian: по́вод (ru) m (póvod), до́вод (ru) m (dóvod), резо́н (ru) m (rezón)
  • Slovak: dôvod
  • Turkish: açıklama (tr)
  • Ukrainian: ра́ція (uk) f (rácija), до́від m (dóvid)
  • Venetian: scuxa f

(the capacity of the human mind for) rational thinking

  • Albanian: arsye (sq)
  • Arabic: عَقْل (ar) m (ʕaql)
  • Armenian: բանականություն (hy) (banakanutʿyun)
  • Asturian: razón
  • Bashkir: аҡыл (aqıl)
  • Belarusian: ро́зум m (rózum)
  • Bulgarian: ра́зум (bg) m (rázum), разсъдък (bg) m (razsǎdǎk)
  • Catalan: raó (ca) f
  • Chinese:
    Mandarin: 理致 (zh) (lǐzhì), 理性 (zh) (lǐxìng), 理智 (zh) (lǐzhì)
  • Czech: rozum (cs) m
  • Danish: fornuft
  • Dutch: rede (nl) f
  • Esperanto: racieco
  • Finnish: järki (fi), tolkku (fi)
  • French: raison (fr) m
  • Friulian: reson f
  • Galician: razón (gl)
  • Georgian: გონება (goneba)
  • German: Verstand (de) m, Vernunft (de) f, Intellekt (de) m
  • Gothic: 𐌷𐌿𐌲𐍃 m (hugs), 𐍆𐍂𐌰𐌸𐌹 f (fraþi)
  • Greek: λόγος (el) m (lógos), λογική (el) f (logikí)
    Ancient: λογισμός m (logismós)
  • Haitian Creole: rezon
  • Hungarian: értelem (hu), ész (hu), gondolkodás (hu)
  • Irish: réasún m
  • Italian: ragione (it) f
  • Japanese: 思慮 (ja) (しりょ, shiryo), 理致 (ja) (りち, richi), 理性 (ja) (りせい, risei)
  • Kazakh: ақыл-парасат (aqyl-parasat)
  • Korean: 이성(理性) (ko) (iseong), 이치(理致) (ko) (ichi)
  • Ladin: rejon
  • Latin: ratio (la) f, causa (la) f
  • Latvian: saprāts m
  • Malayalam: യുക്തി (ml) (yukti)
  • Norwegian: fornuft (no)
  • Occitan: rason (oc)
  • Old Church Slavonic:
    Cyrillic: разоумъ m (razumŭ)
  • Old French: reson, raison
  • Persian: عقل (fa) (‘aql)
  • Polish: rozum (pl) m
  • Portuguese: razão (pt) f
  • Romanian: rațiune (ro)
  • Russian: ра́зум (ru) (rázum), рассу́док (ru) m (rassúdok), ум (ru) m (um)
  • Serbo-Croatian:
    Cyrillic: ра̏зӯм m
    Roman: rȁzūm (sh) m
  • Slovak: rozum m
  • Slovene: rázum m
  • Spanish: razón (es) f
  • Swedish: förstånd (sv) n, förnuft (sv) n
  • Thai: เหตุผล (th) (hèet-pǒn)
  • Turkish: akıl (tr)
  • Ukrainian: ро́зум (uk) m (rózum)
  • Venetian: raxon, rexon (vec) f
  • Vietnamese: lý trí (vi)

math: ratio, proportion see ratio

Translations to be checked‌: «basic meaning «cause»»

  • Albanian: (please verify) arsye (sq), (please verify) arësye
  • Catalan: (please verify) raó (ca)
  • Dalmatian: (please verify) rasaun f
  • Danish: (please verify) grund (da)
  • Esperanto: (please verify) kialo (eo)
  • Estonian: (please verify) põhjus, (please verify) ajend
  • Friulian: (please verify) reson
  • Georgian: (please verify) მიზეზი (mizezi)
  • Greek: (please verify) λόγος (el) m (lógos)
  • Hindi: (please verify) कारण (hi) m (kāraṇ), (please verify) वजह (hi) f (vajah)
  • Hungarian: (please verify) ok (hu)
  • Italian: (please verify) causa (it) f, (please verify) ragione (it) f, (please verify) motivo (it) m
  • Kurdish:
    Central Kurdish: (please verify) ھۆ (ckb) (ho)
  • Latgalian: (please verify) īmesle f
  • Latvian: (please verify) iemesls m, (please verify) cēlonis m
  • Malayalam: (please verify) കാരണം (ml) (kāraṇaṃ), (please verify) ഹേതു (ml) (hētu)
  • Norwegian: (please verify) grunn (no)
  • Occitan: (please verify) rason (oc)
  • Persian: (please verify) سبب (fa) (sabab)
  • Sanskrit: (please verify) निदान (sa) n (nidāna), (please verify) हेतु (sa) m (hetu)
  • Sardinian: (please verify) rajòne
  • Scottish Gaelic: (please verify) adhbhar m
  • Serbo-Croatian: (please verify) rázlog (sh) m
  • Spanish: (please verify) causa (es) f, (please verify) razón (es) f
  • Swahili: (please verify) sababu (sw)
  • Swedish: (please verify) orsak (sv), (please verify) anledning (sv) n
  • Telugu: (please verify) కారణం (te) (kāraṇaṁ)
  • Urdu: (please verify) وجہ (ur) f (vajah), (please verify) کارن(kāraṇ)

Verb[edit]

reason (third-person singular simple present reasons, present participle reasoning, simple past and past participle reasoned)

  1. (intransitive) To deduce or come to a conclusion by being rational
    • 1892, Arthur Conan Doyle, The Adventure of the Speckled Band
      «I had,» said he, «come to an entirely erroneous conclusion which shows, my dear Watson, how dangerous it always is to reason from insufficient data. [] «
  2. (intransitive) To perform a process of deduction or of induction, in order to convince or to confute; to argue.
    • 1853, Solomon Northup, chapter III, in [David Wilson], editor, Twelve Years a Slave. Narrative of Solomon Northrup, a Citizen of New-York, Kidnapped in Washington City in 1841, and Rescued in 1853, from a Cotton Plantation near the Red River, in Louisiana, London: Sampson Low, Son & Co.; Auburn, N.Y.: Derby and Miller, →OCLC, page 47:

      Still my spirit was not broken. I indulged the anticipation of escape, and that speedily. It was impossible, I reasoned, that men could be so unjust as to detain me as a slave, when the truth of my case was known.

  3. (intransitive, obsolete) To converse; to compare opinions.
  4. (transitive, intransitive) To arrange and present the reasons for or against; to examine or discuss by arguments; to debate or discuss.
    I reasoned the matter with my friend.
    • 1901, Ralph Connor, The Man from Glengarry Chapter 9
      The talk was mainly between Aleck and Murdie, the others crowding eagerly about and putting in a word as they could. Murdie was reasoning good-humoredly, Aleck replying fiercely.
  5. (transitive, rare) To support with reasons, as a request.
  6. (transitive) To persuade by reasoning or argument.

    to reason one into a belief; to reason one out of his plan

    • 1815 December (indicated as 1816), [Jane Austen], chapter 10, in Emma: [], volume (please specify |volume=I, II or III), London: [] [Charles Roworth and James Moyes] for John Murray, →OCLC:

      That she was not immediately ready, Emma did suspect to arise from the state of her nerves; she had not yet possessed the instrument long enough to touch it without emotion; she must reason herself into the power of performance; and Emma could not but pity such feelings, whatever their origin, and could not but resolve never to expose them to her neighbour again.

  7. (transitive, with down) To overcome or conquer by adducing reasons.
    to reason down a passion
  8. (transitive, usually with out) To find by logical process; to explain or justify by reason or argument.
    to reason out the causes of the librations of the moon

Derived terms[edit]

Terms derived from the verb “reason”

Translations[edit]

to deduce by being rational

to perform a process of deduction or of induction

to converse; to compare opinions

to arrange and present the reasons for or against; to examine, debate, discuss see debate

Translations to be checked

  • Indonesian: (please verify) alasan (id), (please verify) sebab (id), (please verify) dasar (id)
  • Mandarin: (please verify) 理由 (zh) (lǐyóu)
  • Romanian: (please verify) motiv (ro) n (1), (please verify) rațiune (ro) f (2)
  • Yiddish: (please verify) סיבה‎ f (sibe) (1), (please verify) שׂכל‎ m (seykhl) (2)

Further reading[edit]

  • reason at OneLook Dictionary Search
  • reason in Webster’s Revised Unabridged Dictionary, G. & C. Merriam, 1913
  • “reason”, in The Century Dictionary [], New York, N.Y.: The Century Co., 1911, →OCLC.

Anagrams[edit]

  • Roanes, Serano, arseno-, senora, señora

English word reason comes from Proto-Italic *rēōr (Reckon, calculate.. Think, deem, judge.), Proto-Indo-European *rh₁-tós, Latin reri

Detailed word origin of reason

Dictionary entry Language Definition
*rēōr Proto-Italic (itc-pro) Reckon, calculate.. Think, deem, judge.
*rh₁-tós Proto-Indo-European (ine-pro)
reri Latin (lat)
reor Latin (lat) I reckon, calculate.. I think, deem, judge.
*ratos Proto-Italic (itc-pro) Established, authoritative. Fixed, certain.
ratus Latin (lat) ; rat Established, authoritative. Fixed, certain.
rationem Latin (lat)
raisun Anglo-Norman (xno)
reason English (eng) (intransitive) To converse; to compare opinions.. (intransitive) To deduce or come to a conclusion by being rational. (intransitive) To perform a process of deduction or of induction, in order to convince or to confute; to argue.. (transitive) To arrange and present the reasons for or against; to examine or discuss by arguments; to debate or discuss.. (transitive) To persuade by reasoning or […]

Words with the same origin as reason

  • Top Definitions
  • Synonyms
  • Quiz
  • Related Content
  • Examples
  • British
  • Idioms And Phrases

This shows grade level based on the word’s complexity.

This shows grade level based on the word’s complexity.


noun

a basis or cause, as for some belief, action, fact, event, etc.: the reasons for declaring war.

a statement presented in justification or explanation of a belief or action: I dare you to give me one good reason for quitting school!

sufficient cause, as produced by a situation that makes an act, feeling, etc., obviously proper or appropriate: After the mess he made of our yard, we have good reason to look for another landscaper.

the mental powers concerned with forming conclusions, judgments, or inferences: Effective leadership requires a person of reason.

sound judgment; good sense.

normal or sound powers of mind; sanity.

Logic. a premise of an argument.

Philosophy.

  1. the faculty or power of acquiring intellectual knowledge, either by direct understanding of first principles or by argument.
  2. the power of intelligent and dispassionate thought, or of conduct influenced by such thought.
  3. Kantianism. the faculty by which the ideas of pure reason are created.

verb (used without object)

to think or argue in a logical manner.

to form conclusions, judgments, or inferences from facts or premises.

to urge reasons which should determine belief or action.

verb (used with object)

to think through logically, as a problem (often followed by out).

to conclude or infer.

to convince, persuade, etc., by reasoning.

to support with reasons.

QUIZ

CAN YOU ANSWER THESE COMMON GRAMMAR DEBATES?

There are grammar debates that never die; and the ones highlighted in the questions in this quiz are sure to rile everyone up once again. Do you know how to answer the questions that cause some of the greatest grammar debates?

Which sentence is correct?

Idioms about reason

    bring (someone) to reason, to induce a change of opinion in (someone) through presentation of arguments; convince: The mother tried to bring her rebellious daughter to reason.

    by reason of, on account of; because of: He was consulted about the problem by reason of his long experience.

    in / within reason, in accord with reason; justifiable; proper: She tried to keep her demands in reason.

    stand to reason, to be clear, obvious, or logical: With such an upbringing it stands to reason that the child will be spoiled.

    with reason, with justification; properly: The government is concerned about the latest crisis, and with reason.

Origin of reason

First recorded in 1175–1225; Middle English resoun, reisun (noun), from Old French reisun, reson, from Latin ratiōn- (stem of ratiō ) ratio

synonym study for reason

1. Reason, cause, motive are terms for a circumstance (or circumstances) which brings about or explains certain results. A reason is an explanation of a situation or circumstance which made certain results seem possible or appropriate: The reason for the robbery was the victim’s display of his money. The cause is the way in which the circumstances produce the effect, that is, make a specific action seem necessary or desirable: The cause was the robber’s extreme need of money. A motive is the hope, desire, or other force which starts the action (or an action) in an attempt to produce specific results: The motive was to get money to buy food for his family.

usage note for reason

The construction reason is because is criticized in a number of usage guides: The reason for the long delays was because the costs greatly exceeded the original estimates. One objection to this construction is based on its redundancy: the word because (literally, by cause ) contains within it the meaning of reason; thus saying the reason is because is like saying “The cause is by cause,” which would never be said. A second objection is based on the claim that because can introduce only adverbial clauses and that reason is requires completion by a noun clause. Critics would substitute that for because in the offending construction: The reason for the long delays in completing the project was that the costs. … Although the objections described here are frequently raised, reason is because is still common in almost all levels of speech and occurs often in edited writing as well.
A similar charge of redundancy is made against the reason why, which is also a well-established idiom: The reason why the bill failed to pass was the defection of three key senators.

OTHER WORDS FROM reason

rea·son·er, nounnon·rea·son, nounnon·rea·son·er, nounoutreason, verb (used with object)

sub·rea·son, noun

Words nearby reason

rearrange, rear sight, rearview mirror, rearward, Rea Silvia, reason, reasonable, Reason, Age of, reasoned, reasoning, reasonless

Dictionary.com Unabridged
Based on the Random House Unabridged Dictionary, © Random House, Inc. 2023

Words related to reason

logic, reasoning, sense, argument, basis, cause, consideration, goal, idea, impetus, incentive, motivation, motive, proof, purpose, rationale, case, excuse, justification, figure out

How to use reason in a sentence

  • We have reason to believe these kinds of viruses spread better when it’s cold.

  • Today, Feynman’s “dippy process” has become as ubiquitous in physics as calculus, and its mechanics reveal the reasons for some of the discipline’s greatest successes and its current challenges.

  • There are a number of reasons why a particular virus might be more active during certain times of year.

  • Comparing these results with 2016 exit polling is tricky for a few reasons.

  • One of the reasons for this behavior is that consumers who would ordinarily visit stores are buying online to avoid potential exposure to the virus.

  • When twelve people are killed by violence, whoever they are, for whatever reason, that is a tragedy and a waste.

  • The research literature, too, asks these questions, and not without reason.

  • The reason we were liberals is we were against oppression.

  • There is a larger reason, beyond the airlines themselves, why Lion Air and 61 other Indonesian airlines are on this black list.

  • Yet, for god knows what reason, his name is never brought up in the “Great American Filmmaker” conversation.

  • To Americans Mrs. Wright is interesting by reason of her patriotism, which amounted to a passion.

  • Wordsworth has illustrated how an unwise and importunate demand for a reason from a child may drive him into invention.

  • And she fell to scolding him in the way he usually loved,—but at the moment found less stimulating for some reason.

  • The reason we associate rhythm with the significance of time is that rhythm is a measurer of time.

  • That she had her definite reason he knew, as a woman knows when another woman is wearing a last year’s gown.

British Dictionary definitions for reason


noun

the faculty of rational argument, deduction, judgment, etc

sound mind; sanity

a cause or motive, as for a belief, action, etc

an argument in favour of or a justification for something

philosophy the intellect regarded as a source of knowledge, as contrasted with experience

logic grounds for a belief; a premise of an argument supporting that belief

by reason of because of

in reason or within reason within moderate or justifiable bounds

it stands to reason it is logical or obviousit stands to reason that he will lose

listen to reason to be persuaded peaceably

reasons of State political justifications for an immoral act

verb

(when tr, takes a clause as object) to think logically or draw (logical conclusions) from facts or premises

(intr usually foll by with) to urge or seek to persuade by reasoning

(tr often foll by out) to work out or resolve (a problem) by reasoning

Derived forms of reason

reasoner, noun

Word Origin for reason

C13: from Old French reisun, from Latin ratiō reckoning, from rērī to think

usage for reason

The expression the reason is because… should be avoided. Instead one should say either this is because… or the reason is that…

Collins English Dictionary — Complete & Unabridged 2012 Digital Edition
© William Collins Sons & Co. Ltd. 1979, 1986 © HarperCollins
Publishers 1998, 2000, 2003, 2005, 2006, 2007, 2009, 2012

Other Idioms and Phrases with reason


see by reason of; in reason; it stands to reason; listen to reason; lose one’s mind (reason); rhyme or reason; see reason; stand to reason; with reason.

The American Heritage® Idioms Dictionary
Copyright © 2002, 2001, 1995 by Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing Company. Published by Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing Company.

Reason, in philosophy, is the ability to form and operate upon concepts in abstraction, in accordance with rationality and logic. Discussion and debate about the nature, limits, and causes of reason have been important through the history of philosophy. Discussion about reason especially concerns:

  • (a) Its relationship to several other related concepts such as: language, logic, consciousness, knowledge, perception, emotion and will.
  • (b) Its role in determining what is true and what is right.
  • (c) Its origin.

Reason, like consciousness, with which it is also intimately connected, has traditionally been claimed as a distinctly human capacity, not to be found elsewhere in the animal world. However, recent studies in animal cognition show that animals are capable of some types of on a lower level thinking similar to that of humans.

Etymology

The English term “reason” is derived from the French word raison, from Latin rationem (ratio) «reckoning, understanding, motive, cause.» The concept of reason is connected to the concept of language, as reflected in the meanings of the Greek word, «logos.» As reason, rationality, and logic are all associated with the ability of the human mind to predict effects as based upon presumed causes, the word «reason» also denotes a ground or basis for a particular argument, and hence is used synonymously with the word «cause.»

Reason and Understanding

Reason is the means by which human beings achieve understanding by integrating perceptions received through the senses with concepts and associating them with knowledge already acquired. Reason is also the process of evaluating and manipulating ideas and facts.

The fundamental attribute of reason is clarity, and the use of identifiable ideas, memories, emotions, and sensory input. Since reason is a means of achieving understanding, its method is significant. Reason is organized, systematic, and a purposeful way of thinking. Reason also makes use of vehicles such as logic, deduction, and induction to make sense of perceptions and knowledge.

Reason and Logic

While reason is a type of thought, logic is a field of study which categorizes ways of justifying conclusions that are in accordance with reason. This distinction between reason and logic originates with the writings of Aristotle. Although the Greeks had no separate word for logic as opposed to language and reason, Aristotle’s neologism «syllogism» (syllogismos) identified logic clearly for the first time as a distinct field of study. (When Aristotle referred to «the logical,» the source of our word «logic,» he was referring more broadly to reason or “the rational.”)

Although logic is an important aspect of reason, logic and reason are not synonymous. The modern tendency to prefer «hard logic,» or «solid logic,» has incorrectly led to the two terms occasionally being seen as essentially interchangeable, or to the conception that logic is the defining and pure form of reason.

Animals and machines (including computers) can unconsciously perform logical operations, and many animals (including humans) can unconsciously associate different perceptions as causes and effects and then make decisions and even plans. «Reason» is the type of thinking which combines language, consciousness, and logic, something that at this time, only humans are known to be able to do.

Although the relationship between reason and logic has been under discussion for a long time, the neurologist Terrence Deacon, following the tradition of Peirce, has recently offered a useful new description in modern terms. Like many philosophers in the English tradition of Hobbes, Locke, and Hume, he starts by distinguishing the type of thinking which is most essential to human rational thinking as a type of associative thinking. Reason by his account therefore requires associating perceptions in a way which may be arbitrary (or nominal, conventional, or «formal»). The image or «icon» of smoke may not only be related with the image of fire, but, for example, with the English word «smoke,» or with any made-up symbol (not necessarily a spoken word). What is essentially rational, or at least essentially human, is however not the arbitrariness of symbols, but rather, how they are used.

Speculative Reason and Practical Reason

«In theory, there is no difference between theory and practice. But, in practice, there is.» —Jan L. A. van de Snepscheut

«Speculative reason» or «pure reason» is theoretical (or logical, deductive) thought (sometimes called theoretical reason), as opposed to practical (active, willing) thought. «Practical reason» is the application of reason in deciding on a course of action, while speculative (or theoretical) reason is concerned with absolute and universal truths. For example, deciding exactly how to build a telescope is practical reason, whereas deciding between two theories of light and optics is speculative reason.

The distinction between practical and speculative reason was made by the ancient Greek philosophers Plato and Aristotle, who distinguished between theory (theoria, or a wide or clear vision of its structure) and practice (praxis), as well as productive knowledge (techne).

Speculative reason is contemplative, detached, and certain, whereas practical reason is engaged, involved, active, and dependent upon the specifics of the situation. Speculative reason provides the universal, necessary principles of logic, such as the principle of contradiction, which must apply everywhere, regardless of the specifics of the situation. Practical reason, on the other hand, is that power of the mind engaged in deciding what to do. It is also referred to as moral reason, because it involves action, decision, and particulars. Though many other thinkers have erected systems based on the distinction, two important later thinkers who have done so are Aquinas (who follows Aristotle in many respects) and Kant.

In cognitive research, «practical reason» is the process of ignoring unproductive (or undesirable) possibilities in favor of productive possibilities. It is considered a form of cognitive bias, because it is illogical.

Reason, Truth, and “First Principles”

In ancient Greek philosophy a conflict arose between the Platonists and the Aristotelians over the role of reason in confirming truth. Both Aristotle and Plato recognized this as one of the essential questions of philosophy. Human beings use logical syllogisms such as deduction and inductive reasoning to reach conclusions which they feel are more infallible than basic sense perceptions. However, if such conclusions are built only upon sense perceptions, even the most logical conclusions can never be said to be certain, because they are built upon fallible perceptions (or fallible interpretations of perceptions). It is clear that human beings desire to know things with certainty, and that human beings are certain about some things. These things which are known with certainty are referred to as “first principles.”

What is the source of these first principles? Is the source only experience, as claimed in «empiricist» arguments (considered by some as being Aristotelian, and more recently associated with British philosophers such as David Hume)? Or is there some other “faculty” from which we derive our consciousness of at least some «a priori» truths (a position called “idealist” and associated with Platonism)? Or are there certain undeniable axioms that form the base for all other faculties and experiences (a position supported by the Scottish School of Common Sense as exemplified by Thomas Reid, and more recently by Objectivism)?

In view of all these considerations, we arrive at the idea of a special science which can be entitled the Critique of Pure Reason. For reason is the faculty which supplies the principles of a priori knowledge. Pure reason is, therefore, that which contains the principles whereby we know anything absolutely a priori. An organon of pure reason would be the sum-total of those principles according to which all modes of pure a priori knowledge can be acquired and actually brought into being. The exhaustive application of such an organon would give rise to a system of pure reason. But as this would be asking rather much, and as it is still doubtful whether, and in what cases, any extension of our knowledge be here possible, we can regard a science of the mere examination of pure reason, of its sources and limits, as the propaedeutic to the system of pure reason. (Immanuel Kant, sec VII. «The Idea and Division of a Special Science,» Critique of Pure Reason)

In Greek philosophy, “first principles” were “arkhai,” starting points, and the faculty used to perceive them was sometimes referred to in Aristotle and Plato as “nous,” which was close in meaning to “awareness” and therefore “consciousness.” The question of whether we become aware of “arkhai” by building up and comparing experiences, or in some other way, was left unanswered.

Modern proponents of a priori reasoning, at least with regards to language, are Noam Chomsky and Steven Pinker, to whom Merlin Donald and Terrence Deacon can be contrasted.

Reason, Language and Mimesis

The recent writings of Merlin Donald and Terrence Deacon fit into an older tradition which makes reason connected to language, and mimesis, but more specifically the ability to create language as part of an internal modeling of reality specific to humankind. Other results are consciousness and imagination.

Thomas Hobbes describes the creation of “Markes, or Notes of remembrance” (Leviathan Ch.4) as “speech” (allowing by his definition that it is not necessarily a means of communication or speech in the normal sense; in this description he was presumably thinking of «speech» as an English version of «logos»). In the context of a language, these marks or notes are called «Signes» by Hobbes.

David Hume, following John Locke (and Berkeley), who followed Hobbes, emphasized the importance of associative thinking.

Reason, Truth, and Emotion or Passion

In literature, reason is often placed in opposition to emotions, feelings, desires, drives or passions. Others make reason the servant or tool of emotion and desire, a means of comprehending desire and discovering how to fulfill it. Some philosophers including Plato, Rousseau, Hume, and Nietzsche combined both views, making rational thinking not only a servant of desire, but also something which is desired in itself.

The question of whether reason is in fact driven by emotions is important in philosophy, because reason is seen by almost all philosophers as the means by which we come to know the truth, and truth as something objective which exists outside of human consciousness. If reason is affected by emotions, how can we be certain that we are not deceiving ourselves by ignoring undesirable information, or by misinterpreting information in accordance with our unconscious desires?

Sometimes reason clearly seems to come into conflict with certain human desires. Human beings sometimes make choices on the basis of an association of ideas which is an artificially constructed model, rather than an association based on raw experience or passion. Examples are compliance with civil laws or social customs, or the acceptance of religious precepts and discipline.

Reason and Faith, especially in the “Greater West”

In theology, reason, as distinguished from faith, is the human critical faculty exercised upon religious truth, whether by way of discovery or by way of explanation. Some commentators have claimed that Western civilization can be almost defined by the tension between “unaided” reason and faith in «revealed» truths, figuratively represented as Athens and Jerusalem, respectively. Leo Strauss spoke of a «Greater West» which included all areas under the influence of the tension between Greek rationalism and Abrahamic revelation, including the Muslim lands. Strauss was particularly influenced by the great Muslim philosopher Al-Farabi.

The limits within which reason may be used have been prescribed differently in different religious traditions and during different periods of thought. Modern religious thought tends to allow to reason a wide field, reserving as the domain of faith the ultimate (supernatural) truths of theology.

Reason as an Intrinsic Part of Nature

Wilhelm Reich, the controversial Austrian psychiatrist and naturalist, followed in Hegel’s footsteps in perceiving reason not as a reduction to analytic deduction or mechanistic one-dimensional induction, but as being a primal part of the depth structure of nature itself; «a trait that pulsated from the heart of nature and was thus manifested in all living things.»[1] Viewed in these terms reason becomes an ontological term rather than an epistemological one. Reason is understood here as having an objective existence apart from its relation to the mental operations of any observer.

See also

  • Deism
  • Empiricism
  • Logic
  • Language
  • Mind

Notes

  1. Robert S. Corrington and Wilhelm Reich, Psychoanalyst and Radical Naturalist (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2003), 128-129.

References

ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Blattberg, Charles. From pluralist to patriotic politics: putting practice first. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000. ISBN 0198296886
  • Kant, Immanuel. Critique of pure reason. New York: Modern Library, 1958. ISBN 0486432548
  • Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. Philosophy in the flesh: the embodied mind and its challenge to Western thought. New York: Basic Books, 1999. ISBN 0465056733
  • Taylor, Charles. Explanation and practical reason. WIDER working papers, WP 72. Helsinki: World Institute for Development Economics Research, 1989.

External Links

All links retrieved December 7, 2022.

  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
    • Practical Reason.
    • Medieval Theories of Practical Reason.

General Philosophy Sources

  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Paideia Project Online.
  • Project Gutenberg.

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article
in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

  • Reason  history
  • Practical_reason  history
  • Speculative_reason  history

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

  • History of «Reason»

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.

Понравилась статья? Поделить с друзьями:
  • Origin of word heart
  • Origin of the word read
  • Origin of word given
  • Origin of the word product
  • Origin of word future