History of the word values

Everyone has their own sense of value about the things that affect them.

The values that a person holds may be personal or political depending on whether they are considered in relation to the individual or to society.[1] Apart from moral virtue, examples of personal values include friendship, knowledge, beauty etc. and examples of political values, justice, equality and liberty. This article will outline some current ideas relating to the first group – personal values. It will begin by looking at the kinds of thing that have value and finish with a look at some of the theories that attempt to describe what value is.[2] Reference will be made solely to Western sources although it is recognised that many, if not all, of the values discussed may be universal.

Introduction[edit]

It is only in the last hundred years or so that the subject of value has become a subject of study in its own right, though the subject builds on the work of such earlier thinkers as Plato, Immanuel Kant and Jeremy Bentham. A new field of enquiry called «axiology» (from the Greek axios meaning «worth»), defined as «the philosophical study of goodness or value», began to emerge at around the beginning of the twentieth century, and its significance lay in extending the scope of the term «value» into fields other than traditional ethics.[3] R.H.Lotze, F.Brentano and G.E.Moore have been cited as early proponents of the subject, and to Moore is attributed the important distinction made between intrinsic and instrumental value, that is, between things that have value in themselves and things that might lead to something of value.[4]

Examples of recent articles which introduce the subject include Mark Schroeder’s Value Theory,[5] Elinor Mason’s Value Pluralism[6] and Michael Zimmerman’s Intrinsic and Extrinsic Value.[7] Schroeder defines axiology as being «primarily concerned with classifying what things are good», and, in accepting that there might be a number of things that can be valued or called good, he asks is there, underlying these, just one or is there more than one fundamental intrinsic value. Mason outlines two ways in which values have been considered in relation to one another: the first is called «monist», which maintains that there is just one intrinsic value to which all other values are auxiliary; and the second is called «pluralist», which maintains that there are many kinds of value and that the most important of these are irreducible to one another. Typical of the first school were the Utilitarians, such as Jeremy Bentham, who thought that all the values that a person might hold could be reduced to a desire for happiness or pleasure. Immanuel Kant, too, has been described as a monist in saying that the only good in itself lies in possessing a good will.[8] Regarding those holding pluralist views, Zimmerman in his book The Nature of Intrinsic Value (2012) gives some examples of more recent philosophers with lists of the kinds of thing that they thought had value:[9]

Brentano (1889): Pleasure, Happiness, Love, Knowledge, Beauty, Proportion, Intention, Exercise, Virtue[10]

Moore (1908) — Aesthetics, Affection, Knowledge, Consciousness, Pleasure, Virtue[11]

Ross (1936) — Virtue, Pleasure, Knowledge, Artistic activity[12]

In particular, Zimmerman singles out the work of William Frankena who, in his book Ethics (1963), gave a comprehensive list of values and who, besides suggesting the use of headings, began to group similar values together.[13] It will be useful to discuss these in the following groups:

1. Beauty, harmony, proportion, aesthetic experience

2. Moral disposition, virtue, pleasure, happiness, contentment

3. Truth, knowledge, understanding, wisdom, honour, esteem

4. Life, health, strength, peace, security

5. Love, affection, friendship, cooperation

6. Power, achievement, freedom, adventure, novelty

Frankena, in formulating his list, builds on what he called the «classical triad» of beauty, goodness and truth[14] and headings similar to these terms can be used to introduce a primary set of values as follows.

Primary values[edit]

Aesthetic values[edit]

Frankena in his list of values groups beauty with harmony, proportion and aesthetic experience. There are many different kinds of value that can be included in this category and Frankena himself distinguishes between «harmony and proportion in objects contemplated» and «harmony and proportion in one’s own life».[15] He refers to Plato who, firstly, in the Philebus suggests that aesthetic pleasure lies in the «beauty of colour and form», and secondly in the Republic that formal features like harmony and proportion are important not only to art and music but also to the «good life» which itself should contain «form», «variety» and «balance».[16]

Another distinction results from the question of whether aesthetic value resides in the object contemplated or in the contemplative experience itself.[17] James Shelley in his article The Concept of the Aesthetic notes that the term «aesthetic» in deriving from the Greek aesthesis, which means perception or awareness, tends towards the latter interpretation;[18] George Dickie in his book Art and the Aesthetic charts the development of awareness and consciousness in their growing importance to aesthetic theory;[19] and Zimmerman refers to G.E.Moore who wrote in relation to art and beauty that «by far the most valuable thing we know or can imagine are certain states of consciousness».[20] Both Frankena and Nicolai Hartmann, who Frankena mentions, begin their lists of values with groups including consciousness, life and existence, and Hartmann makes reference to Nietzsche who considered that the value of beauty in art or nature lay in an increased awareness of life as an «affirmation of existence».[21]

Shelley describes another concept apart from «immediacy» or «focussing one’s attention on the subject» and this is the concept of «disinterestedness», a Kantian term which consists in looking at things objectively and impartially.[22] He refers to Schopenhauer who realised that if perception were to be the only criterion of aesthetic value then, with a mind stripped of practical interest and cultural preconceptions, anything at all might be seen as beautiful: «One thing is only taken as more beautiful than another because it makes this pure contemplation easier», wrote Schopenhauer,[23] a view criticised by Sartwell for making the term beauty, ultimately meaningless.[24] Shelley, however, manages to elucidate various criteria of aesthetic value from such a standpoint: firstly, that there is value in simple formal relations, in harmony, grace and balance, and in fact in any other objective aspect that a good critic might care to point to; secondly, that there is value in recognising that people have natural tastes and preferences, whether, for example, they prefer «drama or comicality», or whether the work is striking in some way; and thirdly, that there is value in recognising the presence of «non-exhibited properties», realising that the work, or perception, is located within an «art-historical context» where only knowledge of, in Danto’s terminology, an «artworld» can facilitate our feeling «the proper sentiments».[25]

In addition to the views that aesthetic value lies either in the object or in the subjective experience there is a third view which suggests that value lies in some kind of engagement between the two. G.E.Moore wrote that it is neither in the «beautiful object» nor in the «conscious perception» where value is found but in the relationship between the two.[26] Shelley too concludes with the idea that there is some reciprocal relationship between subject and object, his example being that of a Bartok quartet, where «a value originally belonging to the quartet has been transferred to the experience, before being reflected back, once again, onto the quartet.»[27]

Ethical values[edit]

Happiness by French sculptor Jef Lambeaux

The second group of values listed by Frankena includes happiness, virtue, pleasure, satisfaction and contentment – values traditionally associated with the field of ethics.[28] Zimmerman introduces Plato whose recurring concern was with the nature of the good, how we should live our lives, and whether it is pleasure or virtue that will lead to happiness.[29] Regarding pleasure, he considers food, drink and shelter to be simple goods – people value them, they value the work that goes into providing them and the pleasure that comes from enjoying them. Zimmerman after asking why eating should be considered a value refers to Aristotle who said that value resides in «the proper activity or functioning of things according to their nature» and that it is the «active exercising of man’s faculties that give rise to pleasure».[30]

Regarding virtue, Elinor Mason refers to J.S.Mill who made the distinction between lower values and higher values.[31] The distinction is that between efficient cause and final cause: whereas efficient cause includes hunger, thirst and the need for shelter, final cause arises from our having an overview of the relation of cause and effect whereby we can determine the end we want to achieve and then decide the means to achieve it.[32] If the end is well-being or happiness then such values as friendship, knowledge and beauty, as well as material sustenance, might be instrumental in achieving this.[33] Mason refers to G.E.Moore who, whilst recognising the virtues of «industry and temperance», recognised that there exists a «plurality of bearers of value». Love, beauty and friendship are intrinsic values (i.e. good in themselves) rather than instrumental values, and they do not lead in all cases necessarily either to pleasure or happiness.[34]

Another significant writer on value, mentioned by both Frankena and Zimmerman, is John Dewey who questioned whether intrinsic values exist at all. All values for Dewey were instrumental. He compared life to an «ongoing stream» of cause and effect, which he called the «continuum of means and ends»,[35] where for example a lack of food leads to human activity leading to a further expenditure of energy, the need for more food and so on. He maintained, like Aristotle, that value lay in economy and in the efficient functioning of a human being in terms of a whole range of needs and wants.[36] These needs arise from a constant «interaction between a human being and his environment» and Dewey introduced the notion of having a «framework» of values to deal effectively with the various categories of being which contribute to our environment.[37]

Cultural values[edit]

The third of the classical values – truth – is listed by Frankena alongside knowledge, understanding and wisdom.[38] Given that «truth may never be fully known» he shifted the emphasis onto knowledge, and most lists of values now tend to include knowledge rather than truth as one of the primary values. Jesse Prinz in Culture and Cognitive Science took this further discussing the relativity of the terms knowledge and truth and the role that culture has in shaping knowledge.[39] This relativity is more pronounced in a second group listed by Frankena, a group which included the values of honour, esteem and good reputation. The link between the two groups was noted by Hartmann who realised that the terms «truth» and «truthfulness» involved two different, although related, kinds of value.[40] Whilst truth is associated with the values of knowledge and understanding, truthfulness is associated with the values of honesty, uprightness and integrity.

In his article, Prinz defines culture as a complex whole which includes knowledge, belief, art, morality and custom where the value associated with these things is acquired by people as members of society. This acquisition takes place through observing role models, imitating one’s parents or learning through association with others. The telling of stories is mentioned[41] and we may think of the value of books, whether fiction or non-fiction, and the worth of films or news programmes in disseminating knowledge and furthering understanding generally. Memory too has its place,[42] and the importance of history in this respect is highlighted by Zimmerman who notes that some things may have value, not because they are beautiful or useful, but because they have meaning through either personal or cultural associations, for example a rare stamp or the pen with which Lincoln signed his letters.[43]

Knowledge of both culture and subculture is important in understanding people’s values.[44] Jacobson in an article on fitting attitudes tells us that what people find funny or shameful, honourable or dishonourable are culturally related, and he refers back to Brentano who introduced the related value of what is appropriate, suitable or fitting.[45] Such values, however, can be considered not only from the point of view of a particular culture but from «the point of view of the universe» where integrating one’s set of values with the principles of some higher truth («selective copying» is the example he gives) may result in instances of non-conformity and other kinds of differentiation within society.[46] The concept of «fittingness» introduces the value of integrity which Cox, La Caze and Levine discuss in their article Integrity [2001].[47] The concept is defined in terms of the relation between the different aspects of one’s life – aesthetic, social, intellectual etc. – and in maintaining some sort of balance between them to give a sense of unity or wholeness. Views on integrity range from the practical requirements of honesty and truthfulness on the one hand, where Aristotle could write «with a true view all the data harmonise and with a false view the facts soon clash»,[48] to more general approaches regarding meaning and identity, or «wisdom and self-knowledge».[49]

Secondary values[edit]

The end of the nineteenth and the beginning of the twentieth centuries saw an expansion in the number of values over and above the «classical» or primary values of beauty, goodness and truth. Some, like love, friendship and affection, clearly come from the Christian tradition and were discussed by philosophers like Moore and Brentano.[50] A more complex group revolving around concepts such as power, spirit and the will were introduced as values by Brentano and Hartmann and owe as much to the thoughts of Kant and Schopenhauer as they do to Christianity.[51] The emergence of a third group of values can be seen as a result of the expansion of the field away from traditional ethics, and in this group there begin to appear more material values – what Plato called the «goods of the body» – such as life, health and strength in the lists of Hartmann and Frankena.[52]

Some early attempts were made at compiling a longer set of values and three of these can be mentioned here. R.B.Perry, referred to by Frankena, and whose work The General Theory of Value [1926] was called «the magnum opus of the new approach» by the Encyclopædia Britannica, increased the total number of categories by adding to the fields of aesthetics, ethics and knowledge the three further fields of religion, economics and politics;[53] An earlier work, Lebensformen [1914], by the psychologist, Eduard Spranger, set out a similar list describing six types of personality, namely the Aesthetic, Economic, Theoretic, Religious, Social and Political;[54] and Gordon Allport, who studied under Spranger, and who was mentioned in Peterson and Seligman’s Character Strengths and Virtues [2004],[55] together with Vernon and Lindzey, set out in their Study of Values [1950] six types of personality each of which was orientated towards a different set of values:[56]

Personality

  • Aesthetic
  • Economic
  • Theoretic
  • Religious
  • Social
  • Political

Values

  • Harmony, Beauty, Artistry, Uniqueness
  • Usefulness, Resourcefulness, Practical
  • Truth, Intellectual, Cognitive
  • Faith, Unity, Holiness, Oneness
  • Love, Sympathy, Caring, Altruism
  • Power, Leadership, Influence, Competitiveness

These early links between philosophy and psychology have been discussed by C.B. Miller in his article entitled Empirical Approaches to Moral Character and this concluded with a look at the work of Peterson and Seligman.[57] Their classification of values, «Values in Action» or VIA, arose from an empirical survey of virtues taken from around the world, which led to a six-fold classification, similar to the above, and comprising: Transcendence, Temperance, Wisdom, Justice, Humanity and Courage.[58] Miller suggested, however, that no valid reason has been discovered as to why there should be six categories.

Regarding the content of these additional categories it is clear that their representative values differ according to who is compiling the list. One theory suggests that if the first three categories represent the cognitive or classical tradition, then the additional categories represent the non-cognitive – the «sentimental» or «emotivist» tradition – where neither the cognitive nor the non-cognitive necessarily takes primacy.[59] Zimmerman suggested that values taken from the latter viewpoint could be seen as just expressions of feeling or emotion about what is important.[59] A.M.Taylor in her paper, Investigation into Facts and Values [1983], suggested that there was a fundamental difference between values based on analytical understanding and values based on synthetic or «holistic» understanding.[60] The older values taken from the «aesthetic, moral and scientific spheres» were not enough and new categories would be required to include such concepts as «creativity, feeling and innovation». Jacobson also introduced a distinction between cognitive and non-cognitive values, and among the values derived from feeling or sentiment he included those of being «pride-worthy, shameful, funny and fearsome».[61] He mentioned David Hume in this respect who had used the three headings of «Pride and Humility», «Love and Hatred» and «Will and the Direct Passions» in the second volume of his Treatise of Human Nature[62] and it will be useful to look at the second group of values in this order.

Material values[edit]

Frankena’s list of values begins with a group that contains life, health and strength and in this he closely follows Hartmann.[63] «Material goods» were discussed by Hartmann in the introductory section of his book,The Realm of Ethical Values [1926] in relation to wealth and economics.[64] Frankena mentions Plato who had referred to wealth, health and strength as «goods of the body».[65] Regarding wealth, Frankena, in a discussion of «money, cars and other material possessions», suggested that its value might be either instrumental or contributory, the latter term being defined in terms of «things that are good because they contribute to a good life or are parts of it».[66] Money for a miser becomes part of his happiness, just as clothes, house or land may be a part of happiness for somebody else. Jacobson introduced the value of being «pride-worthy» and he mentioned David Hume who had noted that people take pride in, such «external advantages as … country, family, children, gardens, houses, dogs and clothes».[67] Elinor Mason mentioned the practical wisdom of Aristotle who saw wealth as a matter of prudence, and who advised people to value and «not to neglect» what belongs to them.[68]

Health on the other hand, in relation to the body and the mind, is usually thought of as an intrinsic value. Frankena, for example, wrote that we desire health «for its own sake»,[69] and Zimmerman wrote that «Being healthy is just a good way to be».[70] The value that we ascribe to life itself and the value of «just being» have been mentioned previously, but it was Hartmann who reintroduced the notion from earlier German philosophy that Being has a complementary category, namely that of Becoming.[71] Everything is subject to change over time, and without human intervention, is subject to deterioration and decay. In relation to this, Mason referred to Immanuel Kant one of whose principal values lay in duty, particularly, in this respect, duty to self, and looking after the «basic stuff» through physical exercise and maintenance.[72] Plato had also thought that the right way of living lay in «medicine, bathing and exercise»[73] but Kant added to this idea by saying that value also lay in self-improvement through the cultivation of any «natural talents and gifts of fortune» that a person might possess.[74] James Griffin in his book on Well-Being [1986] similarly introduced the value of «accomplishment» and how, in Aristotle’s terminology, we might grow and «flourish» in other ways.[75]

Communal values[edit]

To the classical triad of beauty, goodness and truth various philosophers in the twentieth century began to add values from another large family: that of, in Frankena’s words, «love, friendship, mutual affection and cooperation»;[76] G.E.Moore added «love» to the values of beauty, moral quality and knowledge;[77] and Jacobson added «friendship» to the values of beauty, pleasure and knowledge.[78] Moore, in reflecting Christianity’s emphasis on the importance of love, suggested that » … the love of love is by far the most valuable good we know … more complicated than beauty … more complicated than knowledge».[79] Both Frankena and Zimmerman mentioned Plato, who had outlined various kinds of love in the Symposium,[80] and who had described sympatheia or coaffection, as «filling men with affection … kindness … friendship … forgiveness».[81] For Plato, the soul was the seat of love and the affections, and its value lay in recognising the «community of feeling among mankind».[82] Jacobson referred to David Hume who similarly linked love with sympathy, the latter feeling arising from «the great resemblance among human creatures».[83]

On a more practical level, Bernard Gert in his work on The Definition of Morality [2002] introduced the notion of «loyalty» as a factor in establishing a sense of community among family and kinship groups.[84] Regarding wider society, Gert mentioned Kant who distinguished between the values of not harming other people on the one hand and performing positive, charitable acts on the other.[84] Zimmerman also mentioned Kant and his view that the only thing that is good without qualification is goodwill or benevolence.[85] Kant had defined friendship as «the coming together of two persons through mutual love, each particating and sharing their lives in a sympathetic manner».[86] He also introduced the concept of «respect» by which he meant keeping an appropriate distance from others within the community,[87] and he talked of community itself in terms of «being able to communicate … to perfect social intercourse … and to cultivate a disposition of… reciprocity … agreeableness … courtesy … hospitality».[88]

Communication was introduced as a separate value by Perry;[89] and Hartmann, after working through the primary values, introduced a «second group» which included not only «brotherly love» but also «social intercourse».[90] Frankena introduced Aquinas who had stressed the value of communication in human relationships saying that «there are close parallels between the communication of words and that between lover and beloved».[91] Gert too realised that there was value in «interpersonal interaction» but queried how such a value could apply in the absence of other people, for example, on a desert island.[92] Frankena answered the question by widening the scope of love to include love of, or communion with, God, animals, nature and the environment.[93]

Spiritual values[edit]

Towards the end of his list, Frankena included the values of power and achievement, freedom, adventure and novelty.[93] Regarding freedom, he introduced Schopenhauer who saw life as a continuous engagement with the realm of strife, a struggle against desire and the «primal will», where the only moments of freedom that a person may have lay in art, music and spiritual contemplation.[94] Strength and freedom of the will were values for Hartmann too,[95] and also for Kant who, as Zimmerman noted, saw such freedom lying in the absence of coercion either from external agencies of from internal «sensuous impulses».[96] These latter included emotions such as desire, fear, hope and anger, whose value, or power, lay, according to Aristotle, in moving a person either towards or away from some perceived object.[97] Griffin distinguished between desire itself and «informed desire», where the value of the latter lay in stirring the mind, not involuntarily through emotion and natural inclination, but through the voluntary power of the will.[98] Attitudes can be controlled through strength of mind, courage and self-discipline, and «corrected», according to Brentano, through an informed choice about what is right, fitting or appropriate.[99]

Frankena recorded that his list included «all the things that Hartmann mentions»,[100] but it is notable that Hartmann completed his list with what he called «spiritual goods» such as «love of the remote» and, in a Nietzschian phrase, «radiant virtue».[101] Love of the remote referred to either love of the wilderness or love of God, but Michael Stocker in Plural and Conflicting Values [1990][102] suggested that value lay more, as Plato had said, not in love but in the «contemplation» of God or of what is good: «He who proceeds aright», said Plato, «should begin in youth to visit beautiful places … to contemplate the vast sea … until on that shore he grows and waxes strong».[103] In the Jewish tradition it was not so much the sea that bestowed strength, but the hills,[104] and Griffin referred to those who value mountains for the excitement or the sublimity that they might afford.[105] Frankena referred to the values of adventure and novelty that A.N.Whitehead had introduced,[106] but it was Ralph Waldo Emerson in the previous century who had written about the inspirational value of new things and of travel, not only for the sake of art or study, but for the value of the experience itself.[107] Hartmann suggested that it might be a great work of art such as a cathedral or a piece of music that might be inspiring,[108] and he mentioned Nietzsche who wrote regarding art: «What does all art do? Does it not select? Does it not highlight? By doing these art strengthens certain values … It is the great stimulus of life».[109] Alternatively it might be humour that lifts the spirits and Jacobson discusses the value that different kinds of humour, such as being funny or being amusing might merit.[110]

Theories of value[edit]

Various theories have been put forward in the West to try and define what a value «is» – as opposed to saying what kinds of value a thing may «have».[111] There are generally held to be three kinds of theory at present that attempt to answer the question of what a value is and these have been borrowed from the field of ethics.[112] Each group of theories tends to concentrate on different aspects of the subject so that if ethics can be defined as, say, the principles governing the conduct of a person[113] then the first group of theories (ontology and deontology) looks at the principles themselves, the second group of theories (teleology and consequentialism) looks at the aims and outcomes of conduct, and the third group of theories (virtue ethics and fitting-attitude theory) looks at the concept of the person, their character and attitudes.

Ontology and deontology[edit]

Ontology (from the Greek Ontos meaning «being» or «that which is»)[114] is that branch of metaphysics which deals with being, and, particularly in relation to value theory, with the «ontological categories» or plain categories of being.[115] Zimmerman mentions G.E.Moore who pointed out that before discussing what we ought to value we should consider the possibility that anything that exists might be of value to somebody: «If we recognise that anything whatever may be good … we start with a much more open mind».[116] Zimmerman introduced the concept of «supervenience» through which it is held that any structuring of our values will reflect the structuring of the underlying categories of being themselves.[117] Kant is mentioned by Zimmerman in this respect, and also Christine Korsgaard who, drawing on Kant’s distinction between things-in-themselves and the relation between things, draws a similar distinction between intrinsic values (values in virtue of «non-relational properties») and extrinsic values (values in virtue of «relational properties»).[118] Regarding the former an impasse is reached when all that can be said of intrinsic values is, in Moore’s words, that goodness «just is», or in Zimmerman’s words that pleasure «just is».[119] This has led to some, like Monroe Beardsley, to say that only extrinsic values, in the final analysis, exist.[119] Different kinds of extrinsic value in this model derive from the different underlying categories of relation, the example given being those of beauty, utility and meaning, each of which is supervenient on one of Kant’s three categories of relation, namely disjunction, causality and inherence respectively.[120]

Deontology, on the other hand, (from the Greek Deon meaning «duty»)[121] is the branch of ethics that bases value on moral principles which in turn form a guide to knowing what «ought» to be done in various situations. The problem in philosophy of moving from an «is» to an «ought» (the «Is-ought problem») is said to have been introduced into philosophy by David Hume. Richmond Campbell, in discussing this, asks how one might move from a knowledge of what exists, i.e. from a whole range of possible values, to a knowledge of which, among these, one ought to value.[122] Given that «a small number of core moral values are espoused universally» the answer would appear to lie in giving priority to those which do not «conflict». Frankena suggested that these moral principles are derived from three main sources: the prevailing moral rules of a culture; divine revelation as found in the holy texts; and logical or metaphysical deduction.[123] Kant’s categorical imperative is given as an example of the latter, although Frankena pointed out that a distinction would need to be made between arguments of logical necessity, i.e. those which contain no contradictions, and arguments of logical sufficiency which would be needed to account for the various kinds of value, whether «aesthetic, prudential or logical».[124]

Teleology and consequentialism[edit]

Mark Schroeder in his article on Value Theory considers consequentialism to be «under the umbrella» of teleology,[125] where the latter can be defined as that branch of metaphysics which deals with the final end or purpose of things (the Greek Telos meaning «the end or purpose of an action»).[126] According to this group of theories things are instrumentally valuable which help to achieve either specific or general ends, and underlying this, Schroeder tells us, is the relation of cause and effect.[127] Frankena defined instrumental value as that which is good or useful for some purpose and he referred to Aristotle who, besides defining different kinds of cause, defined the good as «that at which all things aim».[128] If for example the aim is to live a good life those things will be good or valuable which constitute the means for achieving such an end. However, what is good for a specific person and what is good for the world as a whole are two different things and are reflected, according to Schroeder, in the ideas of egoism and consequentialism respectively.[129] Regarding the latter, Zimmerman writes that a value is good because of a perceived final end in which «all the consequences taken as a whole are good».[130]

Regarding the end at which people aim, Bentham, according to Elinor Mason, thought that the sole end was that of «pleasure», and that all other values such as beauty, friendship, knowledge etc. could be measured in accordance with the quantity of pleasure which each might afford.[131] John Stuart Mill suggested that there were lower and higher pleasures and that these were fundamentally incommensurable. He went on to question, like Plato, whether the values of pleasure or satisfaction were in fact the ends at which intelligent people should aim.[132] Mason also refers to James Griffin who was of the opinion that «well-being» was a better name for such an end, and which he saw in terms of «flourishing» or a «maximisation of life» in all its aspects.[133] A «balancing of elements» is required whereby those activities which we value for well-being, such as work, rest, love, solitude, health, accomplishment etc. should be considered «in various combinations» in order to afford a «framework» or a «plan of life» for ourselves.[134] This way of thinking was called by Elizabeth Anderson, in her article on John Dewey, «objective list theory» as opposed to theories like Bentham’s based on pleasure or those of Dewey based on «informed desire».[135] Dewey rejected the notion of a final end arguing instead that the «value of means and ends are reciprocally determined».[136] According to Zimmerman, he challenged traditional metaphysical ideas with a more «pragmatic» approach saying that only through «calm, informed reflection» on the ways in which people «interact with the environment» and deal with the ensuing consequences can value be ascertained.[137]

Virtue ethics and fitting-attitude theory[edit]

Mason in her article on Value Pluralism introduces virtue ethics as a third way of thinking about the subject of value and describes it as being based on how a person should «be» rather than what a person should «do».[138] Frankena had similarly introduced an «ethics of virtue» as a third approach (following deontology and consequentialism), suggesting that there were two kinds of things that we can value: either the things around us like knowledge or physical objects; or the things inside us like our disposition, attitudes and emotions.[139] Among the latter were the virtues and these he defined as dispositions to act in certain ways.[140] Regarding the virtues, we can either value them in their own right or we can ask whether they tell us something about the nature of value itself. Hursthouse and Pettigrew deal with the first of these options in their article on Virtue ethics, asking questions like «how many virtues are there» and «how do they relate to each other».[141] C.B.Miller, on the other hand, in his article on moral character points to recent work which suggests that the categories used to structure the virtues are the same as those that can be used to structure values. The six «core virtues» listed by Peterson and Seligman have been found to be useful, for example, in the structuring of values in their «Values in Action» or VAI.[142]

One of the similarities between virtue theory and fitting-attitude theory is that they both approach the subject of value through an emphasis on the agent.[143] They are «agent-centred» rather than «act-centred» theories, but whereas virtues are defined purely as a disposition to act, fitting-attitude theory embraces the act as well within its field of consideration. Roderick Chisholm in his book, Brentano and Intrinsic Value [1986] suggested that value lies, for example, not just in virtue but in «individuals acting virtuously» or not just in pleasure but in «individuals experiencing pleasure».[144] However, just as there is conceived to be a necessary interaction between the agent and the environment so there is, in other circumstances, a necessary engagement between the agent and an object. Jacobson in his article on Fitting-Attitude Theory suggests that there is a reciprocity between «facts about human nature» and «facts about the object»,[145] and that «to be valuable» requires either that one’s «feelings are adequate to the object», or that «the object is «fitting» in respect of some particular attitude.[145] The concept of fittingness, or what might fit together, is extended to the relation between different values and, in particular, the possible conflicts between them, the examples given being between that of humour and good taste, or between what is considered funny and what is considered fair or just. Both Mason[146] and Zimmerman[147] discuss the problem of conflicting values, as did Philippa Foot who, in the field of virtue ethics, suggested that the answer to possible conflict lay in bringing the virtues, or values, into relation with one another saying «that even such concepts as love and justice can become dangerously distorted» if not tempered with a consideration of other fundamental values.[148]

References[edit]

  1. ^ Mason E. Value Pluralism, 2006 (ed. Zalta E.N. Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, 2018); cf. Frankena Op.cit.13, pp.7ff
  2. ^ Zimmerman M.J. Intrinsic vs. Extrinsic Value, 2002 (ed. Zalta E.N. Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, 2018)
  3. ^ Ex.Brit. s.v. Axiology
  4. ^ Ibid; cf. Schroeder Op.cit.5
  5. ^ Schroeder M. Value Theory, 2008 (ed. Zalta E.N. Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, 2018)
  6. ^ Mason Op.cit.1
  7. ^ Zimmerman Op.cit.2
  8. ^ Ibid; cf. Kant.I Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals, 1785, p.12
  9. ^ Zimmerman M.J. The Nature of Intrinsic Value (Rowman and Littlefield, Lanham, 2001) p.189
  10. ^ Brentano F. The Origin of our Knowledge of Right and Wrong, 1889 (Routledge and Keegan Paul, London, 1969)
  11. ^ Moore G.E. Principia Ethica (Cambridge University Press, 1903) pp.122 & passim
  12. ^ Ross W.D. The Right and the Good (Oxford University Press, 1930)
  13. ^ Frankena W.K. Ethics, 1963 (Prentice-Hall, Eaglewood Cliffs, 1973) pp.87-88; cf. Zimmerman Op.cit.2
  14. ^ Ibid; cf. O’Hear A. Philosophy: The Good, the True and the Beautiful (Cambridge University Press, 2010) cf. Perry Op.cit.49, pp.93-97, 693
  15. ^ Frankena Op.cit.13, p.88
  16. ^ Frankena Op.cit.13, p.92; cf. Plato The Republic (ed. Ferrari G., tr. Griffith T., Cambridge University Press, 2000) pp.88-92; cf Plato Philebus 51
  17. ^ Beardsley M.C. Aesthetics from Classical Greece to the Present, 1966 (University of Alabama Press, 1975) pp.101-102 & passim
  18. ^ Shelley J. The Concept of the Aesthetic, 2009 (ed. Zalta E.N. Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, 2017)
  19. ^ Dickie G. Art and the Aesthetic: An Intuitional Analysis (Cornell University Press, 1975)
  20. ^ Zimmerman Op.cit.2; cf. MooreOp.cit.11, p.122
  21. ^ Hartmann N. Ethics: Part II, The Realm of Ethical Values or Axiology of Morals, 1926 (George Allen and Unwin, London, 1951) Chapters 11 and 12; cf. Nietzsche F. The Birth of Tragedy pp.263,290
  22. ^ Kant I. The Critique of Judgement (tr. Meredith J.C. Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1952)
  23. ^ Schopenhauer A. The World as Will and Representation (tr. Payne E. Dover Publications, New York, 1966) pp.271-272
  24. ^ Sartwell C. Beauty, 2012 (ed. Zalta E.N. Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, 2017)
  25. ^ Shelley Op.cit.18; cf. Dickie Op.cit.19
  26. ^ Moore Op.cit.11 pp.18,59,122
  27. ^ Shelley Op.cit.18
  28. ^ Frankena Op.cit.13
  29. ^ Zimmerman Op.cit.9, p.114; cf. Plato Op.cit.16, pp.37,51
  30. ^ Zimmerman Op.cit.2; cf. Aristotle Nicomachean Ethics (tr. Thomson J., Penguin, Harmondsworth, 2004)
  31. ^ Mason Op.cit.1
  32. ^ Frankena Op.cit.13, p.86; cf. Aristotle Metaphysics 982b-983a
  33. ^ Mason Op.cit.1
  34. ^ Moore Op.cit.11
  35. ^ Dewey J. Theory of Valuation, 1923, in International Encyclopaedia of Unified Sciences Vol II (University of Chicago Press, 1939) p.43; cf. Anderson Op.cit.140
  36. ^ Ibid. pp.15-18, 50
  37. ^ Ibid. p.47
  38. ^ Frankena Op.cit.13, p.88
  39. ^ Prinz J. Culture and Cognitive Science, 2011 (ed. Zalta E.N. Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, 2016)
  40. ^ Hartmann Op.cit.17, Sec.6
  41. ^ Prinz Op.cit.39
  42. ^ Ibid; cf. Ruskin J. The Seven Lamps of Architecture (George Allen, London, 1880) pp.177ff
  43. ^ Zimmerman Op.cit.2
  44. ^ Dewey Op.cit.35, pp.58-64
  45. ^ Jacobson D. Fitting Attitude Theories of Value, 2011 (ed. Zalta E.N. Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, 2011)
  46. ^ Ibid.
  47. ^ Cox D., La Caze M. & Levine M. Integrity, 2001 (ed. Zalta E.N. Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, 2017)
  48. ^ Aristotle Op.cit.30, 1098b
  49. ^ Cox, La Caze & Levine Op.cit.47
  50. ^ Frankena Op.cit. 13, pp.56-59; cf. Moore Op.cit.11 pp.131-132
  51. ^ Chisholm R. Brentano and Intrinsic Value (Cambridge University Press, 1986)
  52. ^ Hartmann Op.cit.17; cf. Plato Op.cit.16 591b; cf Plato Meno 90ff
  53. ^ Perry R.B. General Theory of Value (Harvard University Press; 1926) pp.693-694
  54. ^ Spranger E. Types of Men, 1914 (tr. Pigors P., Max Niemeyer Verlag, Halle, 1928)
  55. ^ Miller C.B. Empirical Approaches to Moral Character, 2016 (ed. Zalta E.N. Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, 2016); cf. Peterson C. & Seligman M. Character Strengths and Virtues (Oxford University Press, New York, 2004)
  56. ^ Allport G., Vernon P.E. & Lindzey G.E. Study of Values (Houghton Mifflin, Boston, 1960)
  57. ^ Miller Op.cit.55
  58. ^ Peterson and Seligman Op.cit 55
  59. ^ a b Zimmerman Op.cit. 2; Jacobson Op.cit. 45
  60. ^ Taylor A-M (née Cushan) Investigation into Facts and Values, 1983 (Ondwell Publications, Victoria, Australia, 2014) pp.9, 14-16
  61. ^ Jacobson Op.cit.45
  62. ^ Hume D. A Treatise of Human Nature (ed. Selby-Bigge L.A., Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1988)
  63. ^ Frankena Op.cit.13, p.88
  64. ^ Hartmann Op.cit.21
  65. ^ Plato Op.cit.16
  66. ^ Frankena Op.cit.13, pp.62,81
  67. ^ Hume Op.cit.63, p.545
  68. ^ Aristotle Op.cit.30, 1120b
  69. ^ Frankena Op.cit.13, pp.82,87
  70. ^ Zimmerman Op.cit.2
  71. ^ Hartmann Op.cit.21; cf. Schopenhauer Op.cit.23
  72. ^ Kant I The Metaphysics of Morals, 1797 (tr. Gregor M., Cambridge University Press, 1996)
  73. ^ Plato Op.cit.16
  74. ^ Kant Op.cit.73
  75. ^ Griffin J. Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement and Moral Importance (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1986) pp.35,57
  76. ^ Frankena Op.cit.13, pp.42,88
  77. ^ Moore Op.cit.11, pp.122-123; cf. Zimmerman Op.cit.9, p.189
  78. ^ Jacobson Op.cit.45 “Consider a plausible list of intrinsic values: pleasure, beauty, friendship, knowledge…”
  79. ^ Moore Op.cit.11, p.132
  80. ^ Plato Symposium 197
  81. ^ Plato Op.cit.16, 605d
  82. ^ Plato Timaeus 192b; Plato Gorgias 481
  83. ^ Hume Op.cit.63, p.112
  84. ^ a b Gert B. & Gert J. The Definition of Morality, 2002 (ed. Zalta E.N. Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, 2016)
  85. ^ Zimmerman Op.cit.2
  86. ^ Kant Op.cit.73, 6.450, 6.469
  87. ^ Ibid. 6.449
  88. ^ Ibid.6.473
  89. ^ Perry Op.cit.53, pp.13-14
  90. ^ Hartmann Op.cit.21
  91. ^ Gilby T. St Thomas Aquinas: Theological Texts (Oxford University Press) pp.181ff
  92. ^ Gert & Gert Op.cit.85
  93. ^ a b Frankena Op.cit.13 p.88
  94. ^ Beardsley Op.cit.17, p.459; cf. Carrit E.F. The Theory of Beauty (Methuen & Co, London, 1914) p.122
  95. ^ Hartmann Op.cit.21, Sec.3
  96. ^ Zimmerman Op.cit.2; cf.Kant I. Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals, 1785, p.12
  97. ^ Aristotle De Anima 408b; Similar feelings inform our attitudes, according to Brentano, which he termed either pro-attitudes or anti-attitudes accordingly, see Chisholm Op.cit.51, p.22
  98. ^ Griffin Op.cit.76; pp.26-27
  99. ^ Jacobson Op.cit.45
  100. ^ Frankena Op.cit.13, p.88
  101. ^ Hartmann Op.cit.21, Sec.7
  102. ^ Stocker M. Plural and Conflicting Values (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1990)
  103. ^ Plato Symposium 210
  104. ^ Psalms 121.1
  105. ^ Griffin Op.cit.76, p.27
  106. ^ Frankena Op.cit.13, p.92
  107. ^ Emerson R.W. Experience in Nature and Selected Essays (Penguin, Harmondsworth, 1982)
  108. ^ Hartmann Op.cit.21, p.57
  109. ^ Nietzsche F. Twilight of the Idols (tr. Hollingdale R., Penguin, Harmondsworth, 1968) pp.81-82
  110. ^ Jacobson Op.cit.45
  111. ^ Zimmerman Op.cit.2
  112. ^ Mason Op.cit.1; cf. Frankena Op.cit.13, pp.14,62; cf. Schroeder Op.cit.5
  113. ^ Frankena Op.cit.13, p.6; cf. Gert & Gert Op.cit.85
  114. ^ Liddell and Scott A Greek-English Lexicon, 1940, pr.p. of ennai “to be”
  115. ^ Zimmerman Op.cit.9, p.52; cf. Moore Op.cit.11, pp.77ff
  116. ^ Moore Op.cit.11, pp.13,74; cf. Perry Op.cit.53, pp.115-116
  117. ^ Zimmerman Op.cit.2; cf. Zimmerman Op.cit.9, p.115
  118. ^ Ibid; cf. Korsgaard C. Two Distinctions in Goodness (in Philosophical Review, 92, 169-95, 1983)
  119. ^ a b Zimmerman Op.cit.2; cf Moore Op.cit.11, pp.6ff
  120. ^ Ibid; cf. Kant I. Critique of Pure Reason (tr. Smith N.K. Macmillan, London, 1968) pp.107,113
  121. ^ Liddell & Scott Op.cit.118
  122. ^ Campbell R. Moral Epistemology, 2003 (ed. Zalta E.N. Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, 2015)
  123. ^ Frankena Op.cit.13, pp.12ff
  124. ^ Ibid., pp.30-33
  125. ^ Schroeder Op.cit.5
  126. ^ Liddell & Scott Op.cit.118
  127. ^ Schroeder Op.cit.5
  128. ^ Frankena Op.cit.13, p.86; cf. Aristotle Op.cit.30
  129. ^ Schroeder Op.cit.5
  130. ^ Zimmerman Op.cit.2
  131. ^ Mason Op.cit.1
  132. ^ Ibid; cf. Plato Op.cit.16, p.505b
  133. ^ Griffin Op.cit.76, pp.34,57
  134. ^ Ibid., p.58; cf. Dewey Op.cit.35, p.47 re “framework”
  135. ^ Anderson E. Dewey’s Moral Philosophy, 2005 (ed. Zalta E.N. Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, 2014)
  136. ^ Dewey Op.cit.35, pp.24,40ff
  137. ^ Zimmerman Op.cit.2; cf. Dewey Op.cit.35, p.30
  138. ^ Mason Op.cit.1
  139. ^ Frankena Op.cit.13, p.62
  140. ^ Ibid., pp.64,68
  141. ^ Hursthouse R. & Pettigrove G. Virtue Ethics, 2003 (ed. Zalta E.N. Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, 2016)
  142. ^ Miller Op.cit.55
  143. ^ Mason Op.cit.1; cf. Frankena Op.cit.13, p.64
  144. ^ Chisholm Op.cit.51, p.17
  145. ^ a b Jacobson Op.cit.45
  146. ^ Mason Op.cit.1
  147. ^ Zimmerman Op.cit. 2
  148. ^ Foot P. Virtues and Vices and Other Essays in Moral Philosophy, 1978 (Clarendon press, Oxford, 2002) locs.125,225

English[edit]

Alternative forms[edit]

  • valew (in the sense of “valour”)

Etymology[edit]

From Middle English valew, value, from Old French value, feminine past participle of valoir, from Latin valēre (be strong, be worth), from Proto-Italic *walēō, from Proto-Indo-European *h₂welh₁- (to be strong).

Pronunciation[edit]

  • enPR: văl’ū, IPA(key): /ˈvæl.juː/
  • Hyphenation: val‧ue
  • Rhymes: -æljuː

Noun[edit]

value (countable and uncountable, plural values)

  1. The quality (positive or negative) that renders something desirable or valuable.

    The Shakespearean Shylock is of dubious value in the modern world.

    Synonyms: worth; see also Thesaurus:value
    • 2012 May 13, Alistair Magowan, “Sunderland 0-1 Man Utd”, in BBC Sport:

      United were value for their win and Rooney could have had a hat-trick before half-time, with Paul Scholes also striking the post in the second half.

  2. (uncountable) The degree of importance given to something.

    The value of my children’s happiness is second only to that of my wife.

    • 2016 October 16, “Third Parties”, in Last Week Tonight with John Oliver, season 3, episode 26, HBO:

      Okay, for the record, and this is probably obvious, those three departments do actually do things of value, assuming that you find Pell grants, mortgage insurance, low-income housing programs, the National Weather Service, the Patent and Trademark Office, and the Census Bureau to be of some value. And if it comes as news to you that that’s what those departments do, well then, hi Gary, I’m excited you’re watching the show. Uh, quick piece of advice, please stop trying to fuck mountains!

  3. That which is valued or highly esteemed, such as one’s morals, morality, or belief system.
    He does not share his parents’ values.
    family values
    • 2013 June 7, Gary Younge, “Hypocrisy lies at heart of Manning prosecution”, in The Guardian Weekly, volume 188, number 26, page 18:

      WikiLeaks did not cause these uprisings but it certainly informed them. The dispatches revealed details of corruption and kleptocracy that many Tunisians suspected, […]. They also exposed the blatant discrepancy between the west’s professed values and actual foreign policies.

  4. The amount (of money or goods or services) that is considered to be a fair equivalent for something else.
    • 1825, John Ramsay McCulloch, Principles of Political Economy
      An article may be possessed of the highest degree of utility, or power to minister to our wants and enjoyments, and may be universally made use of, without possessing exchangeable value.
    • 1695, C[harles] A[lphonse] du Fresnoy, John Dryden, transl., De Arte Graphica. The Art of Painting, [], London: [] J[ohn] Heptinstall for W. Rogers, [], →OCLC:

      His design was not to pay him the value of his pictures, because they were above any price.

    • 2013 August 3, “Boundary problems”, in The Economist, volume 408, number 8847:

      Economics is a messy discipline: too fluid to be a science, too rigorous to be an art. Perhaps it is fitting that economists’ most-used metric, gross domestic product (GDP), is a tangle too. GDP measures the total value of output in an economic territory. Its apparent simplicity explains why it is scrutinised down to tenths of a percentage point every month.

  5. (music) The relative duration of a musical note.
  6. (art) The relative darkness or lightness of a color in (a specific area of) a painting etc.
    • 2006, Edith Anderson Feisner, Colour: How to Use Colour in Art and Design
      When pigments of equal value are mixed together, the resulting color will be a darker value. This is the result of subtraction.
    • 2010, Rose Edin and Dee Jepsen, Color Harmonies: Paint Watercolors Filled with Light
      Shadows and light move very quickly when you are painting on location. Use Cobalt Blue to quickly establish the painting’s values.
  7. (mathematics, physics) Any definite numerical quantity or other mathematical object, determined by being measured, computed, or otherwise defined.

    The exact value of pi cannot be represented in decimal notation.

  8. Precise meaning; import.

    the value of a word; the value of a legal instrument

    • 1784-1810, William Mitford, The History of Greece
      Yet that learned and diligent annotator has , in a following note , shown his sense of the value of a passage of Livy , marking , in a few words , most strongly the desolation of Italy under the Roman republic
  9. (in the plural) The valuable ingredients to be obtained by treating a mass or compound; specifically, the precious metals contained in rock, gravel, etc.

    The vein carries good values.

    the values on the hanging walls

  10. (obsolete) Esteem; regard.
    • 1724, [Gilbert] Burnet, [Gilbert Burnet Jr.], editor, Bishop Burnet’s History of His Own Time. [], volume (please specify |volume=I or II), London: [] Thomas Ward [], →OCLC:

      My relation to the person was so near, and my value for him so great.
  11. (obsolete) Valour; also spelled valew.
    • And him with equall valew countervayld

Synonyms[edit]

The terms below need to be checked and allocated to the definitions (senses) of the headword above. Each term should appear in the sense for which it is appropriate. For synonyms and antonyms you may use the templates {{syn|en|...}} or {{ant|en|...}}.
  • valence

Hyponyms[edit]

The terms below need to be checked and allocated to the definitions (senses) of the headword above. Each term should appear in the sense for which it is appropriate. For synonyms and antonyms you may use the templates {{syn|en|...}} or {{ant|en|...}}.
  • added value
  • economic value
  • face value
  • intrinsic value
  • lvalue
  • market value
  • note value
  • par value
  • rvalue
  • time value

Derived terms[edit]

  • key-value
  • valuable
  • valueless
  • valueness

Translations[edit]

quality (positive or negative) that renders something desirable or valuable

  • Albanian: vlerë (sq) f
  • Arabic: قِيمَة‎ f (qīma)
  • Armenian: արժեք (hy) (aržekʿ)
  • Azerbaijani: dəyər (az), qiymət (az)
  • Bashkir: ҡәҙер (qäðer), ҡиммәт (qimmät)
  • Basque: balio (eu)
  • Belarusian: кашто́ўнасць f (kaštóŭnascʹ), цэ́ннасць f (cénnascʹ), ва́ртасць (be) f (vártascʹ), кошт m (košt)
  • Bengali: মূল্য (bn) (mullo)
  • Bulgarian: це́нност (bg) f (cénnost), сто́йност (bg) f (stójnost)
  • Burmese: အဖိုး (my) (a.hpui:)
  • Catalan: valor (ca)
  • Chinese:
    Cantonese: 價值价值 (gaa3 zik6)
    Dungan: җяҗы (ži͡ažɨ)
    Mandarin: 價值价值 (zh) (jiàzhí)
  • Czech: hodnota (cs) f
  • Danish: værdi c
  • Dutch: waarde (nl) f
  • Esperanto: valoro
  • Estonian: väärtus
  • Finnish: arvo (fi)
  • French: valeur (fr) f
  • Friulian: valôr m
  • Galician: valor (gl) m
  • Georgian: ღირებულება (ɣirebuleba), ფასეულობა (paseuloba)
  • German: Wert (de) m
  • Gothic: 𐍅𐌰𐌹𐍂𐌸 n (wairþ)
  • Greek: αξία (el) f (axía)
  • Haitian Creole: valè
  • Hebrew: עֵרֶך (he) m (érekh)
  • Hindi: मूल्य (hi) m (mūlya), क़ीमत f (qīmat), क़द्र f (qadra)
  • Icelandic: gildi n, mikilvægi n, gagnsemi (is) f
  • Irish: luach m
  • Italian: valore (it) m
  • Japanese: 価値 (ja) (かち, kachi)
  • Kazakh: мән (män), құндылық (qūndylyq), бағалылық (bağalylyq)
  • Khmer: តម្លៃ (km) (tɑmlay)
  • Korean: 가치(價値) (ko) (gachi)
  • Kurdish:
    Northern Kurdish: biha (ku), nirx (ku), qîmet (ku)
  • Kyrgyz: баалуулук (ky) (baaluuluk), маани (ky) (maani)
  • Lao: ຄ່າ (lo) (khā), ຄຸນຄ່າ (khun khā)
  • Latin: pretium n, valor (la) m
  • Latvian: vērtība f
  • Lithuanian: vertė (lt) f
  • Macedonian: вредност f (vrednost)
  • Malay: nilai
  • Malayalam: മൂല്യം (ml) (mūlyaṃ)
  • Maori: uaratanga, wāriu
  • Marathi: मूल्य (mr) n (mūlya)
  • Mongolian:
    Cyrillic: өртөг (mn) (örtög)
    Mongolian: ᠥᠷᠲᠡᠭ (örteg)
  • Norman: valeu f
  • Norwegian:
    Bokmål: verd (no) n, verdi (no) m
  • Occitan: valor (oc)
  • Old English: weorþ n
  • Papiamentu: balor
  • Pashto: ارزش‎ m (arzeš), ارزښت (ps) m (arzᶕӽt), بها (ps) f (bahā), قيمت (ps) m (qimat)
  • Persian: ارزش (fa) (arzeš), بها (fa) (bahâ), اخش(axš), قیمت (fa) (qeymat)
  • Plautdietsch: Wieet m
  • Polish: wartość (pl) f
  • Portuguese: valor (pt) m, valia (pt) f
  • Quechua: chanin
  • Romanian: valoare (ro) f
  • Romansch: valur m, valour m, valeta f, valita f
  • Russian: це́нность (ru) f (cénnostʹ), сто́имость (ru) f (stóimostʹ)
  • Sardinian: balore m, valore m
  • Scottish Gaelic: fiach m, luach m
  • Serbo-Croatian:
    Cyrillic: вре́дно̄ст f, врије́дно̄ст f, вридност f (Chakavian, Ikavian)
    Roman: vrédnōst (sh) f, vrijédnōst (sh) f, vridnost f (Chakavian, Ikavian)
  • Sicilian: valuri (scn) m
  • Slovak: hodnota (sk) f
  • Slovene: vrednost (sl) f
  • Somali: qiimo
  • Spanish: valor (es) m
  • Swahili: thamani (sw)
  • Swedish: värde (sv) n
  • Tajik: арзиш (tg) (arziš), қимат (qimat), баҳо (baho)
  • Tatar: кыйммәт (qıymmät), кадер (tt) (qader)
  • Telugu: విలువ (te) (viluva)
  • Thai: ค่า (th) (kâa), คุณค่า (th) (kun-kâa)
  • Turkish: değer (tr), kıymet (tr)
  • Turkmen: baha (tk), nyrh
  • Ukrainian: ці́нність (uk) f (cínnistʹ), ва́ртість (uk) f (vártistʹ), кошт m (košt)
  • Urdu: قیمت‎ f (qīmat)
  • Uyghur: قىممەت(qimmet), باھا(baha)
  • Uzbek: qiymat (uz), baho (uz), narx (uz)
  • Vietnamese: giá trị (vi) (價值)

degree of importance given to something

  • Armenian: արժեք (hy) (aržekʿ)
  • Azerbaijani: dəyər (az)
  • Bashkir: ҡәҙер (qäðer), ҡиммәт (qimmät)
  • Bulgarian: важност (bg) f (važnost)
  • Catalan: valor (ca) m or f
  • Danish: værd n
  • Dutch: belang (nl)
  • Estonian: väärtus
  • Finnish: painoarvo (fi), arvo (fi)
  • French: valeur (fr) m
  • Georgian: ღირებულება (ɣirebuleba), მნიშვნელობა (mnišvneloba)
  • German: Wert (de) m, Wichtigkeit (de) f
  • Greek: αξία (el) f (axía)
  • Hebrew: עֵרֶך (he) m (érekh)
  • Hindi: मूल्य (hi) m (mūlya), क़द्र f (qadra)
  • Hungarian: jelentőség (hu), fontosság (hu)
  • Irish: fiúntas m
  • Macedonian: значење n (značenje), важност f (važnost)
  • Malay: nilai
  • Malayalam: വില (ml) (vila)
  • Marathi: मूल्य (mr) n (mūlya)
  • Norman: valeu f
  • Norwegian:
    Bokmål: betydning (no) c, verdi (no) m
  • Old English: weorþ n
  • Persian: ارزش (fa) (arzeš)
  • Polish: wartość (pl) f, znaczenie (pl) n
  • Portuguese: apreço (pt) m
  • Russian: значе́ние (ru) n (značénije), ва́жность (ru) f (vážnostʹ), це́нность (ru) f (cénnostʹ)
  • Scottish Gaelic: fiach m, luach m
  • Serbo-Croatian:
    Cyrillic: ва́жно̄ст f, зна̏ча̄ј m, вре́дно̄ст f, врије́дно̄ст f, вридност f (Chakavian, Ikavian)
    Roman: vážnōst (sh) f, znȁčāj (sh) m, vrédnōst (sh) f, vrijédnōst (sh) f, vridnost f (Chakavian, Ikavian)
  • Spanish: valor (es) m, importancia (es) f
  • Swahili: thamani (sw)
  • Swedish: värde (sv) n
  • Thai: คุณค่า (th) (kun-kâa)
  • Turkish: değer (tr), kıymet (tr); ehemmiyet (tr) (obsolescent), önem (tr)
  • Ukrainian: зна́чення (uk) n (znáčennja)

amount (of money, goods or services) that is considered to be a fair equivalent for something else

  • Armenian: գին (hy) (gin)
  • Azerbaijani: dəyər (az)
  • Bashkir: ҡиммәт (qimmät)
  • Belarusian: кошт m (košt)
  • Bulgarian: цена (bg) f (cena)
  • Catalan: valor (ca) m or f
  • Cherokee: ᏧᎬᏩᎶᏗ (tsugvwalodi)
  • Danish: værdi c
  • Dutch: waarde (nl)
  • Esperanto: valoro
  • Estonian: väärtus
  • Finnish: hinta-laatusuhde (fi), hinta–laatu-suhde
  • French: valeur (fr) f
  • Georgian: ფასი (pasi), ღირებულება (ɣirebuleba)
  • German: Wert (de) m
  • Greek: αξία (el) f (axía)
  • Hebrew: עֵרֶך (he) m (érekh)
  • Hindi: मूल्य (hi) m (mūlya), क़ीमत f (qīmat), कीमत (hi) f (kīmat)
  • Hungarian: érték (hu)
  • Icelandic: verðgildi n
  • Irish: luach m
  • Italian: valore (it) m
  • Kurdish:
    Central Kurdish: نرخ (ckb) (nirx)
  • Latin: pretium n
  • Latvian: vērtība f
  • Macedonian: вредност f (vrednost)
  • Malay: nilai
  • Malayalam: വില (ml) (vila), മൂല്യം (ml) (mūlyaṃ)
  • Maori: wāriu
  • Marathi: मूल्य (mr) n (mūlya), किंमत f (kimmat)
  • Norman: valeu f
  • Norwegian:
    Bokmål: pris (no) m, verdi (no) m
  • Old English: weorþ n
  • Persian: ارزش (fa) (arzeš), بها (fa) (bahâ)
  • Polish: wartość (pl) f, cena (pl) f, koszt (pl) m
  • Portuguese: valor (pt) m
  • Russian: цена́ (ru) f (cená), сто́имость (ru) f (stóimostʹ), це́нность (ru) f (cénnostʹ)
  • Scottish Gaelic: fiach m, luach m
  • Serbo-Croatian:
    Cyrillic: вредност f, вриједност f, цена f
    Roman: vrednost (sh) f, vrijednost (sh) f, cena (sh) f
  • Slovene: cena (sl) f (as in cost), vrednost (sl) f
  • Spanish: valor (es) m
  • Swahili: thamani (sw)
  • Swedish: värde (sv) n
  • Thai: มูลค่า (th) (muun-lá-kâa), ราคา (th) (raa-kaa)
  • Turkish: değer (tr), kıymet (tr)
  • Ukrainian: ціна́ (uk) f (ciná), ва́ртість (uk) f (vártistʹ), кошт m (košt)
  • West Frisian: djoerst n

relative duration of a musical note

  • Bashkir: оҙонлоҡ (oðonloq)
  • Bulgarian: продължителност (bg) f (prodǎlžitelnost)
  • Catalan: valor (ca) m or f
  • Estonian: vältus
  • Finnish: aika-arvo
  • French: valeur (fr) f
  • German: Notenwert m, Wert (de) m
  • Hungarian: érték (hu)
  • Icelandic: lengdargildi n
  • Macedonian: траење n (traenje), времетраење n (vremetraenje)
  • Malay: nilai
  • Norman: valeu f
  • Polish: wartość (pl) f
  • Portuguese: valor (pt) m
  • Russian: дли́тельность (ru) f (dlítelʹnostʹ)
  • Serbo-Croatian:
    Cyrillic: вре́дно̄ст f, врије́дно̄ст f, вридност f (Chakavian, Ikavian)
    Roman: vrédnōst (sh) f, vrijédnōst (sh) f, vridnost f (Chakavian, Ikavian)
  • Swedish: värde (sv) n, notvärde n
  • Turkish: nota değeri

numerical quantity measured or assigned or computed

  • Armenian: մեծություն (hy) (mecutʿyun)
  • Bulgarian: сто́йност (bg) f (stójnost)
  • Catalan: valor (ca) m or f
  • Chinese:
    Mandarin:  (zh) (zhí)
  • Czech: hodnota (cs) f
  • Danish: værdi c
  • Dutch: waarde (nl)
  • Esperanto: valoro
  • Estonian: väärtus
  • Finnish: arvo (fi)
  • French: valeur (fr) f
  • Georgian: მნიშვნელობა (mnišvneloba)
  • German: Wert (de) m
  • Greek: τιμή (el) f (timí)
  • Haitian Creole: valè
  • Hebrew: עֵרֶך (he) m (érekh)
  • Hindi: मिकदार (hi) m (mikdār)
  • Hungarian: érték (hu)
  • Irish: méid (ga) f
  • Italian: valore (it) m
  • Japanese:  (ja) (あたい, atai)
  • Kazakh: мән (män)
  • Latvian: vērtība f
  • Macedonian: износ f (iznos)
  • Malay: nilai
  • Norman: valeu f
  • Persian: مقدار (fa) (meqdâr)
  • Polish: wartość (pl) f
  • Portuguese: valor (pt) m
  • Romanian: valoare (ro) f
  • Russian: значе́ние (ru) n (značénije), значе́ние переме́нной n (značénije pereménnoj)
  • Serbo-Croatian:
    Cyrillic: вре́дно̄ст f, врије́дно̄ст f, вридност f (Chakavian, Ikavian)
    Roman: vrédnōst (sh) f, vrijédnōst (sh) f, vridnost f (Chakavian, Ikavian)
  • Spanish: valor (es) m
  • Swedish: värde (sv) n
  • Turkish: değer (tr)

ideal accepted by some individual or group

  • Armenian: արժեք (hy) (aržekʿ)
  • Danish: værdi c
  • Dutch: waarde (nl)
  • Estonian: väärtused pl
  • Finnish: arvo (fi)
  • French: valeur (fr) f
  • German: Werte (de) m pl
  • Greek: αξία (el) f (axía)
  • Hebrew: עֵרֶך (he) m (érekh)
  • Hungarian: értékrend (hu)
  • Icelandic: gildi n
  • Italian: valore (it) m
  • Japanese: 価値観 (ja) (かちかん, kachikan)
  • Latvian: vērtība f
  • Macedonian: вредност f (vrednost)
  • Malay: nilai
  • Malayalam: മൂല്യം (ml) (mūlyaṃ)
  • Marathi: मूल्य (mr) n (mūlya)
  • Norman: valeu f
  • Persian: ارزش (fa) (arzeš)
  • Polish: wartość (pl) f
  • Portuguese: valor (pt) m, ideal (pt) m
  • Romanian: valoare (ro) f
  • Russian: це́нность (ru) f (cénnostʹ)
  • Serbo-Croatian:
    Cyrillic: вре́дно̄ст f, врије́дно̄ст f, вридност f (Chakavian, Ikavian), вредно̀та f, вриједно̀та f
    Roman: vrédnōst (sh) f, vrijédnōst (sh) f, vridnost f (Chakavian, Ikavian), vrednòta (sh) f, vrijednòta f
  • Slovene: vrednota f
  • Spanish: valor (es) m
  • Swedish: värde (sv) n
  • Thai: ค่านิยม (th) (kâa-ní-yom)
  • Turkish: değerler (tr) pl

Translations to be checked

  • Afrikaans: (please verify) waardeer
  • Albanian: (please verify) vlerë (sq)
  • Azerbaijani: (please verify) qiymət (az)
  • Basque: (please verify) balio (eu)
  • Dutch: (please verify) waarde (nl)
  • Esperanto: (please verify) valoro
  • Georgian: (please verify) ფასი (pasi)
  • Hindi: (please verify) upayogita
  • Indonesian: (please verify) nilai (id)
  • Italian: (please verify) valore (it)
  • Latvian: (please verify) vērtība
  • Lithuanian: (please verify) vertė (lt)
  • Persian: (please verify) ارزش (fa)
  • Romanian: (please verify) valoare (ro)
  • Slovak: (please verify) cena (sk)
  • Spanish: (please verify) valor (es)
  • Sranan Tongo: (please verify) gi-grani
  • Swahili: (please verify) bao (sw)
  • Tagalog: (please verify) halaga (tl)
  • Tamil: (please verify) madippu
  • Thai: (please verify) มูลค่า (th) (moon kâa)
  • Ukrainian: (please verify) оці́нювати (ocínjuvaty)
  • Uyghur: (please verify) qimmiti
  • Welsh: (please verify) gwerth (cy)
  • Yiddish: (please verify) vert
  • Yucatec Maya: (please verify) baler

Verb[edit]

value (third-person singular simple present values, present participle valuing, simple past and past participle valued)

  1. To estimate the value of; judge the worth of something.
    • 2013 August 3, “Boundary problems”, in The Economist, volume 408, number 8847:

      Economics is a messy discipline: too fluid to be a science, too rigorous to be an art. Perhaps it is fitting that economists’ most-used metric, gross domestic product (GDP), is a tangle too. [] But as a foundation for analysis it is highly subjective: it rests on difficult decisions about what counts as a territory, what counts as output and how to value it. Indeed, economists are still tweaking it.

    I will have the family jewels valued by a professional.

  2. To fix or determine the value of; assign a value to, as of jewelry or art work.
  3. To regard highly; think much of; place importance upon.

    Gold was valued highly among the Romans.

  4. To hold dear.

    I value these old photographs.

Synonyms[edit]

The terms below need to be checked and allocated to the definitions (senses) of the headword above. Each term should appear in the sense for which it is appropriate. For synonyms and antonyms you may use the templates {{syn|en|...}} or {{ant|en|...}}.
  • appreciate
  • assess
  • esteem
  • prize
  • rate
  • respect
  • treasure
  • valuate
  • worthen

Antonyms[edit]

The terms below need to be checked and allocated to the definitions (senses) of the headword above. Each term should appear in the sense for which it is appropriate. For synonyms and antonyms you may use the templates {{syn|en|...}} or {{ant|en|...}}.
  • belittle
  • derogate
  • despise
  • disesteem
  • disrespect
  • undervalue

Translations[edit]

to estimate the value of

  • Bulgarian: оценявам (bg) (ocenjavam)
  • Czech: ocenit (cs)
  • Danish: vurdere, værdsætte
  • Finnish: arvioida (fi)
  • French: évaluer (fr)
  • Georgian: აფასებს (apasebs), შეფასება (šepaseba) (verbal noun)
  • German: schätzen (de)
  • Hebrew: העריך(he’eríkh)
  • Irish: luacháil
  • Italian: valutare (it), stimare (it)
  • Japanese: 評価する (ja) (hyōka suru)
  • Latin: aestimō (la), taxō (la)
  • Latvian: novērtēt, vērtēt
  • Malay: dinilai
  • Maori: wāriu
  • Norwegian: verdsette, taksere
  • Persian: ارزشگذاری (fa) (arzešgozâri)
  • Polish: wycenić (pl), wyceniać (pl)
  • Portuguese: valorar
  • Quechua: chaniy
  • Russian: оце́нивать (ru) impf (océnivatʹ), оцени́ть (ru) pf (ocenítʹ)
  • Serbo-Croatian: vrednovati (sh), valorizirati (sh)
  • Spanish: valorar (es), cifrar (es)
  • Swedish: värdera (sv)
  • Telugu: వెలకట్టు (velakaṭṭu)

to fix or determine the value of

  • Bulgarian: оценявам (bg) (ocenjavam)
  • Danish: vurdere
  • Finnish: arvioida (fi), määrittää arvo
  • French: valoriser (fr)
  • Georgian: აფასებს (apasebs), შეფასება (šepaseba) (verbal noun)
  • Irish: luacháil
  • Italian: computare (it)
  • Maori: wāriu, wāriu
  • Norwegian: vurdere (no), verdsette
  • Polish: wycenić (pl), wyceniać (pl)
  • Portuguese: valorar
  • Russian: оце́нивать (ru) impf (océnivatʹ), оцени́ть (ru) pf (ocenítʹ)
  • Serbo-Croatian: vrednovati (sh), valorizirati (sh)
  • Spanish: valorar (es), cifrar (es)
  • Swedish: värdera (sv)

to regard highly

  • Bulgarian: ценя (bg) (cenja)
  • Czech: považovat (cs), vážit si (cs)
  • Danish: skatte
  • Esperanto: alttaksi, valori
  • Finnish: arvostaa (fi), pitää arvossa
  • German: schätzen (de)
  • Hebrew: העריך(he’eríkh)
  • Hungarian: becsül (hu), értékel (hu)
  • Italian: apprezzare (it), tenere in gran conto
  • Japanese: 重視する (ja) (jūshi suru)
  • Latin: dīligō
  • Malay: hargai
  • Maori: matapopore, kaingākau, kaingākaunui, whakamaioha
  • Norwegian: verdsette, skatte
  • Polish: cenić (pl)
  • Portuguese: valorizar (pt)
  • Russian: цени́ть (ru) impf (cenítʹ)
  • Serbo-Croatian: vrednovati (sh), cijeniti (sh), ceniti (sh)
  • Spanish: valorar (es)
  • Swedish: värdera (sv)

to hold dear

  • Czech: cenit si
  • Danish: skatte
  • Esperanto: valori
  • Finnish: arvostaa (fi), pitää arvossa
  • Georgian: აფასებს (apasebs), დააფასებს (daapasebs), დაფასება (dapaseba) (verbal noun)
  • Italian: apprezzare (it), valorizzare (it)
  • Maori: whakamaioha
  • Norwegian: sette pris på, verdsette
  • Persian: ارج نهادن(arj nahâdan)
  • Polish: cenić (pl)
  • Portuguese: valorizar (pt), apreciar (pt)
  • Russian: цени́ть (ru) impf (cenítʹ), дорожи́ть (ru) impf (dorožítʹ)
  • Serbo-Croatian: cijeniti (sh), ceniti (sh)
  • Spanish: apreciar (es)
  • Swedish: värdera (sv)

See also[edit]

  • value system

References[edit]

  • value at OneLook Dictionary Search
  • value in Keywords for Today: A 21st Century Vocabulary, edited by The Keywords Project, Colin MacCabe, Holly Yanacek, 2018.
  • value in Webster’s Revised Unabridged Dictionary, G. & C. Merriam, 1913
  • “value”, in The Century Dictionary [], New York, N.Y.: The Century Co., 1911, →OCLC.

Anagrams[edit]

  • uveal

French[edit]

Pronunciation[edit]

Participle[edit]

value f sg

  1. feminine singular of the past participle of valoir

Middle English[edit]

Alternative forms[edit]

  • valew

Etymology[edit]

From Old French value.

Pronunciation[edit]

  • IPA(key): /ˈvaliu̯/

Noun[edit]

value (uncountable)

  1. Material or monetary worth.

Descendants[edit]

  • English: value
  • Yola: vallert

References[edit]

  • “valū(e, n.”, in MED Online, Ann Arbor, Mich.: University of Michigan, 2007.

Recent Examples on the Web



In essence, split femininity fuses a form of passive femininity that’s redolent of China’s traditional patriarchal values with the commodification of female sexuality.


Qingyue Sun, The Conversation, 10 Apr. 2023





Trump previously sat for an hourslong deposition in August, prior to James filing her lawsuit that accused Trump, his eldest children and his company of fraudulently inflating the value of the Trump real estate portfolio and his net worth.


Aaron Katersky, ABC News, 10 Apr. 2023





Shengkai kept studying even after the Cultural Revolution sent him, and other intellectuals like him, to learn the value of hard labor in rural villages.


Jeff John Roberts, Fortune Crypto, 10 Apr. 2023





The value of those LCFS credits—which represents a market price for carbon emissions—has been sliding since early 2021 and recently hovered around $70 per metric ton.


Bob Henderson, WSJ, 10 Apr. 2023





Others have called the former postal worker’s arguments at odds with the American value of freedom of religion.


Jorja Siemons, BostonGlobe.com, 10 Apr. 2023





Just as lenders to the sector grapple with turmoil triggered by rapidly rising interest rates, the value of buildings such as offices is crashing.


Julia Horowitz, CNN, 10 Apr. 2023





That might count as conventional preparation for most NBA players, but Looney came to realize the value of joga.


Ron Kroichick, San Francisco Chronicle, 9 Apr. 2023





Then over time, designers, brands, and [fashion] houses started to understand the value of putting their clothes on camera because that lasts forever.


Juliana Ukiomogbe, ELLE, 8 Apr. 2023




During the past 18 years, Thomas has reported receiving just two gifts, according to a Washington Post review of his financial disclosure forms: One was an award from his alma mater, Yale Law School, and the other a bronze bust of Frederick Douglass given to him by Crow that’s valued at $6,484.12.


Amy B Wang, Washington Post, 7 Apr. 2023





The startup, which is now valued at $25 billion, has more than 110 monthly million users.


Michelle Cheng, Quartz, 6 Apr. 2023





In 2019, as a policy advisor at the BHA, Bok led Boston’s push for a seemingly small, but tremendously influential, change in the way Section 8 housing vouchers were valued.


Emma Platoff, BostonGlobe.com, 5 Apr. 2023





The offer is roughly the same price that Industrials REIT’s assets were valued at last September.


Carol Ryan, WSJ, 3 Apr. 2023





In fact, a recent report by Statista revealed that the global laundry detergent market size in 2020 was valued at a staggering $154.6 billion!


Amber Smith, Discover Magazine, 3 Apr. 2023





Within the wellness world, which was valued at more than $4 trillion in 2020, food and beverage isn’t the only category that has people searching for shrooms.


Bryce Jones, Better Homes & Gardens, 3 Apr. 2023





Since 2017, the tower has been owned by a unit of CBRE Global Investors and is valued for property taxes at more than $115 million.


Steve Brown, Dallas News, 3 Apr. 2023





The problem for Musk is that his carmaker is valued as a growth stock thanks to its prediction that annual sales will increase to 20 million vehicles a year by 2030.


Christiaan Hetzner, Fortune, 3 Apr. 2023




Ask them to look at their daily, repetitive tasks or those that are a non-value add.


Steve Smith, Forbes, 20 Sep. 2021





Without adjustment for inflation, the 2022 total ex-value total is among the highest in Alaska history, but adjustments for inflation bring that total down to about the median for the harvests reported since 1975, the Fish and Game report said.


Yereth Rosen, Anchorage Daily News, 12 Nov. 2022





Indeed, many non-value, discretionary retailers also are expanding in 2021.


Bryan Pearson, Forbes, 7 Apr. 2021



See More

These examples are programmatically compiled from various online sources to illustrate current usage of the word ‘value.’ Any opinions expressed in the examples do not represent those of Merriam-Webster or its editors. Send us feedback about these examples.

  • Top Definitions
  • Synonyms
  • Quiz
  • Related Content
  • When To Use
  • Examples
  • British
  • Scientific
  • Idioms And Phrases

This shows grade level based on the word’s complexity.

This shows grade level based on the word’s complexity.


noun

relative worth, merit, or importance: the value of a college education; the value of a queen in chess.

monetary or material worth, as in commerce or trade: This piece of land has greatly increased in value.

the worth of something in terms of the amount of other things for which it can be exchanged or in terms of some medium of exchange.

equivalent worth or return in money, material, services, etc.: to give value for value received.

estimated or assigned worth; valuation: a painting with a current value of $500,000.

denomination, as of a monetary issue or a postage stamp.

Mathematics.

  1. magnitude; quantity; number represented by a figure, symbol, or the like: the value of an angle; the value of x; the value of a sum.
  2. a point in the range of a function; a point in the range corresponding to a given point in the domain of a function: The value of x2 at 2 is 4.

import or meaning; force; significance: the value of a word.

liking or affection; favorable regard.

values, Sociology. the ideals, customs, institutions, etc., of a society toward which the people of the group have an affective regard. These values may be positive, as cleanliness, freedom, or education, or negative, as cruelty, crime, or blasphemy.

Ethics. any object or quality desirable as a means or as an end in itself.

Fine Arts.

  1. degree of lightness or darkness in a color.
  2. the relation of light and shade in a painting, drawing, or the like.

Music. the relative length or duration of a tone signified by a note.

values, Mining. the marketable portions of an orebody.

Phonetics.

  1. quality.
  2. the phonetic equivalent of a letter, as the sound of a in hat, sang, etc.

verb (used with object), val·ued, val·u·ing.

to calculate or reckon the monetary value of; give a specified material or financial value to; assess; appraise: to value their assets.

to consider with respect to worth, excellence, usefulness, or importance.

to regard or esteem highly: He values her friendship.

QUIZ

CAN YOU ANSWER THESE COMMON GRAMMAR DEBATES?

There are grammar debates that never die; and the ones highlighted in the questions in this quiz are sure to rile everyone up once again. Do you know how to answer the questions that cause some of the greatest grammar debates?

Which sentence is correct?

Origin of value

1275–1325; Middle English <Old French, noun use of feminine past participle (cf. valuta) of valoir<Latin valēre to be worth

synonym study for value

1. Value, worth imply intrinsic excellence or desirability. Value is that quality of anything which renders it desirable or useful: the value of sunlight or good books. Worth implies especially spiritual qualities of mind and character, or moral excellence: Few knew her true worth.

OTHER WORDS FROM value

mis·val·ue, verb (used with object), mis·val·ued, mis·val·u·ing.non·val·ue, nounoutvalue, verb (used with object), out·val·ued, out·val·u·ing.pre·val·ue, noun, verb (used with object), pre·val·ued, pre·val·u·ing.

self-val·u·ing, adjectivesu·per·val·ue, noun, verb (used with object), su·per·val·ued, su·per·val·u·ing.

Words nearby value

valse, valuable, valuate, valuation, valuator, value, value-added, value-added tax, valued, value date, valued policy

Dictionary.com Unabridged
Based on the Random House Unabridged Dictionary, © Random House, Inc. 2023

WHEN TO USE

What are other ways to say value?

To value something is to consider it with respect to worth, excellence, usefulness, or importance. How is value different from esteem, appreciate, and prize? Learn more on Thesaurus.com.

Words related to value

amount, cost, expense, price, profit, rate, benefit, content, import, importance, meaning, power, purpose, quality, sense, significance, use, valuation, appreciate, cherish

How to use value in a sentence

  • The idea was to give families a bit of extra money as well as hire navigators who would help families understand the value of relocating to “high opportunity” neighborhoods, away from concentrated poverty and blight.

  • If the algorithm chose one of the original faces, the value was recorded.

  • Rather than mission statements, management directives, or corporate values printed on placards, organizational behavior is driven by peer pressure and behavioral norms that spread, like pathogens, through organizations.

  • The most reliable way to stop baselines from shifting is to encode the public’s values and aspirations into law and practice, through politics.

  • This powerful imagery surely ignites an emotional response in anyone who values life and is capable of empathy.

  • But there’s a ton of value for me in my background and my history, and losing it would be a shame.

  • There is reference after reference to the “black community,” “black worth ethic,” and adherence to the “black value system.”

  • As Randy notes, “Maybe there is a value in shining a light on this and asking the questions.”

  • Canned drinks like Mercy contain up 5,000 percent of the daily value of certain vitamins.

  • For me and some of my students, 2014 was the year of rediscovering old resources whose value is not exhausted yet.

  • Other things being equal, the volume of voice used measures the value that the mind puts upon the thought.

  • Of course the expression of this value is modified and characterized by the nature of the thing spoken of.

  • Was a pupil of Caspar Netscher of Heidelberg, whose little pictures are of fabulous value.

  • He must trust to his human merits, and not miracles, for his Sonship is of no value in this conflict.

  • The living (value £250) is in the gift of trustees, and is now held by the Rev. M. Parker, Vicar.

British Dictionary definitions for value


noun

the desirability of a thing, often in respect of some property such as usefulness or exchangeability; worth, merit, or importance

an amount, esp a material or monetary one, considered to be a fair exchange in return for a thing; assigned valuationthe value of the picture is £10 000

reasonable or equivalent return; satisfactionvalue for money

precise meaning or significance

(plural) the moral principles and beliefs or accepted standards of a person or social groupa person with old-fashioned values

maths

  1. a particular magnitude, number, or amountthe value of the variable was 7
  2. the particular quantity that is the result of applying a function or operation for some given argumentthe value of the function for x=3 was 9

(in painting, drawing, etc)

  1. a gradation of tone from light to dark or of colour luminosity
  2. the relation of one of these elements to another or to the whole picture

phonetics the quality or tone of the speech sound associated with a written character representing it`g’ has the value in English `gem’

verb -ues, -uing or -ued (tr)

to assess or estimate the worth, merit, or desirability of; appraise

to have a high regard for, esp in respect of worth, usefulness, merit, etc; esteem or prizeto value freedom

(foll by at) to fix the financial or material worth of (a unit of currency, work of art, etc)jewels valued at £40 000

Word Origin for value

C14: from Old French, from valoir, from Latin valēre to be worth, be strong

Collins English Dictionary — Complete & Unabridged 2012 Digital Edition
© William Collins Sons & Co. Ltd. 1979, 1986 © HarperCollins
Publishers 1998, 2000, 2003, 2005, 2006, 2007, 2009, 2012

Scientific definitions for value


Mathematics An assigned or calculated numerical quantity.

The relative darkness or lightness of a color. Value measures where a color falls on an achromatic scale from white to black. Compare hue saturation.

The American Heritage® Science Dictionary
Copyright © 2011. Published by Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing Company. All rights reserved.

Other Idioms and Phrases with value

The American Heritage® Idioms Dictionary
Copyright © 2002, 2001, 1995 by Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing Company. Published by Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing Company.

When we positively evaluate persons, actions, objects and situations we ascribe value to them. In most general terms, we call them good. Consequently, investigation into value closely parallels inquiry into goodness. Philosophical inquiry into value (see also axiology) is structured around three related concerns: firstly, determining what we are doing when we ascribe value to entities evaluated; secondly, saying whether value is subjective or objective; and thirdly, specifying what things (such as pleasure or equality) are valuable or good. These concerns are plainly interrelated.

Value is not equivalent to moral value. Works of art have value, but not moral value. Or again, relaxation may be good for a person, but there is nothing morally good about taking a walk. The theory of value is concerned with the nature of goodness in general, of which moral goodness is one species. Other types of value include aesthetic value, and prudential value. The theory of value is of central importance to ethics, economics, and political philosophy.

The meaning of value judgments

What are we doing when we ascribe value to some person, action, or state of affairs? For example, what are we doing when say that a person is good, or that freedom is valuable? Answering these questions involves explaining the meaning of evaluative judgments. What, for instance, does the word ‘good’ signify?

Value realists argue that evaluative statements purport to represent facts. When one ascribes value to something, one attributes to it the property of goodness. For example, when someone utters a sentence such as “Mother Teresa is good,” they are (aiming to) state a fact about the world. This statement, viz., “Mother Teresa is good” is true if and only if Mother Teresa has the property of goodness. Goodness is a property that is ascribed to an object in which case the sentence would be true just in case the object does possess the attributed property. Value realists understand attributions of goodness to a person in analogy with attributing, for example, white-ness to somebody’s hair.

Value realists have in common the assumption that attributing value to an object or person involves ascribing a property—goodness—to that person or thing. But value realists disagree about the nature of the property attributed, and on this point divide into two camps: (1) non-naturalists, and (2) naturalists.

Non-naturalism may be traced to G.E. Moore who argued that any attempt to identify ‘good’ with a natural property (such as producing pleasure, or being desired) commits a ‘naturalistic fallacy’, and that ‘goodness’ is therefore a simple ‘non-natural’ property. A non-natural property is, roughly, a property not discoverable or quantifiable by science—it cannot be detected with the senses, or measured by any scientific instrument. Non-naturalists are likely to be intuitionists in epistemology: if value-properties are not discovered by science, then they must be known by intuition of some sort.

Value naturalists agree with the non-naturalists that when we ascribe value we attribute the property of goodness. But in contrast with Moore, they hold that goodness can be identified with some natural property or properties. Naturalistic definitions of value are varied, but all share in common an attempt to identify value or goodness with properties that can be described by physical science. One rudimentary form of value naturalism (see Perry 1926) argues that an object is good if and only if a person has a positive interest in that object. This theory may very well be too generous since it implies that torture could be good if some sadist happens to desire it. A more sophisticated version of the theory identifies goodness with what would be desired by an observer in ideal conditions.

Value anti-realists disagree with realists on the question of whether ascriptions of value attribute goodness to things. Anti-realists say that sentences such as “Mother Teresa is good” are not descriptions at all and so do not attribute any property to an object. There are two main groups of anti-realists: (1) emotivists and (2) prescriptivists. Emotivists such as A.J. Ayer, and C.L. Stevenson, hold that evaluations express the speaker’s feelings and attitudes: saying that kindness is valuable is a way of expressing one’s approval of kindness. Similarly, R.M. Hare argues that evaluations are prescriptions (commands): saying that kindness is valuable is a way of telling people that they should be kind. Evaluative judgments are then understood as emotive or prescriptive, and are contrasted with descriptive judgments. Descriptive judgments are appraisable as true or false; evaluative judgments are not.

Value and the subjective-objective distinction

Theories of value are often classified in terms of the subjective-objective distinction.

Subjectivist theories of value make value dependent on the subject states of human beings and other sentient creatures. Subjectivist theories say that certain things and states are valuable insofar as they produce pleasure, are desired, or preferred. Utilitarian theories of value, such as hedonism and its descendents, desire and preference satisfaction theories, are subjectivist accounts of value.

Objectivists may characterize value in terms of the states of individual sentient creatures but deny that good depends on what is desired or valued by people. Objectivists hold that, for example, knowledge, achievement, and aesthetic appreciation are good apart from any pleasure or satisfaction they bring. Their occurrence in a life makes that life better independently of how much they are desired or enjoyed, and their absence diminishes it even if it is not a source of regret. Most generally, objectivist theories of value hold that certain things and states could be valuable independently of their impact on consciousness states.

Perfectionism is an objectivist theory of value according to which goodness depends on the actualization or perfection of human nature. According to Aristotle’s version of the theory, fulfilling the function (ergon) of a human being involves the exercise and perfection of its rational capacities. It follows that the good life for man involves the attainment of virtue or excellence (arête) in reason. In contrast, extreme objectivists characterise value entirely independently of human interests and concerns: they may hold, for instance, that the continued existence of diverse species of animals is a good in itself.

Important distinctions in the theory of value

One important distinction in value is that between things valued as means—instrumental goods—and things valued as ends, or final goods. This distinction is often called the means/ends distinction. An object, experience or state of affairs is «instrumentally» valuable if it serves as a means to ones ends. For example, working out at gym may be laborious but is a means to the end of promoting good health. Similarly, the value of making money is dependent on the value of commodities one wants to obtain. It is instrumentally valuable: valuable only because of what one obtains by means of it.

Another important distinction in value is the distinction between intrinsic and extrinsic value. In Principia Ethica (1903), G.E. Moore argued that in order to ascertain whether something is intrinsically good we should employ a test of isolation, and ask: does the object have value apart from its relations to other things? This provides a criterion of intrinsic goods: an object, or state of affairs is «intrinsically» valuable if it is good simply because of its internal nature. It does not derive its value from anything else. Correspondingly, value is extrinsic if its worth is derivative from something else.

What is the relation between the instrumental/final values and extrinsic/intrinsic values? Instrumental goods are plainly extrinsically valuable, because their goodness derives from the good things that they promote. Although most philosophers have held that ends must be intrinsically valuable, arguments have recently been presented against collapsing the two distinctions. Christine Korgaard, for example, presents an interpretation of Kant’s ethics according to which happiness is an extrinsic good that is nonetheless the final end of human action.

In his enormously influential Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant articulates another important distinction in the theory of value. Kant distinguishes between conditional values and unconditional values. A conditional value is something valuable in some circumstances whereas an unconditional value is valuable in all. According to Kant, the value of (e.g.) intelligence is conditional because we can imagine circumstances in which it would be bad for someone to possess it, such as when it would be used for evil ends. By means of this line of argument, Kant argues that the ‘good will’ is the only unconditional good—good in all circumstances. The good will is roughly a disposition to make morally commendable choices, or do the right thing.

The right and the good

The two central concepts of normative ethics are the ‘right’ and the ‘good’. The concept of the ‘right’ is the concept of duty, of actions we «ought» to perform, and which it would be wrong not to perform. What is the relationship between the theory of right action and the theory of value?

The answer depends on the ethical theory concerned. Classical utilitarianism aims to account for right action in terms of the promotion of human good. In this respect, utilitarianism requires an account of human good in order to specify just what sort of good consequences must be maximized. Classical Utilitarianism holds that morally right actions are simply those that produce the maximum balance of pleasure over pain. By contrast, deontological theories, of which Kant’s ethics is the best-known example, do not explain right action in terms of the promotion of good. Many deontologists would argue that it is wrong to kill an innocent person no matter what the value of the consequences might be. So whereas the utilitarian defines right action in terms of the promotion of goodness, the deontologist holds that (e.g.) respecting people’s rights is more important that increasing the amount of value in the world. This is sometimes expressed by saying that deontology makes the right prior to the good.

What things have value?

What things have value? If one includes both intrinsic and extrinsic goods, then plainly the list is endless. A more manageable task would be to compose a list of intrinsic goods. A plausible list of this sort would probably include the following: life, knowledge, virtue, aesthetic experience, friendship, and perhaps, a continued state of biological diversity (see environmental ethics).

Almost everyone agrees on the goodness of certain basic goods such as knowledge and friendship but ancient ethical thinkers went further. They tried to provide a systematic account of how different good things relate to one another in an optimally worthwhile life. In ancient philosophy this sort of discussion was articulated in terms of the concept of eudaimonia (or beatitude in Medieval philosophy). For example, in Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle criticizes philosophers who argue that eudaimonia is (the life of) pleasure or (the life of) honor. The view the eudaimonia consists in pleasure alone is false since it fails to include goods such as knowledge. While Aristotle does not deny that pleasure is good, and an important component in a good life, he argues that eudaimonia consists in the exercise of the virtues, which themselves instantiate all the other human goods such as pleasure and knowledge. The summum bonnum played a similar role in the writings of Cicero and the Stoics.

References

ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Anderson, E. 1993. Value in Ethics and Economics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ISBN 0674931890
  • Aristotle. 1984. «Nicomachean Ethics.» In The Complete Works of Aristotle, edited J. Barnes. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, books I 6-7, X. ISBN 0691099502
  • Aristotle. 1984. «Metaphysics.» In The Complete Works of Aristotle, edited by J. Barnes. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, books VII-X, XII. ISBN 0691099502
  • Ayer, A.J. 1952. Language, Truth, and Logic. New York, Dover Publications.
  • Griffin, J. 1986. Well-Being. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Kant, I. 1998. Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten, translated and edited by M. Gregor, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0521622352
  • Kant, I. 1978. Critik der practischen Vernunft, translated by L.W. Beck, Critique of Practical Reason. Bobbs-Merrill Co. ISBN 0672602237
  • Korsgaard, C. 1983. «Two Distinctions in Goodness.» In Philosophical Review, 92: 27-49.
  • Korsgaard, C. 1986. «Aristotle and Kant on the Source of Value,» Ethics. 96: 486-505.
  • Korsgaard, C.M. 1996. Creating the Kingdom of Ends. New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0521496446
  • Mill, J.S. 2002. Utilitarianism, ed. G. Sher. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company,chaps II, IV. ISBN 087220605X
  • Moore, G.E. 2004. Principia Ethica. Dover Publications. ISBN 0486437523
  • Moore, G.E. 1912. Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, chap. IV, VII.
  • Moore, G.E. 1922. «The Conception of Intrinsic Value.» In Philosophical Studies. London: Kegan Paul.
  • Nagel, T. 1978. The Possibility of Altruism. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0691072310
  • Perry, R.B. 1926. General Theory of Value: Its Meaning and Basic Principles Construed in Terms of Interest. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Plato. 2004. Republic, translated by G.M.A. Grube, revised by C.D.C. Reeve. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company. ISBN 0872207366
  • Stevenson, C.L. 1944. Ethics and Language. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
  • Wiggins, D. 1987. Needs, Values, Truth. New York, NY: Blackwell. ISBN 0631140441

External links

All links retrieved April 27, 2020.

  • Intrinsic vs. Extrinsic Value – Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

General Philosophy Sources

  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Paideia Project Online.
  • Project Gutenberg.

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article
in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

  • Value_theory  history

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

  • History of «Value, Philosophical theories of»

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.

Понравилась статья? Поделить с друзьями:
  • History of the word university
  • Highlight text in picture word
  • History of the word text
  • History of the word teacher
  • History of the word stress